Embodied Experience and the Semiosis of Abductive Reasoning. Donna E. West State University of New York at Cortland

Similar documents
Cognitive and linguistic underpinnings of deixis am phantasma: Bühler s and Peirce s semiotic

Figurative Deictic Use: A Semiotic Analysis. Dr. Donna E. West. State University of New York at Cortland

Cognitive and linguistic underpinnings of deixis am phantasma: Bühler s and Peirce s semiotic

Keywords: Peirce, index, degenerate, genuine, development

How Semantics is Embodied through Visual Representation: Image Schemas in the Art of Chinese Calligraphy *

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Re-appraising the role of alternations in construction grammar: the case of the conative construction

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Keywords: semiotic; pragmatism; space; embodiment; habit, social practice.

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

THE PROBLEM OF NOVELTY IN C.S. PEIRCE'S AND A.N. WHITEHEAD'S THOUGHT

MISSING FUNDAMENTAL STRATUM OF THE CURRENT FORMS OF THE REPRESENTATION OF CONCEPTS IN CONSTRUCTION

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

GLOSSARY for National Core Arts: Visual Arts STANDARDS

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

44 Iconicity in Peircean situated cognitive Semiotics

1/10. The A-Deduction

Phenomenology Glossary

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Theories and Activities of Conceptual Artists: An Aesthetic Inquiry

observation and conceptual interpretation

Intersemiotic translation: The Peircean basis

THE SENSUAL AND THE CONCEPTUAL: ARTEFACT-MEDIATED KINESTHETIC ACTIONS AND SEMIOTIC ACTIVITY

4 Embodied Phenomenology and Narratives

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination and Reason by Mark Johnson, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

Metaphors we live by. Structural metaphors. Orientational metaphors. A personal summary

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Architecture is epistemologically

Semiotics of culture. Some general considerations

Sidestepping the holes of holism

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

Object Oriented Learning in Art Museums Patterson Williams Roundtable Reports, Vol. 7, No. 2 (1982),

CONCEPT-FORMATION ACCORDING TO RAND A PERSONAL ADAPTATION (AND TWO EXTRA PHASES)

Immanuel Kant, the author of the Copernican revolution in philosophy,

Image and Imagination

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

The Cognitive Nature of Metonymy and Its Implications for English Vocabulary Teaching

Second Grade: National Visual Arts Core Standards

Semiotic modelling of biological processes: semiotic systems João Queiroz a,b,c & Charbel El-Hani a,b

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Kant IV The Analogies The Schematism updated: 2/2/12. Reading: 78-88, In General

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Haecceities: Essentialism, Identity, and Abstraction

Inter-subjective Judgment

Affect, perceptual experience, and disclosure

Cognitive poetics as a literary theory for analyzing Khayyam's poetry

Understanding the Cognitive Mechanisms Responsible for Interpretation of Idioms in Hindi-Urdu

On Recanati s Mental Files

Types of perceptual content

Analysis of local and global timing and pitch change in ordinary

Thomas Szanto: Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes

Pragmatism, Semiotic mind and Cognitivism

CONRAD AND IMPRESSIONISM JOHN G. PETERS

The Interconnectedness Principle and the Semiotic Analysis of Discourse. Marcel Danesi University of Toronto

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995.

Is composition a mode of performing? Questioning musical meaning

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

Theatre Standards Grades P-12

A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique of Pure Reason for Describing Epistemological Trends in IS

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

The Doctrine of the Mean

SYNTAX AND MEANING Luis Radford Université Laurentienne, Ontario, Canada

Gestalt, Perception and Literature

Social Semiotic Techniques of Sense Making using Activity Theory

Abstract Several accounts of the nature of fiction have been proposed that draw on speech act

1/9. The B-Deduction

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

Architecture as the Psyche of a Culture

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

DAT335 Music Perception and Cognition Cogswell Polytechnical College Spring Week 6 Class Notes

