Predication and Ontology: The Categories

Similar documents
Aristotle s Metaphysics

Z.13: Substances and Universals

Aristotle s Categories and Physics

Substances. The Categories

Humanities 116: Philosophical Perspectives on the Humanities

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

Lecture 12 Aristotle on Knowledge of Principles

Aristotle's Metaphysics

ARISTOTLE S METAPHYSICS. February 5, 2016

ABELARD: THEOLOGIA CHRISTIANA

Accidental Beings in Aristotle s Ontology 1

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

PHILOSOPHY PLATO ( BC) VVR CHAPTER: 1 PLATO ( BC) PHILOSOPHY by Dr. Ambuj Srivastava / (1)

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

On Aristotelian Universals and Individuals: The Vink that is in Body and May Be In Me

Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates Republic Symposium Republic Phaedrus Phaedrus), Theaetetus

ON ARISTOTELIAN UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS: THE VINK THAT IS IN BODY AND MAY BE IN ME. Irena Cronin

Chapter 1. The Power of Names NAMING IS NOT LIKE COUNTING

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN:

Instantiation and Characterization: Problems in Lowe s Four-Category Ontology

«Only the revival of Kant's transcendentalism can be an [possible] outlet for contemporary philosophy»

Aristotle on the matter of corpses in Metaphysics H5

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Definition and Essence in Aristotle s Metaphysics vii 4

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala

Lecture 13 Aristotle on Change

Lecture 16 Thinking about schemas Ontology [and Semiotics] and the Web

Lecture 6.1: Introduction to Aristotle: The Categories

Identity and Individuation

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Alexander of Aphrodisias s Account of Universals and Its Problems

Riccardo Chiaradonna, Gabriele Galluzzo (eds.), Universals in Ancient Philosophy, Edizioni della Normale, 2013, pp. 546, 29.75, ISBN

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

Aristotle's Abstract Ontology

Aristotle. By Sarah, Lina, & Sufana

Aristotle's Stoichiology: its rejection and revivals

Aristotle, Vision, and Communicable Change

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

An introduction to biological essentialism. John Wilkins Biohumanities Project University of Queensland

AN INSIGHT INTO CONTEMPORARY THEORY OF METAPHOR

Tropes and the Semantics of Adjectives

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Valuable Particulars

The Influence of Chinese and Western Culture on English-Chinese Translation

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

THE TIME OF OUR LIVES: ARISTOTLE ON TIME, TEMPORAL PERCEPTION, RECOLLECTION, AND HABITUATION. MICHAEL BRUDER, B.A., M.A. A Thesis

Substances, Accidents, and Kinds: Some Remarks on Aristotle's Theory of Predication

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press,

Why Pleasure Gains Fifth Rank: Against the Anti-Hedonist Interpretation of the Philebus 1

ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPT OF MATIER IN THE CONTEXT OF CHANGE

Lecture 24: Motivating Modal Logic, Translating into It

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

LYCEUM A Publication of the Philosophy Department Saint Anselm College

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring Russell Marcus Hamilton College

- 1 - I. Aristotle A. Biographical data 1. Macedonian, from Stagira; hence often referred to as "the Stagirite". 2. Dates: B. C. 3.

To link to this article:

Aristotle on the Mechanism of Inheritance

The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall Class #7 Final Thoughts on Frege on Sense and Reference

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan. by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

Greek Ontology and the 'Is' of Truth MOHAN MATTHEN

Ludger Jansen (Rostock) Aristotle s Categories *

MATTHEWS GARETH B. Aristotelian Explanation. on "the role of existential presuppositions in syllogistic premisses"

A Basic Aristotle Glossary

[My method is] a science that studies the life of signs within society I shall call it semiology from the Greek semeion signs (Saussure)

Language and Mind Prof. Rajesh Kumar Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

The (Other) Meaning of Life: Aristotle on being animate

Types of perceptual content

Substance, Nature, and Immanence Form in Aristotle s Constituent Ontology

ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. Parmenides on Change The Puzzle Parmenides s Dilemma For Change

An Aristotelian Understanding of Object-Oriented Programming

Post 2 1 April 2015 The Prison-house of Postmodernism On Fredric Jameson s The Aesthetics of Singularity

