ANCIENT PLATONIC RECEPTION

Similar documents
PLATO AND THE TRADITIONS OF ANCIENT LITERATURE

PROFESSORS: George Fredric Franko (chair, philosophy & classics), Christina Salowey

Writing an Honors Preface

Greek Intellectual History: Tradition, Challenge, and Response Spring HIST & RELS 4350

Plato's Symposium By Albert A. Anderson, Plato

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Ovid s Revisions: e Editor as Author. Francesca K. A. Martelli. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. ISBN: $95.

CTI 310 / C C 301: Introduction to Ancient Greece Unique #33755, MWF 2:00 3:00 PM Waggener Hall, Room 308

Course Syllabus. Ancient Greek Philosophy (direct to Philosophy) (toll-free; ask for the UM-Flint Philosophy Department)

General Bibliographical Resources p. 1 Research Guides p. 1 General Bibliographies p. 5 Bibliographies of Dissertations p. 12 Bibliographies of

In order to enrich our experience of great works of philosophy and literature we will include, whenever feasible, speakers, films and music.

Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates Republic Symposium Republic Phaedrus Phaedrus), Theaetetus

Care of the self: An Interview with Alexander Nehamas

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

EROS AND SOCRATIC POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

Humanities Learning Outcomes

Department of American Studies M.A. thesis requirements

Introduction and Overview

The History of Philosophy. and Course Themes

Karen Hutzel The Ohio State University, Columbus, Ohio REFERENCE BOOK REVIEW 327

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

An Outline of Aesthetics

The Oxford History Of Ancient Egypt Download Free (EPUB, PDF)

GORDON, J. (2012) PLATO S EROTIC WORLD: FROM COSMIC ORIGINS TO HUMAN DEATH. CAMBRIDGE, CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS.

Why Pleasure Gains Fifth Rank: Against the Anti-Hedonist Interpretation of the Philebus 1

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Myth and Philosophy in Plato s Phaedrus

On The Nature Of The Universe (Oxford World's Classics) PDF

Course Outline TIME AND LOCATION MWF 11:30-12:20 ML 349

Ralph K. Hawkins Bethel College Mishawaka, Indiana

Classics. Affiliated Faculty: Sarah H. Davies, History (on Sabbatical, Fall 2017) Michelle Jenkins, Philosophy Matthew Bost, Rhetoric Studies

Literature: An Introduction to Reading and Writing

Department of American Studies B.A. thesis requirements

SOCRATES AND ARISTOPHANES BY LEO STRAUSS

1. Physically, because they are all dressed up to look their best, as beautiful as they can.

PHILOSOPHY PLATO ( BC) VVR CHAPTER: 1 PLATO ( BC) PHILOSOPHY by Dr. Ambuj Srivastava / (1)

Stenberg, Shari J. Composition Studies Through a Feminist Lens. Anderson: Parlor Press, Print. 120 pages.

Plato and Aristotle: Mimesis, Catharsis, and the Functions of Art

William Shakespeare. Coriolanus, The Arden Shakespeare, Third. Series. Ed. Peter Holland. London: Bloomsbury Publishing, Christian Griffiths

Paul Allen Miller, Postmodern Spiritual Practices: The Construction of the Subject and the Reception of Plato in Lacan, Derrida, and Foucault

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

INTRODUCTION TO CLASSICAL CIVILIZATION: GREECE

21H.301 The Ancient World: Greece Fall 2004

Vol 4, No 1 (2015) ISSN (online) DOI /contemp

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

Song of War: Readings from Vergil's Aeneid 2004

Classics and Philosophy

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

Critical Analytical Response to Literature: Paragraph Writing Structure

Modernism And Homer: The Odysseys Of H.D., James Joyce, Osip Mandelstam, And Ezra Pound (Classics After Antiquity) By Leah Culligan Flack

Georg Simmel's Sociology of Individuality

From Pre-Socratics through Postmodernism, Western Tradition Dialectical at Its Core