Categories and Schemata

Objects and Things: Notes on Meta- pseudo- code (Lecture at SMU, Dec, 2012)

Georg Simmel's Sociology of Individuality

Aesthetics and meaning

Pure and Applied Geometry in Kant

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

Why Pleasure Gains Fifth Rank: Against the Anti-Hedonist Interpretation of the Philebus 1

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Lecture (0) Introduction

Metaphors: Concept-Family in Context

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

Valuable Particulars

Broadcasting Order CRTC

The Observer Story: Heinz von Foerster s Heritage. Siegfried J. Schmidt 1. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2011

Five Theses on De Re States and Attitudes* Tyler Burge

THE TIME OF OUR LIVES: ARISTOTLE ON TIME, TEMPORAL PERCEPTION, RECOLLECTION, AND HABITUATION. MICHAEL BRUDER, B.A., M.A. A Thesis

Introduction SABINE FLACH, DANIEL MARGULIES, AND JAN SÖFFNER

Aristotle s Metaphysics

AJIS Vol.11 No. 1 September 2003 THE MANAGEMENT OF INTUITION ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

Transcription:

Embodied Experience and the Semiosis of Abductive Reasoning Donna E. West State University of New York at Cortland Abstract A case will be made for the indispensability of embodied experience as a foundation for Peirce s pragmatic semiotic, especially given the place of semiosis in signification. Lakoff and Johnson s model of space and time, from dependence on physical, embodied experience, to more analogous based concepts in the mental world, is employed as a framework for a discussion of the primacy of Secondness in Peirce s model of reasoning. Peirce s later writings reveal that abductive reasoning entails recommending a course of action, demonstrating the pivotal place of Secondness in abductive thinking. Nonetheless, recommending a course of action does not stop at experience it likewise relies on spontaneous insights to trigger a synthesized and acceptable explanatory prediction of a state of affairs. The prediction/hypothesis emanates not from previous direct experience, but from its culminating effects. This retroduction ensures the preeminence of self controlled logic (Thirdness impinging on Secondness) over capricious affect in Firstness. Keywords: Abduction, Peirce, Lakoff and Johnson, Lived experience, Secondness Introduction In elucidating Peirce s model of travel toward abductive reasoning, the emphasis is placed on participatory involvement in experiences, or as Lakoff and Johnson (1980, 1999) term it, lived experience. We have no more fundamental way of comprehending the world than through our embodied, basic-level concepts and the basic-level experiences that they generalize over. Such basic concepts are fundamental not only to our literal conception of the world but to our metaphorical conceptualization as well (Lakoff and Johnson, 1999: 231). The tenets of Lakoff and Johnson s model bear resemblance to Peirce s model of the development of abductive reasoning, in that both squarely rest their assumptions on the Piagetian claim that foundational to higher level reasoning are primary experiences. Piaget Embodied Experience and the Semiosis of Abductive Reasoning by Donna E. West 53