Causes and Kinds in Aristotle s Embryology. Jessica Louise Gelber. A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the

The Philosophy of Language. Frege s Sense/Reference Distinction

Rhetoric - The Basics

Semiotics and the Philosophy of Language UMBERTO ECO INDIANA. University Press. Bloomington & Indianapolis

The Origin of Aristotle's Metaphysical Aporiae

JD Casten (free to share) Post Egoism Media Eugene, Oregon, USA

Martin, Gottfried: Plato s doctrine of ideas [Platons Ideenlehre]. Berlin: Verlag Walter de Gruyter, 1973

Ontology as a formal one. The language of ontology as the ontology itself: the zero-level language

Análisis Filosófico ISSN: Sociedad Argentina de Análisis Filosófico Argentina

QUESTION 7. The Circumstances of Human Acts

Unity and Primary Substance for Aristotle

dialectica The Place of Subjects in the Metaphysics of Material Objects

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Glossary alliteration allusion analogy anaphora anecdote annotation antecedent antimetabole antithesis aphorism appositive archaic diction argument

Relational Logic in a Nutshell Planting the Seed for Panosophy The Theory of Everything

Chapter 2 The Conception of Abstraction

The erratically fine-grained metaphysics of functional kinds in technology and biology

AP LANGUAGE & COMPOSITION SUMMER PROJECT

MAURICE MANDELBAUM HISTORY, MAN, & REASON A STUDY IN NINETEENTH-CENTURY THOUGHT THE JOHNS HOPKINS PRESS: BALTIMORE AND LONDON

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Aristotle on the Perception of Universals

Three Ones and Aristotle s Metaphysics

Plato s Absolute and Relative Categories at Sophist 255c14

Julie K. Ward. Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) Mathesis Publications

Transcription:

Predication and Ontology: The Categories A theory of ontology attempts to answer, in the most general possible terms, the question what is there? A theory of predication attempts to answer the question what is it to say something about something? This is a book about ontology and predication. Ontology: The Ten Categories In the Categories, we get this list (1b25): 1. Substance 2. Quality 3. Quantity 4. Relation 5. Where 6. When 7. Position 8. Having 9. Action 10. Passion This is presumably a list of the ten fundamentally different kinds of things that there are. The first category substance is the most important in Aristotle s ontology. Substances are, for Aristotle, the fundamental entities. To see why this is so, we will have to understand what Aristotle says about predication. Is this linguistics or ontology? What are the categories categories of? a. Things in the world? b. Linguistic expressions? c. Concepts? A likely account: Aristotle is classifying things in the world on the basis of linguistic considerations. (The idea seems to be that the structure of language mirrors the structure of reality.) Subjects and predicates These are non-linguistic entities: not the subjects and predicates of sentences, but the entities referred to by linguistic subjects and predicates. Examples: A subject (hupokeimenon) is what a statement is about. A predicate (katêgoroumenon) is what a statement says about its subject. This (particular animal) is a man. Man is an animal. This (particular color) is white. White is a color. Copyright 2008, S. Marc Cohen 1

Subjects This (particular animal) Man This (particular color) White Predicates Man Animal White Color The same thing may be both a subject and a predicate, e.g., man and white above. Some things are subjects but are never predicates, e.g., this (particular) animal, or this (particular) color. Two kinds of predication Consider the following pair of simple (atomic) sentences: Socrates is a human being Socrates is wise Do both of these atomic sentences have the same kind of ontological underpinning? I.e., is the structure of the fact that Socrates is a man the same as the structure of the fact that Socrates is wise? Plato s account suggests that it is. For Plato x is F means that x partakes of the Form, F-ness. For Plato, predication, in general, is explicated in terms of the notion of participating in a Form. In response, Aristotle thinks this oversimplifies. The superficial similarity between these two sentences disguises an important ontological difference in the facts they express. (In Greek, the sentences look even more similar than in English, since Greek lacks the indefinite pronoun: Socrates man (is) vs. Socrates wise (is).) On Aristotle s account: Socrates is a human being tells us something fundamental about what kind of a thing Socrates is: it is an essential predication. Socrates is wise tells us something less fundamental, something that merely happens to be the case: it is an accidental predication. For Aristotle, man is what Socrates IS; wise, on the other hand, is not what he IS (even though we say he is wise). Rather, it is something he HAS. (Cf. Code and Grice on IZZing and HAZZing handout on web site.) Copyright 2008, S. Marc Cohen 2