Download History And Historians (7th Edition) Books

Aristotle's theory of price formation and views on chrematistics. Failing to confirm the law of demand and supply

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Book Reviews Department of Philosophy and Religion Appalachian State University 401 Academy Street Boone, NC USA

Rachel G.K. Singpurwalla

CLSX 148, Spring 15 Research worksheet #2 (100 points) DUE: Monday 10/19 by midnight online

Ionuţ BÂRLIBA University of Konstanz & Al.I. Cuza University of Iasi ART AND RHAPSODY IN PLATO S ION

The Theory and Practice of Virtue Education Edited by Tom Harrison and David I. Walker *

Integration, Ambivalence, and Mental Conflict

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

Cambridge Pre-U 9787 Classical Greek June 2010 Principal Examiner Report for Teachers

African Fractals Ron Eglash

Julie K. Ward. Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) Mathesis Publications

Source: Anna Pavlova by Valerian Svetloff (1931) Body and Archetype: A few thoughts on Dance Historiography

Reading Greek. The Teachers Notes to

Emerging Questions: Fernando F. Segovia and the Challenges of Cultural Interpretation

Colloque Écritures: sur les traces de Jack Goody - Lyon, January 2008

Canterbury Christ Church University s repository of research outputs.

COMPUTER ENGINEERING SERIES

Martin, Gottfried: Plato s doctrine of ideas [Platons Ideenlehre]. Berlin: Verlag Walter de Gruyter, 1973

Hebrew Bible Monographs 18. Colin Toffelmire McMaster Divinity College Hamilton, Ontario, Canada

WRITING A BACHELOR THESIS (B.SC.) AT THE ENDOWED CHAIR OF PROCUREMENT

Book Review: Treatise of International Criminal Law, Vol. i: Foundations and General Part, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2013, written by Kai Ambos

DEPARTMENT OF ANCIENT MEDITERRANEAN STUDIES. I. ARCHAEOLOGY: AR_H_A COURSES CHANGE TO AMS (pp. 1 4)

Policy Statement on Academic Integrity and Plagiarism

Brill Companions to Classical Reception Series

Dynamics in Document Design: Creating Text for Readers

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

from On the Sublime by Longinus Definition, Language, Rhetoric, Sublime

Eng 104: Introduction to Literature Fiction

UvA-DARE (Digital Academic Repository) Film sound in preservation and presentation Campanini, S. Link to publication

COMPREHENSIVE EXAMINATION SAMPLE QUESTIONS

George Levine, Darwin the Writer, Oxford University Press, Oxford 2011, 272 pp.

ANCIENT ROME: A MILITARY AND POLITICAL HISTORY BY CHRISTOPHER S. MACKAY

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

FIFTY KEY CONTEMPORARY THINKERS

Media Literacy and Semiotics

Comparative Literature: Theory, Method, Application Steven Totosy de Zepetnek (Rodopi:

Logic and argumentation techniques. Dialogue types, rules

Introduction to Drama

Edward Clarke. The Later Affluence of W.B. Yeats and Wallace Stevens.

City, University of London Institutional Repository. This version of the publication may differ from the final published version.

THE GOLDEN AGE POETRY

Othello (Arden Shakespeare: Third Series) PDF

Nickelodeon City: Pittsburgh at the Movies, (review)

POLI 300A: Ancient and Medieval Political Thought Fall 2018 Tuesday, Wednesday, Friday 9:30AM 10:20AM COR A229 Course Description Course Texts:

Rhetorical Review 7:2 (June 2009) 14

Transcription:

CJ-Online, 2013.05.01 ANCIENT PLATONIC RECEPTION Platonic Drama and its Ancient Reception. By NIKOS G. CHARALABOPOULOS. Cambridge Classical Studies. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 2012. Pp. xxi + 331. Hardcover, 60.00/$99.00. ISBN 978-0-521-87174-7. Plato and the Traditions of Ancient Literature: The Silent Stream. By RICHARD HUNTER. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 2012. Pp. vii + 279. Hardcover, 60.00/$99.00. ISBN 978-1-107-01292-9. Two books of similar length, by two scholars with close ties to Cambridge, published by the same press, in the same year, and treating related topics from a similar methodological perspective. Both are deeply learned (though Hunter s 16-page bibliography is dwarfed by Charalabopoulos, which weighs in at 48). Both, too, are Janus-faced, looking back at Plato s engagement with the cultural traditions that formed him as well as on to later writers who engaged with him in turn. One of our authors is, however, a seasoned scholar, the other a neophyte. Charalabopoulos book still bears for better or worse the imprint of its origins in a Cambridge PhD dissertation, while Hunter s joins the distinguished bibliography of that university s Regius Professor of Greek. Platonic Drama and its Ancient Reception is intended to show that there was throughout antiquity a tradition of interpreting the Platonic dialogue as a piece of dramatic performance literature (256). The key phrase here is throughout antiquity. Charalabopoulos does, as we would expect, discuss the evidence from the Roman period for the dialogues as sympotic entertainment; but he argues that such performance was not an imperial invention but a practice instituted by Plato himself. When he claims that Plato s authorial identity was that of an alternative dramatist (104), Charalabopoulos means not only that the dialogues are in their essence dramatic (in some sense), but also that they were composed for performance by multiple speakers in theatrical style or even a full production in the manner of plays (20). These two points are logically distinct (though Charalabopoulos does not always separate them). But he believes that the latter, no less than the former, was intrinsic to the philosopher s purpose in creating the dialogues to challenge and supplant the cultural authority of theater.

2 RUBY BLONDELL The book commences with a thorough and well documented survey of current work in literary Plato studies, especially the now substantial bibliography on Plato s relationship to drama. Chapter 2 treats the dramatic nature of Plato s dialogues in general terms, ending with more detailed discussions of the Republic and Laws. Chapter 3 examines the evidence such as it is for the performance of the dialogues in Plato s own time. Finally, the very long Chapter 4 analyses several intriguing pieces of post-classical evidence linking Plato s dialogues with dramatic performance. The most substantive of these are the remarks about Plato as dinner theater in Plutarch and Athenaeus, together with a mosaic from Herculaneum juxtaposing scenes from Menander with a panel of Platonic characters (handsomely reproduced on the jacket). One can learn about many things from this extraordinarily learned book from dinner parties at Plato s house (224) to the intricacies of Byzantine musical notation (226-38). Not all of what one learns is, however, strictly pertinent to the author s thesis. Chapter 4, for example, includes a great deal of technical detail regarding various statues of Socrates, whose relevance is tenuous at best. The detailed summary of the evidence on such points, fully documented in lengthy footnotes, will be valuable for scholars, especially those new to the field; but it is unclear what some of these surveys contribute to the book s central argument. That argument itself suffers from a certain imprecision regarding the dramatic or performative nature of Plato s dialogues, by which Charalabopoulos sets such store. It is clear enough that Plato engages with drama at every turn, both discursively and through his choice of form. It is likely, too, that he intended at least some of the dialogues for performance (though not all necessarily in the same way or for the same kind of audience). As Charalabopoulos is well aware, however, virtually all classical texts were originally performed in some sense. He therefore needs to clarify what, in his view, makes these specific texts performative in a way that distinguishes them from (say) the performances of a Homeric rhapsode, or even of Thucydides or Herodotus (whose speeches likewise involve the role-playing that Charalabopoulos treats as a touchstone of theater). He needs to say more, in particular, about the distinction between theatrical performance by multiple actors and histrionic recitation by a single narrator (which seems appropriate, for obvious reasons, to the narrated dialogues). Charalabopoulos seems to have left no stone unturned in his quest for traces of the ancient fascination with dramatic aspects of Plato s dialogues. Chapter 4, in particular, is a mine of obscure information from the byways of Platonic reception. Yet despite this assiduous collection and analysis of the evidence, at the end

