Lecture 7. Scope and Anaphora. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 1

Similar documents
I-language Chapter 8: Anaphor Binding

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press,

! Japanese: a wh-in-situ language. ! Taroo-ga [ DP. ! Taroo-ga [ CP. ! Wh-words don t move. Islands don t matter.

Comparatives, Indices, and Scope

Meaning 1. Semantics is concerned with the literal meaning of sentences of a language.

17. Semantics in L1A

Linking semantic and pragmatic factors in the Japanese Internally Headed Relative Clause

Intro to Pragmatics (Fox/Menéndez-Benito) 10/12/06. Questions 1

CAS LX 522 Syntax I. Islands. Wh-islands. Phases. Complex Noun Phrase islands. Adjunct islands

8. Numerations The existential quantifier Exemplification Overview

Dynamic Semantics! (Part 1: Not Actually Dynamic Semantics) Brian Morris, William Rose

8. Numerations The existential quantifier Overview

February 16, 2007 Menéndez-Benito. Challenges/ Problems for Carlson 1977

An HPSG Account of Depictive Secondary Predicates and Free Adjuncts: A Problem for the Adjuncts-as-Complements Approach

Deriving the Interpretation of Rhetorical Questions

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

Review Jean Mark Gawron SDSU. March 14, Translation basics (you shouldnt get these things wrong):

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

Vagueness & Pragmatics

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Symbolization and Truth-Functional Connectives in SL

Possible Ramifications for Superiority

Answering negative questions in American Sign Language

A picture of the grammar. Sense and Reference. A picture of the grammar. A revised picture. Foundations of Semantics LING 130 James Pustejovsky

The Syntax and Semantics of Traces Danny Fox, MIT. How are traces interpreted given the copy theory of movement?

Peirce's Remarkable Rules of Inference

1 Pair-list readings and single pair readings

Plurals Jean Mark Gawron San Diego State University

COMP Intro to Logic for Computer Scientists. Lecture 2

The structure of this ppt

1 The structure of this exercise

Background to Gottlob Frege

Where are we? Lecture 37: Modelling Conversations. Gap. Conversations

VP Ellipsis. (corrected after class) Ivan A. Sag. April 23, b. Kim understands Korean and Lee should understand Korean, too.

On Meaning. language to establish several definitions. We then examine the theories of meaning

Depiction Verbs and the Definiteness Effect DRAFT 1. This paper is part of a longer project on the semantics of depiction verbs and

Semantic Research Methodology

IBPS Pronouns Notes for Bank Exam

Replies to the Critics

The structure of this ppt. Sentence types An overview Yes/no questions WH-questions

Topics in Linguistic Theory: Propositional Attitudes

Introduction to English Linguistics (I) Professor Seongha Rhee

What s New in the 17th Edition

Ling 720 Implicit Arguments, Week 11 Barbara H. Partee, Nov 25, 2009

The Grass Roots for the ACT English Exam

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Pragmatics - The Contribution of Context to Meaning

Nissim Francez: Proof-theoretic Semantics College Publications, London, 2015, xx+415 pages

The Language of First-Order Predicate Logic

Elements of Style. Anders O.F. Hendrickson

Lexical Semantics: Sense, Referent, Prototype. Sentential Semantics (phrasal, clausal meaning)

Intensional Relative Clauses and the Semantics of Variable Objects

Talk a Lot. Hotel. Multi-Purpose Text. A Cultural Visit (Original Text)

Recap: Roots, inflection, and head-movement

Exploring nominal reference in the field: Diagnostics plus results from Bulu

6.034 Notes: Section 4.1

OKLAHOMA SUBJECT AREA TESTS (OSAT )

Characterizing quotation

MONOTONE AMAZEMENT RICK NOUWEN

Sentence Processing. BCS 152 October

11. SUMMARY OF THE BASIC QUANTIFIER TRANSLATION PATTERNS SO FAR EXAMINED

CSC 373: Algorithm Design and Analysis Lecture 17

Reviewed by Max Kölbel, ICREA at Universitat de Barcelona

The Embedding Problem for Non-Cognitivism; Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism

10 Common Grammatical Errors and How to Fix Them

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

On Recanati s Mental Files

Honors 10 English Final Exam Study Guide

slowly quickly softly suddenly gradually

First Order Logic. Xiaojin Zhu Computer Sciences Department University of Wisconsin, Madison. [Based on slides from Burr Settles]

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

What are meanings? What do linguistic expressions stand for or denote?