This idea emerges in the Categories distinction between what is said of a subject and what is in a subject, introduced as part of the four-fold distinction drawn at 1a20. Since Aristotle is using the terms said of and in in a somewhat technical way, we will write them, from now on, in SMALL CAPS in order to indicate this technical use. Two fundamental relations Aristotle s relations SAID OF a subject and IN a subject correspond, respectively, to the notions (that Aristotle later develops) of essential predication ( IZZing ) and accidental predication ( HAZZing ), and they cut across all ten categories. Aristotle Grice-Code Standard Interpretation x is SAID of y y IZZes x y is essentially x x is IN y y HAZZes x y is accidentally x SAID OF a subject This is a relation of fundamental ontological classification. It is the relation between a kind and a thing that falls under it. It is a transitive relation (i.e., if x is SAID OF y and y is SAID OF z, it follows that x is SAID OF z). Its relata belong to the same category. A universal in a given category is SAID OF the lower-level universals and individuals that fall under it. What is SAID OF a subject is essential to that subject. Examples Man is SAID OF Socrates. Animal is SAID OF man. (Hence) animal is SAID OF Socrates. White is SAID OF an individual <instance of> color. Color is SAID OF white. IN a subject This is a relation of fundamental ontological dependence. What is IN a subject, Aristotle says, belongs to it not as a part, and cannot exist separately from what it is in (1a24). Copyright 2008, S. Marc Cohen 3

This is a cross-categorial relation; things IN a subject are nonsubstances; the things they are IN are substances: non-substances are IN substances. What is IN a subject is accidental (non-essential) to that subject. Examples An individual <instance of> grammatical knowledge (hê tis grammatikê) is IN a soul. An individual <instance of> white is IN a body. Color is IN body. Universals and Particulars Although Aristotle does not use these terms in the Categories, it is clear that he intends to capture the notions of universal and particular with his SAID OF locution. Cf. these passages: De Int. 17 a 38: Some things are universals, others are particulars. By universal I mean what is naturally predicated of more than one thing; by particular, what is not. For example, man is a universal, and Callias is a particular. Met. B, 1000 a 1: For this is just what we mean by the individual the numerically one, and by universal we mean that which is predicable of the individuals. An. Pr. A27, 43a26ff: Of all the things which exist some are such that they cannot be predicated of anything else, e.g. Cleon and Callias, i.e. the individual and sensible, but other things may be predicated of them (for each of these is both man and animal); and some things are themselves predicated of others, but nothing prior is predicated of them; and some are predicated of others, and yet others of them, e.g. man of Callias and animal of man. It is clear then that some things are naturally not said of anything; for as a rule each sensible thing is such that it cannot be predicated of anything. So a universal is what is SAID OF some subject, and a particular is what is not SAID OF any subject. Note that there are universals and particulars in all the categories: Man and animal are universal substances (Aristotle calls them secondary substances.) Callias and an individual horse (ho tis hippos, lit. the some horse ) are particular substances. (Aristotle calls them primary substances.) White and color are universal qualities. Copyright 2008, S. Marc Cohen 4

An individual <instance of> white (to ti leukon, lit. the some white ) is a particular quality. The fourfold division (Categories, Ch. 2) The SAID OF relation divides entities into universals and particulars; the IN relation divides them into substances and non-substances. Hence, the fourfold division at 1 a 20ff produces (in Aristotle s order of presentation): a. Universal substances ( secondary substances ) b. Particular non-substances c. Universal non-substances d. Particular substances ( primary substances ) (a) SAID OF a subject not IN a subject man, horse, animal (the species) Universal Substances (c) SAID OF a subject IN a subject knowledge, white Universal non-substances (d) not SAID OF a subject not IN a subject an individual man, an individual horse Individual Substances (b) IN a subject not SAID OF a subject a bit of grammatical knowledge an individual <instance of> white Individual non-substances Notice the following facts about these relations: 1. x is SAID OF something x is a universal. 2. x is not SAID OF anything x is a particular. 3. x is IN y x is a non-substance and y is a substance. 4. x is not IN anything x is a substance. 5. x is neither IN anything nor SAID OF anything x is a particular substance (primary substance). Copyright 2008, S. Marc Cohen 5