(1937/1954: 403) expressly asserts that sensorimotor interactions are the building blocks for mature logic: Thus, starting with the use of reflexes and the first acquired association, the child succeeds within a few months in constructing a system of schemata capable of unlimited combinations which presages that of logical concepts and relations. Lakoff and Johnson likewise follow this rationale in constructing their model of spatial relations. Although Peirce s claims are in line with those of Lakoff and Johnson (and implicitly of Piaget, as well), they are not explicitly developmental in nature. Nonetheless, the three models are in accord that lived experience is primary in developing higher level logic. They further agree that spatial concepts/modes of representation are primary skills for developing more advanced reasoning competencies. Lakoff and Johnson s Contemporary Model of Lived Experience Lakoff and Johnson (1999: 30-35) posit that three reasoning approaches govern children s involvement in experience: container schema, source-path-goal schema, and bodily projection schema. These lines of reasoning regarding spatial relations between and among the self and between objects arises such that when the higher level becomes dominant, it does not supplant lower level rationale. The result is that higher reasoning simply is integrated with patterns of prior reasoning, to the effect that prior schemas are modified to preclude contravening assumptions within the same system. Nevertheless, the core of Lakoff and Johnson s assumptions is that spatial relationships are the basis upon which increasingly more complex logic is constructed: Spatial-relations concepts are at the heart of our conceptual system (Lakoff and Johnson 1999: 30). The initial assumptions of the container schema consist in determining inside vs. outside. The inside-outside determination requires identifying boundaries (Lakoff and Johnson 1999: 31-32). Children focus on boundaries to specify locations of objects relative to landmarks. Initially landmarks are static they are not mobile, nor is movement of objects within them a possibility (Lakoff and Johnson 1999: 32). Landmark parameters are perceived to be relatively unchangeable, and are topological. Upon emergence of the source-path-goal schema, the issue of movement surfaces as a primary determinant of spatial relations (Lakoff and Johnson 1999: 32-34). Spatial and temporal sequences become paramount, such that spatial trajectories, involving motion to and from a landmark take precedence. During this process, cause and effect relations within event structures materialize as issues to be reckoned with, i.e., which event in the episode preceded other events to logically ascertain the resultant event (state/action). Southern Semiotic Review Issue 5 (1) 2015 54

Bodily projection schemas consider orientations other than a single, egocentric viewpoint. Perspectives recognizing the import of other points of view (entities, persons) facilitates the appreciation of origos (points of orientation) belonging to a unique perspective. Equally critical is dependence on one s own bodily interaction with objects and one s own orientation to entities, forms the foundation for recognition of other s (persons/things) unique perspectives appreciating their orientation. We project fronts and backs onto objects. What we understand as the front of a stationary artifact, like a TV or a computer or a stove, is the side we normally interact with using our fronts (Lakoff and Johnson 1999: 34). This projective perspective depends upon recognition of social roles and the particular physical, affective, and cognitive orientation of the origo. Movement in this genre is likewise critical, since repositioning of origo or of objects with respect to origo alters the relationship of origo to contextualized features. It is evident then that the more contemporary model of Lakoff and Johnson incorporates sensorimotor schemes into higher level reasoning, first by integrating movement into spatial parameters, and afterward when applying origo as the shifting role for the zero-point of orientation. In any case, basic spatial relations continue to serve as a necessary foundation for higher levels of reasoning. Peirce s Model of Lived Experience Peirce s model highlights the value of lived experience to prefigure higher reasoning skills. Four sequential levels emerge as indicators of abductive reasoning: pure Secondness, percepts, perceptual judgments, and hallucinations. Although these levels of reasoning represent epistemic (cognitive) advances, they do not preclude some components of affect in the mix. Whereas the initial reasoning levels (pure Secondness, percepts) have their foundation in physical interaction with the environment, the latter two levels (perceptual judgments, hallucinations) operate on elements of Thirdness and internal dialogue (with the self). Peirce characterizes reasoning from a pure Secondness perspective as compulsive (1903: EP2: 268). This compulsivity takes flight from the appearance on the scene of unexpected objects/events, and the spontaneous reaction which unforeseen circumstances impose on the human s response. Action orientation is then another obvious component of pure Secondness for Peirce (1885: CP 8.41). [volition] does involve the sense of action and reaction, resistance, externality, otherness, pair-edness. Pure Secondness does not merely result in reaction to stimuli, but surfaces as volition -- initiated action. Children take event roles other than that of receiver, as well as agent and the like. At this level of pure Secondness-based reasoning, Peirce accords direct experience a pivotal role in the Embodied Experience and the Semiosis of Abductive Reasoning by Donna E. West 55