Independent Clause. An independent clause is a group of words that has a subject and a verb that expresses a complete thought and can stand by itself.

Directions: Read the following passage then answer the questions below. The Lost Dog (740L)

Imperatives are existential modals; Deriving the must-reading as an Implicature. Despina Oikonomou (MIT)

Formalising arguments

An action word- walk, run, sit, stand

!"#$%&'()**#%*#+,*,-./#!"##)*0#1.*02#%3#3.-2'45,-2%*4%-.,*',0#/%*',*'"#

Knowledge Representation

1. Introduction. Truth is a pretense. This bald statement might inspire incredulous stares, but my aim here is to deflect

Appendix B. Elements of Style for Proofs

Singular Propositions, Abstract Constituents, and Propositional Attitudes

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Conversational Implicature: The Basics of the Gricean Theory 1

PHIL12A Section answers, 20 April 2011

LOCALITY DOMAINS IN THE SPANISH DETERMINER PHRASE

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall 2015

Two Styles of Construction Grammar Do Ditransitives

Metonymy Research in Cognitive Linguistics. LUO Rui-feng

Lesley Jeffries CRITICAL STYLISTICS: The Power of English

Dinosaurs. B. Answer the questions in Hebrew/Arabic. 1. How do scientists know that dinosaurs once lived? 2. Where does the name dinosaur come from?

Key - Worksheet 3 Linguistics Eng B

Sentence Processing III. LIGN 170, Lecture 8

Formalizing Irony with Doxastic Logic

Frege: Two Kinds of Meaning

How to write a scientific paper

CAS LX 502 Semantics. Meaning as truth conditions. Recall the trick we can do. How do we arrive at truth conditions?

1 st Final Term Revision SY Student s Name:

Speaker s Meaning, Speech Acts, Topic and Focus, Questions

Introduction p. 1 The Elements of an Argument p. 1 Deduction and Induction p. 5 Deductive Argument Forms p. 7 Truth and Validity p. 8 Soundness p.

Transcription:

Lecture 7 Scope and Anaphora October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 1

Today We will discuss ways to express scope ambiguities related to Quantifiers Negation Wh-words (questions words like who, which, what, ) October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 2

A few simple examples first to illustrate the nature of problems October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 3

Not everyone lived in castles during the Middle Ages. Many people think of the Middle Ages as a romantic time when gallant knights rescued lovely damsels in distress and everyone lived in castles. ( ) October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 4

Not everyone lived in castles during the Middle Ages. Many people think of the Middle Ages as a romantic time when gallant knights rescued lovely damsels in distress and everyone lived in castles. ( ) Now, compare this with Some people did not live in castles during the Middle Ages. Many people think of the Middle Ages as a romantic time when gallant knights rescued lovely damsels in distress and everyone lived in castles. ( ) Rhetorically speaking, the second version with the altered title is much less effective, although truth-conditionally it is equivalent to the first version with the original title. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 5

(i) Everybody needs someone to lean on. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 6

(i) (ii) Everybody needs someone to lean on. There is someone needed by everybody to lean on. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 7

(i) Everybody needs someone to lean on. (ii) There is someone needed by everybody to lean on. (iii) Someone needs everybody to lean on. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 8

(i) Everyone did not know for sure Saddam had WMD. active sentence (ii) That Saddam had WMD wasn t known by everyone. passive sentence For most native speakers of English, (i) is ambiguous and has the following two readings: (a) No one knew for sure that Saddam had WMD (b) Some people knew for sure and some people did not know for sure (ii) is taken not to be ambiguous, it can probably be only understood as having only the reading (b). October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 9

So - how do we represent such scope ambiguities? October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 10

Quantified DPs may occur in the subject and in the object position, and we may have more than one quantified NP/DP in one clause: a. No student read every book. subject b. Mary ate every apple. object October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 11

Sentences with more than one quantifier may be ambiguous: Every scientist admires a/some/one film star. (i) Åx[scientist(x) y[film star(y) admire(x,y)]] For every scientist x, for some film star y, x admires y (ii) y[film star(y) Åx[scientist(x) admire(x,y)]] For some film star y, for every scientist x, x admires y October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 12

Every scientist admires a/some/one film star. (i) Åx[scientist(x) y[film star(y) admire(x,y)]] Å > For every scientist x, for some film star y, x admires y The sentence is true if and only if every scientist admires some film star or another, with possibly a different film star admired by each different scientist. Model 1: Albert Brigitte Paul Angelina David Liz October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 13