ANCIENT PLATONIC RECEPTION 3 of the day what he does prove is not new (no doubt at least some of the dialogues were recited or otherwise performed upon occasion) and what he wants to prove is not convincing ( a full production in the manner of plays ). That said, Chapter 3 ends with an appealing suggestion. Here Charalabopoulos relates the performance of the dialogues to the founding of the Academy, which as a community of like-minded individuals offered an alternative to civic institutions (141). As such, he suggests, the Academy provided for the performance of Platonic dialogues, displacing the traditional institutional framework of theatrical festivals. This attractive idea remains, however, little more than speculation. When Charalabopoulos describes Thrasyllus procedure as wishful guesswork (184), the phrase, alas, applies all too accurately to his own. Since Charalabopoulos work is marked by scrupulous intellectual honesty, this results in a palpable tension. His most characteristic rhetorical maneuver is a kind of intellectual seesaw, where he acknowledges that the evidence he has just outlined does not prove his point, but goes on to insist that, since it doesn t disprove it either, his desired conclusion could be true (e.g. pp. 194-6, 222, 228, 230, 248-9). He has done himself a disservice, however, by binding his evidence to the Procrustean bed of his overarching thesis, instead of seeing where it may lead in its own terms. As he himself remarks (256), his work has interesting potential for the history of Platonic reception. There is much to be said about the perception of Plato s works as dramatic, and about the history of Platonic performance (which is by no means dead), without resorting to dubious claims about Plato s own time. The book is, then, rather less than the sum of its parts. Yet many of those parts remain intriguing. Richard Hunter s new book, Plato and the Traditions of Ancient Literature: The Silent Stream, begins, appropriately, with Lucian s rewriting of one of the most famous literary beginnings of all time: the opening of Plato s Phaedrus, which, as Hunter argues, became a marker of Hellenic cultural identity in the Roman period. As this opening signals, the traditions referred to in Hunter s title are primarily those of the Second Sophistic. His enigmatic subtitle alludes to Longinus characterization of Plato s style as a noiseless flow (7 n. 28). For the most part, however, the book focuses on texts where the flow is quite noisy not to say a deafening roar that is, where there can be no mistake about these writers conscious engagement with Plato s texts. Hunter guides us expertly on a series of more or less interrelated journeys along that abundant river.

4 RUBY BLONDELL Plato stands at the heart of the Second Sophistic s intense preoccupation with classical literature, not only for reasons of style and theme but also, as Hunter shows, because of his concern with textuality, voice and narrative. But the overwhelming cultural prestige assigned to the philosopher by authors of this period also obliged them to come to terms with such awkward matters as his rejection of Homer and elevation of pederasty not to mention his embarrassing departures from the very pure, lucid style for which he was admired. Hunter is concerned with the complex negotiations that this entailed, and the resulting role played by Plato s texts in the formation of the distinctive literary culture of the 2nd century CE. Yet he also casts an eye back towards Plato s own use of tradition, arguing that for the ancient critics, the philosopher s attention to earlier literature means that engagement with Plato always entailed also Plato s own relationship with other texts (9). After a far-ranging introductory chapter Hunter turns, in his lengthy Chapter 2, to Plato s problematic relationship with poetry, and above all Homer. He is most interested in the way that relationship was construed by later authors, especially their need to defang the philosopher s critique of the divine Homer (for example through allegory). Yet there are also perceptive comments about Plato in his own right, especially in the discussion of certain Platonic images. He situates the Republic s Ship of State, for example, in the context of Theognis, Aristophanes, and Thucydides, showing how deeply veined it is with the heritage of classical literature (79). The four remaining chapters each maintain a tighter focus. Chapter 3 begins with Plato s Apology, then traces that dialogue s reception from Isocrates to Apuleius. Chapters 4, 5, and 6 reverse this critical perspective, to study the multifarious use of Plato by specific authors of the Roman period. Chapter 4 is devoted to Dionysius of Halicarnassus engagement with Phaedrus and the challenges that dialogue posed to orators. In Chapter 5 Hunter elucidates the bountiful Platonic menu from which Plutarch drew in his Amatorius. Finally, Chapter 6 parses ways in which the novelists specifically Apuleius and Petronius reacted to Plato s erotic dialogues from the perspective of narrative. There the book ends, rather abruptly. A broad spectrum of Second Sophistic genres and authors thus fall within Hunter s purview. Where Plato himself is concerned, the Symposium and Phaedrus naturally play a starring role, thanks to the abiding significance of eros for both philosophers and novelists. Phaedrus is important for additional reasons (including its iconic opening). As for the Symposium the subject of a short in-

