The (Lack of) Evidence for the Kuhnian Image of Science: A Reply to Arnold and Bryant

Similar documents
Is There Anything Wrong with Thomas Kuhn? Markus Arnold, University of Klagenfurt

Each Kuhn Mutually Incommensurable. Amanda Bryant, Trent University

What s the Support for Kuhn s Incommensurability Thesis? A Response to Mizrahi and Patton James A. Marcum, Baylor University

Incommensurability and the Bonfire of the Meta-Theories: Response to Mizrahi Lydia Patton, Virginia Tech

Keywords: incommensurability; lexical taxonomy; scientific change; scientific revolution; Thomas Kuhn

Can Kuhn s Taxonomic Incommensurability Be an Image of Science?

Semantic Incommensurability and Scientific Realism. Howard Sankey. University of Melbourne. 1. Background


Sidestepping the holes of holism

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

An Alternative to Kitcher s Theory of Conceptual Progress and His Account of the Change of the Gene Concept

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

In Search of Mechanisms, by Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden, 2013, The University of Chicago Press.

AN ALTERNATIVE TO KITCHER S THEORY OF CONCEPTUAL PROGRESS AND HIS ACCOUNT OF THE CHANGE OF THE GENE CONCEPT. Ingo Brigandt

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1

Modeling Scientific Revolutions: Gärdenfors and Levi on the Nature of Paradigm Shifts

Normal Science and Normal Kuhn.

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

(as methodology) are not always distinguished by Steward: he says,

Hoyningen Symposium Systematicity: The Nature of Science

Université Libre de Bruxelles

Claim: refers to an arguable proposition or a conclusion whose merit must be established.

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

PART II METHODOLOGY: PROBABILITY AND UTILITY

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

The Art of Time Travel: A Bigger Picture

MATTHEWS GARETH B. Aristotelian Explanation. on "the role of existential presuppositions in syllogistic premisses"

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

REVIEW. Patrick Enfield

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Thomas Kuhn's "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions"

The Debate on Research in the Arts

Why Pleasure Gains Fifth Rank: Against the Anti-Hedonist Interpretation of the Philebus 1

Kuhn and the Structure of Scientific Revolutions. How does one describe the process of science as a human endeavor? How does an

The UCD community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters!

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress: Reduction Between Incommensurable Theories in a Rigid Structuralist Framework

Science: A Greatest Integer Function A Punctuated, Cumulative Approach to the Inquisitive Nature of Science

MODULE 4. Is Philosophy Research? Music Education Philosophy Journals and Symposia

Logic and argumentation techniques. Dialogue types, rules

The Epistemological Status of Theoretical Simplicity YINETH SANCHEZ

CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Introduction to the Philosophy of Science

Caught in the Middle. Philosophy of Science Between the Historical Turn and Formal Philosophy as Illustrated by the Program of Kuhn Sneedified

Kuhn and coherentist epistemology

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

RETHINKING SCIENTIFIC CHANGE AND THEORY COMPARISON

26:010:685 Social Science Methods in Accounting Research

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

Relativism and the Social Construction of Science: Kuhn, Lakatos, Feyerabend

Philosophical foundations for a zigzag theory structure

Perceptions and Hallucinations

THE STRUCTURE OF SCIENTIFIC REVOLUTIONS

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN:

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

A New Approach to the Paradox of Fiction Pete Faulconbridge

Thomas S. Kuhn ( )

In The Meaning of Ought, Matthew Chrisman draws on tools from formal semantics,

observation and conceptual interpretation

Prephilosophical Notions of Thinking

Internal Realism. Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

THE LANGUAGE OF SCIENCE: MEANING VARIANCE AND THEORY COMPARISON HOWARD SANKEY *

Examples of straw man fallacy in advertising

AN ABSTRACT OF THE THESIS OF

Composition, Counterfactuals, Causation

Teaching Art History to Children: A Philosophical Basis

Glossary of Rhetorical Terms*

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Introduction to the Philosophy of Science

IS SCIENCE PROGRESSIVE?

12th Grade Language Arts Pacing Guide SLEs in red are the 2007 ELA Framework Revisions.

Conceptual Change, Relativism, and Rationality

General Educational Development (GED ) Objectives 8 10

ARISTOTLE ON SCIENTIFIC VS NON-SCIENTIFIC DISCOURSE. Philosophical / Scientific Discourse. Author > Discourse > Audience

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

2016 Ian Michael Hegger

Perception and Mind-Dependence Lecture 3

SUPERIOR COURT OF THE STATE OF CALIFORNIA FOR THE COUNTY OF LOS ANGELES ) ) ) ) ) ) ) ) ) ) ) ) ) ) ) ) ) ) )

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Interpretive and Critical Research Traditions

Normative and Positive Economics

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

Review of "The Unexplained Intellect: Complexity, Time, and the Metaphysics of Embodied Thought"

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner

istarml: Principles and Implications

Paradox, Metaphor, and Practice: Serious Complaints and the Tourism Industry

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

Cyclic vs. circular argumentation in the Conceptual Metaphor Theory ANDRÁS KERTÉSZ CSILLA RÁKOSI* In: Cognitive Linguistics 20-4 (2009),