Every scientist admires a/some/one film star. (i) Åx[scientist(x) y[film star(y) admire(x,y)]] Å > For every scientist x, for some film star y, x admires y Another model which makes the above sentence true under the interpretation of (i): Model 2: Albert Brigitte Paul Angelina David Liz October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 14

Every scientist admires a/some/one film star. (ii) y[film star(y) Åx[scientist(x) admire(x,y)]] > Å For some film star y, for every scientist x, x admires y The sentence is true if and only if there is one particular film star who is universally admired by all the different scientists. Model 1: Albert Brigitte Paul Angelina David Liz October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 15

Every scientist admires a/some/one film star. (ii) y[film star(y) Åx[scientist(x) admire(x,y)]] > Å For some film star y, for every scientist x, x admires y Another Model 2 which makes (ii) true: Albert Brigitte Paul Angelina David Liz October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 16

What we have seen so far: The order of the quantifiers in a sentence of a natural language like English does not necessarily reflect their scope with respect to each other. Such sentences exhibit scope ambiguities with respect to their quantifiers. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 17

Every scientist admires a/some/one film star. (i) (ii) Åx[scientist(x) y[film star(y) admire(x,y)]] For every scientist x, for some film star y, x admires y y[film star(y) Åx[scientist(x) admire(x,y)]] For some film star y, for every scientist x, x admires y The order of the quantifiers in a logical formula reflects their scope with respect to each other. Predicate logic formulas never display any scope ambiguities. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 18

We say that in a formula like Åx[scientist(x) y[film star(y) admire(x,y)]] For every scientist x, for some film star y, x admires y Åx (the universal quantifier) takes wide scope with respect to y (the existential quantifier). y (the existential quantifier) takes narrow scope with respect to Åx (the universal quantifier). y (the existential quantifier) is in the scope of Åx (the universal quantifier). Also abbreviated as: Å > or < Å October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 19

We find such scopal ambiguities also with respect to other operators, like negation: All that glitters isn t gold. What matters here is NOT the order of two quantifiers with respect to each other, but the order of a negation with respect to a quantifier. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 20

All that glitters isn t gold. (i) Åx[glitters(x) gold(x)] > Å It is not the case, for all x that glitters, x is gold Not everything that glitters is gold, some is and some is not. (ii) Åx[glitters(x) gold(x)] Å > For all x that glitters, it is not the case, x is gold Whatever glitters is not gold. Nothing that glitters is gold. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 21

(i) Everyone did not know for sure Saddam had WMD. active sentence For most native speakers of English, (i) is ambiguous and has the following two readings: (a) x Know(x, Saddam-has-WMD) = No one knew for sure that Saddam had WMD (b) x Know(x, Saddam-has-WMD) = Some people knew for sure and some people did not know for sure (ii) That Saddam had WMD wasn t known by everyone. passive sentence can probably be only understood as having the reading (b) above. Problem: If the passive transformation is thought of as a meaning-preserving transformation, (i) and (ii), which are related through the passive transformation, are problematic, because they don t have the same meaning (see already Chomsky 1957). October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 22

Some natural languages are like predicate logic in that the surface order of the quantifiers reflects their semantic scope. Example: Mandarin Chinese (e.g., May 1985, Aoun & Li 1993) October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 23

In languages like English, the scope of scopebearing words and phrases is less tied to the surface syntactic structure. In general, scope ambiguities arise when it is not possible to determine which quantifier has scope over another one from the surface syntax. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 24

Someone loved everybody. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 25

Someone loved everybody. (i) x y [Love(x,y)] October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 26

Someone loved everybody. (i) x y [Love(x,y)] (ii) y x [Love(x,y)] October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 27

No one has read an email I sent. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 28

No one has read an email I sent. (i) x y[email-i-send(y) Read(x,y)] It s not the case that there is at least one person who read an email I sent. No one read an email I sent. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 29

No one has read an email I sent. (i) x y[email-i-send(y) Read(x,y)] It s not the case that there is at least one person who read an email I sent. No one read an email I sent. (ii) y x[email-i-send(y) Read(x,y)] One particular email I sent was read by nobody. (But other emails I sent were read.) October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 30

John didn t find a mistake. (Karttunen 1976) (i) (ii) It is not the case that John found a mistake. x[mistake(x) Miss(John,x)] Neg > = John found no mistake at all. non-specific reading of a mistake One situation which makes this sentence true under the wide scope reading of Neg is a world in which there was no mistake, hence no mistake was found. There was a particular mistake that John didn t find. x[mistake(x) Miss(John,x)] > Neg specific reading of a mistake This interpretation allows for the possibility that John found some other mistakes. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 31