ANCIENT PLATONIC RECEPTION 5 troductory book by Hunter published in 2004 a highlight among its several appearances here is the discussion of Petronius vulgar riff on Alcibiades notorious failure to seduce Socrates (246-55). An impressive number of other dialogues are also grist to Hunter s mill. His treatment of the Apology is particularly valuable. Chapter 3 shows deftly how this work was simultaneously genredefining and genre-defying (118), an observation that comes sharply into focus when the speech is viewed through its multiple receptions. The early history of literary criticism was not only driven by the need to respond to Plato s critique of Homer but foreshadowed in Plato s own writings. In Chapter 1 Hunter argues that Plato s Ion launched the literary scholarship of Homer, including certain modern concerns such as authorial intention (89-108). Subsequent chapters show repeatedly how later authors used Plato as a chief witness against Plato (183) a tactic also employed, for example, by Nietzsche, who turns a specifically Platonic dagger against Plato himself when he characterizes the dialogues as a mixture of all available styles and forms (224-5). In short, Plato himself invented the tools that were later used to attack/defend/interpret him tools of which we are in many cases the heirs. For as Hunter makes clear, we are still swimming in the stream of his title. He rightly warns against easy dismissal of early interpretive practices, which bear close relationship to some of our own (51), and urges a generous spirit in approaching our ancient forebears (67). As scholars, we live in glass houses from which we cannot afford to cast stones at the seeming naiveté of our predecessors. By way of preface to his project, Hunter worries that Plato is too often left to the philosophers, fearing that our distinction between literature and philosophy is at risk of becoming sclerotic (10). This seems at first blush rather odd, given the current state of Plato scholarship. Literary Plato is thriving (not least at Cambridge University Press). Countless scholars, including many of the philosophers, have grasped the importance of approaching Plato as a writer one with a complex and fraught relationship to literature for understanding him as a thinker (a trend well documented by Charalabopoulos). But this is not, in fact, what Hunter has in mind. He wants, rather, to reclaim Plato for the kind of unabashedly literary study that does not aspire to elucidate Plato s thought as such. There is plenty of room for such scholarship, considering the multiple strands or streams of Platonic influence that have wound through every aspect of European intellectual traditions. As Hunter freely acknowledges, there are many Platos (10). Yet the slightly defensive presentation of his case buys

6 RUBY BLONDELL into and reinforces the problematic dichotomy of which he complains just at a time when the sclerosis in question seems to be softening. In contrast with Charalabopoulos book, where I noticed a handful of typographical errors, along with some linguistic oddities and solecisms, Hunter s is impeccably written, produced, and edited. I caught only one small error (Fernández-Galiano, cited in n. 209 on p. 106, is missing a date and absent from the bibliography). His lucid scholarly style is smoother than Charalabopoulos rather awkward prose, but equally old-fashioned (both use AD instead of CE, and men for human beings ), and a magisterial of course is sprinkled rather too freely through the text. Hunter s book also differs from Charalabopoulos in its lack of a strong unifying thesis (the absence of a concluding chapter seems symptomatic). As a whole, it offers less a cohesive, focused argument than a series of explorations, dipping into a stream that Hunter would be the first to admit is inexhaustible. There is more than enough here, however, to demonstrate the towering importance of Plato s oeuvre, which stands as a massive rock or island in the gathering flow of early literary criticism, one that diverted and transformed its course forever. University of Washington, blondell@uw.edu RUBY BLONDELL