6. x is IN y and x is SAID OF z y z. (6) may require amplification. The reason is that if x is IN y, then y is a substance and x is a non-substance (e.g., a quality). But if x is a quality and is SAID OF z, then z is a (more specific) quality. So y is a substance and z is a quality. But no quality is a substance. For example, knowledge is IN the soul (a substance), and SAID OF grammar (a kind of knowledge). But knowledge is not SAID OF the soul (for the soul is not a kind of knowledge), and knowledge is not IN grammar (for grammar is not a substance). Cross-categorial predication Predication within a category ( Socrates is a human, a tiger is an animal, red is a color ) involves classifying something (whether a particular or a universal) under some higher universal within the same category tree. Predication is a matter of classification. Cross-categorial predication ( Socrates is wise, This horse is white ) is more complicated. Here we are predicating an accident (something IN a subject) of a substance in which it inheres. Are such (accidental) predications still a matter of classification? Yes. But we are classifying something IN a substance, rather than the substance itself. Example: This horse is white classifies a particular bit of color, inhering in this horse, under the color-universal white. That is: White is SAID OF an individual bit of color that is IN this horse. Category Trees Each category can be thought of as having a tree structure. The category itself can be divided into its fundamental kinds (e.g., substance can be divided into plants and animals). Each of these kinds can in turn be divided (e.g., animal can be divided into the various broad genera of animals). Each of these can in turn be divided into the fundamental species of the category in questions (e.g., into such basic kinds as tiger, and horse, and human being). (All of these kinds animal, tiger, horse are what Aristotle calls secondary substances.) Finally, we can divide these lowest-level kinds into the basic individuals in the category (e.g., human being can be divided into Socrates, Callias, Coriscus, etc.). Copyright 2008, S. Marc Cohen 6

Similarly, the category of quality can be divided into subcategories such as color, which can in turn be divided into red, green, etc. Aristotle thinks that these specific qualities can be further divided into individuals (analogous to individual substances) such as this individual instance of white. Thus, each category is ultimately divisible into the individual members of that category. Here s a useful chart that illustrates the tree structure of the categories. Primary Substances: the basic individuals Things neither SAID OF nor IN any subject Aristotle calls primary substances (protai ousiai). They are fundamental in that if they did not exist it would be impossible for any of the other things to exist (2 b 5). That is, on Aristotle s account, primary substances have ontological priority. Here is his argument (2 a 34-2 b 7): 1. Every secondary (universal) substance is predicated of (i.e., SAID OF) some primary substance or other. 2. Every non-substance (whether universal or particular) is IN some primary substance or other. 3. That is, everything other than primary substance is either SAID OF or IN primary substances. 4. Therefore, if primary substances did not exist, neither would anything else. Copyright 2008, S. Marc Cohen 7

Amplifications on Aristotle s argument: It is clear that a non-substance cannot exist unless it is IN a substance. For the only subject a non-substance can be IN is a substance, and things IN a subject (i.e., non-substances) cannot exist if they are not IN subjects. What about universals? Aristotle s premises seem to leave open the possibility that they might exist even though they are not SAID OF anything. But he clearly seems to be assuming an ontological dependence condition for universals analogous to the one he assumes for non-substances: The existence of a universal depends upon there being individuals falling under it. So universal substances cannot exist unless there are primary substances for them to be SAID OF. And universal non-substances cannot exist unless there are individual non-substances for them to be SAID OF. And individual non-substances cannot exist unless there are substances for them to be IN. Therefore, if there were no primary substances, there would not be anything else. Some important features of substances See esp. Categories chapter 5. Substances are not IN subjects (they are not dependent entities). Differentiae are not IN subjects either. Why does Aristotle say this? After all, differentiae are (typically) qualities, and qualities can exist only by being IN substances. So it would seem to follow that differentiae are IN subjects. The precise status of differentiae in Aristotle s system is hard to pin down. But there are some good reasons for him to say that differentiae are not IN subjects: a. It seems to be a corollary of his claim that substances are not IN subjects. For Aristotle thinks that a definition consists of genus + differentia (cf. Topics A.8, 103 b 15). So a differentia of a substance is part of what the substance IZZES, and not something it HAZZES. Copyright 2008, S. Marc Cohen 8