emergence of higher reasoning skills (1903: CP 8.266): The practical exigencies of life render Secondness the most prominent of the three. This is not a conception, nor is it a peculiar quality. It is an experience. Peirce s next level to ascertain abductive reasoning draws on the percept as a point of departure. It is noteworthy, however, that the percept (despite its basis in Secondness) goes beyond raw experience to incorporate some element of interpretation (1903: CP 7.624). Moreover, percepts neither rest on, nor do they fail to rest on belief structures reflections on interpretations do not encompass belief or disbelief. Nonetheless, percepts do unequivocally consist in mental constructions (1903: CP 7.624): Every percept is the product of mental processes except that we are not directly aware of them They require some semblance of recognition of object attributes, but do not reach the level of generalizations or conscious deliberation. This kind of percept might entail an implicit comparison between two objects, without raising any general observation about how certain kinds of objects appear or function. In other words, percepts fall short of a classificatory operation, e.g., all balls are round and bounce. Although Peirce asserts that percepts are not the first impressions of sense (1902: CP 2.141). Not the first impressions of sense intimates that percepts only slightly extend beyond sense impressions -- to rather simple mental operations consequent to individualized experiences. To illustrate, recognition of an object or an observation that a particular ball bounces well, demonstrates mental processes just beyond first exposure to sense data. Any interpretations which ensue do not rise to the level of a second look back, given that analysis is unnecessary to experience a percept. All that is necessary is notice of an object and its effectiveness within an action schema. In contrast, perceptual judgments require reasoning beyond noticing, or beyond an awareness of object similarities, either functionally or perceptually. One of the functions of the perceptual judgment entails revealing the nature of percepts (CP 7.643). This process materializes via exposure to the percipuum (CP 7.643). As such, perceptual judgments ascribe to a higher order reasoning process than do percepts, such that the former exude Thirdness (CP 7.631), while the latter are still limited to Secondness in direct experience: There are several other points of contrast between the perceptual judgment and the percept that are calculated to exhibit their disparateness. The judgment, This chair appears yellow, separates the color from the chair, making the one predicate and the other subject. The percept, on the other hand, presents the chair in its entirety and makes no analysis whatever. Thirdness here has its foundation in the use of genuine signs (not degenerate uses). Short (2007: 90) characterizes the presence of Thirdness within the Interpretant of a sign as the primary characteristic to qualify for genuine signhood the meaning must be reducible. Southern Semiotic Review Issue 5 (1) 2015 56

Signs which are reducible derive some of their meaning/effects from factors beyond immediate experience and beyond the immediate space and time of the object s observation; that is, genuine Indexes derive meaning from the general use of a term, not from the contextual features coexistent with the Object. The general use of a term represents its invariant meaning in the code. Illustrations of genuine Indexes are deictics such as this / that when their contrastive use is apprehended (West 2012: 244). Accordingly, these Indexes are genuine by virtue of the rather objective function of their Interpretants near/far space from speaker s viewpoint (since according to cultural norms, speaker is origo). Furthermore, Interpretants of genuine Indexes must transcend limitations of haecceity (CP 3.460) accessibility to that which is near. Interpretants must reach a higher representational threshold, that of recognizing (however unconsciously) that speaker viewpoint can be assumed by anyone who actualizes the conversational role. (For further discussion of this topic, cf. West 2013). Without superseding limitations of haecceity necessary components of perceptual judgments could not materialize, especially the means to recommend a course of action. Peirce emphasizes that a primary characteristic of judgments is recommending a course of action (MS 637-12): It will be remarked that the result of both Practical and Scientific Retroduction is to recommend a course of action. This recommendation is not generated consequent to extensive deliberation; rather it arises spontaneously (CP 5.181). This spontaneous reasoning emerges in a flash to preclude any contrivance from infecting the recommendation: The abductive suggestion comes to us like a flash. It is an act of insight Additional support for the inclusion of spontaneity in abductive reasoning, Peirce recounts a particularly relevant incident in which his brother, Herbert, in a flash of insight made a determination to instantaneously cover their mother s burning dress with a rug, allegedly to save her from peril (CP 5.538). The judgment then constitutes a relatively undeliberated (perhaps fallible), but viable conclusion (CP 5.181). This account still does not suffice. Likewise incorporated into perceptual judgments is a recommendation which is functional not necessarily for the self, but for another. Perceptual judgments then must include Lakoff and Johnson s notion of the means to bodily project one s self into the place of another a return to space relations as the pivotal construct. Without projecting one s self into the place of another, an outgrowth of lived experience, a course of action could not be effectively recommended for another. In short, projecting one s self into the situation links individual epistemological and deontic issues to social ones, and perpetuates interpsychological advances. Recommending a course of action particular to another (a remedy which is likely to function for another), presupposes knowledge of another s idiosyncratic knowledge base, as well as an appreciation for their potential emotional reaction(s). Embodied Experience and the Semiosis of Abductive Reasoning by Donna E. West 57