John didn t find a mistake. (Karttunen 1976) (i) x[mistake(x) Miss(John,x)] Neg > = John found no mistake at all. A continuation of with it was very easy to miss is not possible (indicated by # ) under this interpretation: I.e., John didn t find a mistake. #It was very easy to miss. (ii) There was a particular mistake that John didn t find. x[mistake(x) Miss(John,x)] > Neg A continuation of with it was very easy to miss is possible under this interpretation: I.e., John didn t find a mistake [we knew about]. It was very easy to miss. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 32

Someone loved everybody. (i) x y [Love(x,y)] (ii) y x [Love(x,y)] (i) entails (ii), because whenever there is one specific person that loves everybody, then everybody is loved by someone. BUT (ii) does not entail (i). If everybody is loved by someone, it does not need to be the SAME person that loves everybody. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 33

However, this does not mean that we cannot treat scope ambiguities in terms of entailment relations between the relevant readings October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 34

No one has read an email I sent. (i) (ii) (i) (ii) x y[email-i-send(y) Read(x,y)] It s not the case that there is at least one person who read an email I sent. Nobody read an email I sent. y x[email-i-send(y) Read(x,y)] One particular email I sent was read by nobody. (But other emails I sent were read.) does not entail (ii) does not entail (i) October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 35

Laws of quantifier (in)dependence In doubly quantified propositions, if both quantifiers are universal or both are existential, their linear order in the proposition is irrelevant x y[φ(x,y)] y x[φ(x,y)] Everybody loved everybody Everybody was loved by everybody. x y[φ(x,y)] y x[φ(x,y)] Somebody loved someone Somebody was loved by someone. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 36

Laws of quantifier (in)dependence Reversing the order of existential and universal quantifiers produces a non-equivalent statement. x y[φ(x,y)] y x[φ(x,y)] Somebody loved everybody Everybody was loved by someone. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 37

Laws of Quantifier Negation There are a number of equivalences based on the set-theoretic semantics of predicate logic. Take for instance a statement of the form x φ(x) (Example: Somebody did not pass the test.) It asserts that there is at least one individual e in the universe of discourse which makes φ(x) true. That means that e makes φ(x) false. That, in turn, means that xφ(x) is false, which means that xφ(x) is true. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 38

Laws of Quantifier Negation The same reasoning can be applied in the reverse direction: If xφ(x) (Not everyone passed the test) is true, then xφ(x) (Everyone passed the test) is false, which is when there is at least one individual e that makes φ(x) false and that makes φ(x) true. There is at least one individual e that makes φ(x) true is expressed as: x φ(x) The result of this reasoning is the first quantifier law: Law 1: xφ(x) x φ(x) Not everyone passed the test Someone did not pass the test. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 39

Laws of Quantifier Negation Because of the Law of Double Negation, i.e., φ φ, Law 1 could also be written in the following equivalent forms: Law 1 : xφ(x) x φ(x) Law 1 : x φ(x) xφ(x) Law 1 : x φ(x) x φ(x) Example for Law 1 : Everyone did not pass the test (i.e., everyone failed the test) No one passed the test. A consequence of Law 1 and the Law of Double Negation is that either quantifier could be eliminated from predicate logic in favor of the other and the result would be an equivalent system. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 40

Scope ambiguities arise with Quantifiers Negation as we have seen, and they also arise with Interrogative NPs, i.e., wh-expressions like who, which, what, where, etc. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 41

Scope in questions Which woman does every man love? Three kinds of answers (i) Brigitte an individual answer (ii) Paul loves Brigitte, Albert loves Liz, David loves Liz, Paul loves Angelina, a pair list answer (Groenendijk&Stokhof 1984) (iii) his wife a functional answer: wife(x) These three kinds of answers are related to a scope ambiguity between which woman and every man October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 42

Which woman does every man love? scope ambiguity (i) Which woman is such that every man loves her? Wh > (ii) For every man, which woman does he love? > Wh October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 43

Which woman does every man love? Take the interpretation (i): Which woman is such that every man loves her? Wh > The appropriate answer to our question under the interpretation (i) is the first type of answer, exemplified by Brigitte, supposing a situation like: Albert Brigitte Paul Angelina David Liz October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 44

Which woman does every man love? Take the interpretation (ii): For every man, which woman does he love? > Wh The appropriate answer is a list of pairs. We have: <albert, brigitte>, <paul, brigitte>, < paul, angelina>, <david, liz> Albert Brigitte Paul Angelina David Liz October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 45