b. When Aristotle talks about parts of substances in the Categories, he is probably thinking of conceptual parts, and differentiae would be such parts (cf. Frede, Individuals in Aristotle ). But Aristotle says that the things IN a subject are not parts of the subject, i.e., not differentiae. Perhaps Aristotle can say about differentiae (of substances) what he says about secondary substances (3 b 14-22): a secondary substance signifies a poion lit. quality, but here it pretty clearly means sort. He certainly does not think that horse (the species) is a quality he thinks it is a type or sort of substance. (That s why he says that a species such as horse is not simply a poion, but a poion with respect to substance 3 b 21). Similarly, a differentia is not simply a poion, but a poion with respect to substance. That means that it is not a quality (in the way that white is a quality); and hence it does not count as being IN a subject. Substances have no contraries (opposites). Substances do not admit of degree. (If F is a substance term, nothing can be more or less F.) Most distinctive Aristotle says (4a10) is that substances remain one and the same while admitting contraries. By this Aristotle means that a distinctive feature of substances is that they undergo change. That is, they persist through changes. They can be subjects of change. We will examine this. Substances and Change Presumably, in the Categories Aristotle thinks that only substances can undergo change. Since he holds that change requires that one property of a subject be replaced by another, opposed, property, what he has to prove is this: if x goes from being F at one time to being not-f at a later time, then x is a substance. [One might think that Aristotle can obtain this conclusion easily, since it might appear that only substances can be subjects. But although he is tempted by this equation of substancehood with subjecthood, he realizes that it will not work. Cf. Topics A9: the what is it? question can be raised about qualities, quantities, etc. So any item from any category can be a subject.] Copyright 2008, S. Marc Cohen 9

The argument he gives in the Categories consists in choosing some nonsubstances as values of x, and then showing that for a choice of values of F (with respect to which we would expect there to be change) x does not go from being F at one time to being not-f at another time. These are his examples: a. x = a color F = white not-f = black b. x = an action F = good not-f = bad But these examples beg the question. For the choices of values for x and F are from the same category. [This is certainly clear in the case of example (a).] Yet when Aristotle gives an example of change, x and F are from different categories, with x a substance and F a non-substance. a. If x and F are both from the category of substance, there will not be change either. E.g., an animal (x) does not go from being a horse (F) to a tiger (not-f). b. If x and F are from different categories, change appears to be possible even if x is a non-substance. E.g., a color (x) can go from being in Boston (F) to being in Seattle (not-f), or from being popular (F) to being unpopular (not-f). The principle on which Aristotle s point seems to depend is this: A thing never changes with respect to what it IZZes, but only with respect to what it HAZZes. And this seems to guarantee that substances can change (since every substance HAZZes some accidental properties); but it doesn t show that only substances can change. For it hasn t been proved that non-substances can t also HAZZ accidental properties. A Defense of Aristotle What can be said in behalf of Aristotle s argument? There is still an intuition that substances play a special role as subjects. One might defend that intuition in the following way: In those cases in which a non-substance (e.g. a quality) seems to change (i.e. goes from being F to being not-f), the change doesn t really seem to be in the non-substance that is the apparent subject, but in some (unspecified) Copyright 2008, S. Marc Cohen 10

substance. E.g., cf. Purple has become unpopular. Here, it seems that purple itself hasn t changed. Rather, people (substances) have changed their attitudes about colors. So we can analyze Purple has become unpopular as Most people no longer like purple. In this case, a more defensible thesis for Aristotle might be: Every (apparent) change which a non-substance undergoes can be analyzed as a (real) change that a substance undergoes. But even this thesis (as we shall see) will not stand up. The criterion of ultimate subject of change for substancehood will have to be given up. Aristotle s Ontology after the Categories. In the Categories, individual substances are left unanalyzed, structureless. They are (in Furth s phrase) methodologically opaque. The further analysis of individual substances is motivated by concerns about change, in the Physics and Metaphysics. This analysis will complicate Aristotle s ontology and threaten the primacy of the individual (concrete) substances of the Categories. So we will move on to examine the introduction of matter in the Physics and the problems that it raises in the Metaphysics. Copyright 2008, S. Marc Cohen 11