Peirce s final, and most developed form of lived experience is hallucination. Such extends reasoning of perceptual judgments (CP 7.641 and CP 7.644): I proceed to compare the entire host of hallucinations, which there is no good reason to separate into the veridical and the non-veridical, and which there is good reason to account far more frequent than the census of the Society for Psychical Research admits. For Peirce hallucination does not conform to the ordinary or socially normative construal. It is distinguishable from that of the Psychoanalytic model and from common use, in that it necessarily entails the addition of compulsive affect. Such affect though does not by nature give rise to uncontrolled, untrue, unacceptable or destructive forces. Rather its actualization is creative it stimulates cognitive/epistemic growth (EP 2:192). This growth demonstrates a primary advance in intrapsychological reasoning, in that it materializes in the sudden synthesis of heretofore unforeseen connections/relations, to offer a novel rendition of or a projective account of events driven by unconventional affect, but without being subject to taboo or cultural sanctions. In fact, affect (which is an artifact of experience) is so crucial to epistemic development that, absent its influence, the inception of novel cognitions/propositions which inhabit Peirce s sense of hallucination are unlikely to come to fruition. Conclusion Although Lakoff and Johnson s model was proposed a century after that of C. S. Peirce, it highlights many of the spatial and experiential components which are only implicit in Peirce s account of logic construction. In particular primary to the development of abductive reasoning are three factors: personal implementation of experience in participatory action schemas, determining the epistemic and deontic complexion of another to suggest viable alternative approaches for them, and proposing alternative approaches/remedies from those already constructed. In short, advancing to abductive thinking requires both interpsychological (social), and intrapsychological competencies, largely arising from self-to-self dialogue. Hence, the role of lived experience in this enterprise can not be overstated. It is the catalyst for bodily participation in events, providing social and cultural remedies. Lived experience further hastens abductive reasoning (the proposal of novel, viable remedies) through the exercise of internally mediated problem-solving competencies. Southern Semiotic Review Issue 5 (1) 2015 58

References Lakoff, G. & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors We Live By. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Lakoff, G. & Johnson, M. (1999). Philosophy in the Flesh. New York: Basic Books. Peirce, C. S. (1867-1913). Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Vols. 1-6 edited by C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1931-1966. Vols. 7-8 edited by A. Burks. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1958. Peirce, C. S. (1867-1913). The Essential Peirce: Selected Philosophical Writings. Vol. 1, N. Houser & C. Kloesel (Eds.); Vol. 2, Peirce Edition Project, (eds.). Bloomington: University of Indiana Press, 1992-1998. Piaget, J. (1937/1954). The Construction of Reality in the Child. M. Cook, (trans.). New York: Ballantine Books. Short, T.L. (2007). Peirce s Theory of Signs. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. West, D. (2012). The semiosis of the degenerate index, : in K. Haworth, J. Hogue, and L. Sbrocchi, eds., Semiotics 2011, 240-246. Toronto: Legas Press. West, D. (2013). The semiosis of indexical use: From degenerate to genuine. The American Journal of Semiotics 28(3-4), 301-323. Embodied Experience and the Semiosis of Abductive Reasoning by Donna E. West 59