Question: Which woman does every man love? Answer: His wife. e.g., <albert, elsa>, <paul, robin>, The answer is such that there is one function, wife(x), but for every man x the outcome will be a different unique woman A function attributes a unique value to the argument it is applied to. I.e., a function denotes a set of pairs relating the argument and its value. This means that the pair list answer and the functional answer are related: A list of pairs corresponds to the extension of a function, because a function is a special kind of a two-place relation. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 46

Though related, the pair list answer and the functional answer must be kept apart. Reason: Not all quantifiers allow both pair-list and functional answers. Question: Possible answers: Which woman does no man love? (i) Mother Theresa. (ii) #Albert loves Elsa, Paul loves Robin, (iii) His wife. Negative quantifiers like no man take narrow scope with respect to the whexpressions. I.e., the above question is interpreted as Which woman is such that no man loves her? Wh > no man. This triggers an individual answer like (i). Negative quantifiers like no man cannot take wide scope reading with respect to the wh-expressions. It makes no sense, semantically and pragmatically to ask: For no man x, which woman does x love? Hence, * > Wh. Consequently, the pair list answer is blocked. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 47

Co-indexing Co-referentiality Binding (Recall Lecture 2) October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 48

PRONOUNS deictic I am glad he is gone. non-deictic / anaphoric John entered the room. He took off his coat. antecedent NP anaphoric pronoun PRONOUNS have a deictic interpretation if their interpretation depends on the context of an utterance. PRONOUNS have an anaphoric interpretation if their interpretation depends on the linguistic context. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 49

I am glad the bastard is gone. I am glad Rufus is gone. definite description proper name Definite descriptions and proper names behave like deictic pronouns in so far as they may refer directly to some individual in the discourse. Definite descriptions and proper names are referential, because they pick out individuals in the domain of discourse. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 50

Generally, a given expression (e.g., pronoun) is used anaphorically when it picks up its reference from another phrase in the linguistic context (sentence context or discourse context). John entered the room. antecedent NP He took off his coat. anaphoric pronoun Anaphorically interpreted NPs (e.g., pronouns like she, her, himself, his) are said to be coreferential with or referentially dependent on their antecedent NPs. COINDEXING [John] i entered the room. [He] i took off his coat. antecedent NP anaphoric pronoun October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 51

(1) Every time I see your brother i, I feel like choking the bastard i. CO-REFERENTIALITY (2) Every time I see your brother i, I feel like choking the bastard j October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 52

Anaphorically interpreted pronouns which are dependent for their interpretation on proper names or other referential expressions are translated in terms of the same individual constant as their antecedent proper name or other referential expression: (i) Milly likes herself. Like(m, m) (ii) If Milly i likes Fred j, she i will invite him j. Like (m, f) Invite(m, f) (iii) Milly i and Fred j like each other i,j. Like(m,f) Like(f,m) This amounts to interpreting coindexing in the syntax as coreferentiality in the semantics. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 53

Question: Can all examples of anaphoric pronouns be subsumed under one characterization? Answer: No. Some pronouns do not refer to an individual at all. Background: Every dog barked. Pluto barked. Some truck were damaged. The tallest man in the world won. He sneezed. quantified NP s referential non-referential A quantified noun phrase like every dog and some truckin the above sentences cannot be represented by an individual in our domain of discourseunlike Pluto (proper name), the tallest man (definite description) or he in the above sentences. Quantified noun phrases are non-referential. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 54

Question: Can all examples of anaphoric pronouns be subsumed under one characterization? Answer: No. Some pronouns do not refer to an individual at all. Background: Every dog barked. Pluto barked. Some truck were damaged. The tallest man in the world won. He sneezed. quantified NP s referential non-referential Pluto (proper name), the tallest man (definite description) or he in the above sentences can be represented by an individual in our domain of discourse. A quantified noun phrase like every dog and some truck in the above sentences cannot be represented by an individual in our domain of discourse. Quantified noun phrases are non-referential. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 55

Bound Variable Anaphora Every man i put a screen in front of him i. binding of variables quantified NP pronoun = bound variable antecedent anaphor non-referential non-referential Since every man is non-referential, the pronoun him must be non-referential, as well, because the pronoun cannot derive its reference from its antecedent. The pronoun him here does not refer to an individual any more than its antecedent every man does. Therefore, not all anaphoric pronouns can be treated as referential. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 56

Bound Variable Anaphora Every man i put a screen in front of him i. binding of variables Since the quantified NP is non-referential, the coindexing between the pronoun and the quantificational NP cannot be interpreted in terms of coreferentiality in this case. Instead, co-indexing is interpreted as binding of variables. The interpretation/value of the pronoun him covaries with the interpretation/value of the variable introduced by the quantified subject NP every man. If your world (the universe of discourse) consists of Steven, Leopold and Rufus, then you may first pick Steven as the value for him AND for the variable introduced by the quantified subject NP and check whether Steven put a screen in front of him. Then you do the same with Leopold and Rufus. The sentence is true just in case Steven, Leopold and Rufus each put a screen in front of him. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 57

Everyone i hates himself i. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 58

Everyone i hates himself i. x Hate(x,x) October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 59

Everyone i thinks he i is brilliant. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 60

Everyone i thinks he i is brilliant. x[x thinks that x is brilliant] Verbs like think are relations between individuals and propositions Such relations cannot be represented in the first order predicate logic. For now, we simplify, and leave a part of the formula not analyzed. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 61

Everyone i likes his i mother. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 62

Everyone i likes his i mother. x y[mother-of(y,x) z(mother-of(z,x) [y=z]) Like(x,y)] Uniqueness condition: It ensures that everyone has exactly one mother October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 63

The following sentence that contains a universally quantified subject NP and the anaphoric pronoun in the subject position of the embedded clause. Every cat i was happy that she i cought a mouse. x [ [cat(x) y[mouse(y) catch(x,y)] ] happy(x)] Here too, the anaphoric pronoun is in the scope of the universal quantifier in the main clause. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 64

Prediction: Anaphoric relations between pronouns and quantificational antecedents are not licensed across the sentence boundary (indicated by # below), because the variable introduced by a pronoun will not be in the scope of the quantifier introduced by a quantificational antecedent. This prediction is borne out: Every cat i came in. #She i wanted to be fed. Åx[cat(x) come-in(x)] want-to-be-fed(x) # : adding the second sentence to the first is odd. The pronoun she i is not in the scope of the universal quantifier, it introduces an individual variable that is free. Therefore, no bound variable interpretation is available, i.e., the pronoun cannot be interpreted as introducing an individual variable that is bound by the universal quantifier, and whose value co-varies with the individual variable introduced by the quantified subject NP in the first sentence. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 65

Summary: The interpretation of anaphoric pronouns at the sentence and discourse level can be derived in a straightforward way from the semantic properties of their antecedents. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 66

SUMMARY Co-reference implies reference. Two (or more) expressions (or occurrences of an expression) co-refer iff they refer to the same individual. It follows that if two expressions co-refer, then each of them refers to something. Binding In [Every man] i put a screen in front of [him] i neither every man nor him refer to anything. This is not an instance of co-reference, but rather an instance of variable binding (in this case, bound variable anaphora). Anaphor depends for its interpretation on some other element in the same sentence or in the wider discourse. The expression the anaphor is (referentially) dependent on is called the antecedent. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 67

SUMMARY uses of pronouns non-referring referring bound-variable (a) deictic non-deictic (b) co-referring (a) Every man i put a screen in front of him i. (b) I am glad he is gone. (c) John i entered the room. He i took off his coat. (d) If she i calls, tell Joan i I ve gone to the movies. anaphoric cataphoric (c) (d) October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 68

When quantifiers are embedded in a formula, it is useful to move them up front to make it clear what their scope is. Movement of quantifiers in conditionals is restricted by the following laws: Laws of quantifier movement (φ x ϕ(x)) x (φ ϕ(x)), provided x is not free in φ (φ x ϕ(x)) x (φ ϕ(x)), provided x is not free in φ ( x φ(x) ϕ) x (φ(x) ϕ)) provided x is not free in ϕ ( x φ(x) ϕ) x (φ(x) ϕ)) provided x is not free in ϕ A universal quantifier in the antecedent of a conditional switches to an existential quantifier that takes wide scope over the conditional as a whole. An existential quantifier switches to a universal quantifier. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 69

Laws of quantifier movement If every problem set counts, Sue fails the exam. There is an object such that if it is a problem set and it counts, Sue fails the exam. ( x φ(x) ϕ) x (φ(x) ϕ)) October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 70

Laws of quantifier movement If a storm hits the coast, there is a lot of damage. For every object, it is the case that if it is a storm that hits the coast, there is a lot of damage. ( x φ(x) ϕ) x (φ(x) ϕ)) October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 71