Glossary alliteration allusion analogy anaphora anecdote annotation antecedent antimetabole antithesis aphorism appositive archaic diction argument

Improving Scientific Language

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Part IV Social Science and Network Theory

Systemic and meta-systemic laws

Transcription:

The (Lack of) Evidence for the Kuhnian Image of Science: A Reply to Arnold and Bryant Moti Mizrahi, Florida Institute of Technology, mmizrahi@fit.edu Whenever the work of an influential philosopher is criticized, a common move made by those who seek to defend the influential philosopher s work is to claim that his or her ideas have been misconstrued. This is an effective move, of course, for it means that the critics have criticized a straw man, not the ideas actually put forth by the influential philosopher. However, this move can easily backfire, too. For continued iterations of this move could render the ideas in question immune to criticism in a rather ad hoc fashion. That is to say, shouting straw man every time an influential philosopher s ideas are subjected to scrutiny is rather like shouting wolf when none is around; it could be seen as an attempt to draw attention to that which may not be worthy of attention. The question, then, is whether the influential philosopher s ideas are worthy of attention and/or acceptance. In particular, are Kuhn s ideas about scientific revolutions and incommensurability worthy of acceptance? As I have argued, along with a few other contributors to my edited volume, The Kuhnian Image of Science: Time for a Decisive Transformation? (2018), they may not be because they are based on dubious assumptions and fallacious argumentation. In their reviews of The Kuhnian Image of Science: Time for a Decisive Transformation? (2018), both Markus Arnold (2018) and Amanda Bryant (2018) complain that the contributors who criticize Kuhn s theory of scientific change have misconstrued his philosophy of science and they praise those who seek to defend the Kuhnian image of science. In what follows, then, I would like to address their claims about misconstruing Kuhn s theory of scientific change. But my focus here, as in the book, will be the evidence (or lack thereof) for the Kuhnian image of science. I will begin with Arnold s review and then move on to Bryant s review. 1. Arnold on the Evidence for the Kuhnian Image of Science Arnold (2018, 42) states that one of the results of [his] review is that the inductive reasoning intended to refute Kuhn s incommensurability thesis (found in the first part of the book) is actually its weakest part. I am not sure what he means by that exactly. First, I am not sure in what sense inductive reasoning can be said to refute a thesis, given that inductive arguments are the sort of arguments whose premises do not necessitate the truth of their conclusions, whereas a refutation of p, if sound, supposedly shows that p must be false. Second, contrary to what Arnold claims, I do not think that the chapters in Part I of the book contain inductive reasoning intended to refute Kuhn s incommensurability thesis (Arnold 2018, 42). Speaking of my chapter in particular, Chapter 1 (Mizrahi 2018b, 32-38), it contains two arguments intended to show that there is no deductive support for the Kuhnian thesis of taxonomic incommensurability (Mizrahi 2018b, 32), and an argument intended to show that there is no inductive support for the Kuhnian thesis of taxonomic incommensurability (Mizrahi 2018b, 37). These arguments are deductive, not inductive, for their premises, if true, guarantee the truth of their conclusions. Besides, to argue that there is no evidence for p is not the same as arguing that p is false. None of my arguments is intended to show that p (namely, the Kuhnian thesis of taxonomic 1

incommensurability) is false. Rather, my arguments show that there is no evidence for p (namely, the Kuhnian thesis of taxonomic incommensurability). For these reasons, as a criticism of Part I of the book, Arnold s (2018, 42) claim that the inductive reasoning intended to refute Kuhn s incommensurability thesis (found in the first part of the book) is actually its weakest part completely misses the mark. Moreover, the only thing I could find in Arnold s review that could be construed as support for this claim is the aforementioned complaint about straw-manning Kuhn. As Arnold (2018, 43) puts it, the counter-arguments under consideration brought forward against his model seem, paradoxically, to underestimate the complexity of Kuhn s claims. In other words, Kuhn s theory of scientific change is so complex and those who attempt to criticize it fail to appreciate its complexity. But why? Why do the criticisms fail to appreciate the complexity of Kuhn s theory? How complex is it such that it defies interpretation and criticism? Arnold does not say. Instead, he (Arnold 2018, 43) states that it is not clear, why Kuhn s image of science should be dismissed because [...] taxonomic incommensurability is the exception rather than the rule [Mizrahi 2018b,] (38). As I argue in Chapter 1, however, the fact that taxonomic incommensurability is the exception rather than the rule (Mizrahi 2018b, 38) means that Kuhn s theory of scientific change is a bad theory because it shows that Kuhn s theory has neither explanatory nor predictive power. A theory with no explanatory and/or predictive power is no theory at all (Mizrahi 2018b, 37-38). From his review, however, it is clear that Arnold thinks of Kuhn s image of science as a theory of scientific change. For instance, he talks about Kuhn s epistemology (Arnold 2018, 45), Kuhn s theory of incommensurability (Arnold 2018, 46), and Kuhn s complex theory of science (Arnold 2018, 42). If Kuhn s thesis of taxonomic incommensurability has no explanatory and/or predictive power, then it is a bad theory, perhaps not even a theory at all, let alone a general theory of scientific knowledge or scientific change. In that respect, I found it rather curious that, on the one hand, Arnold approves of Alexandra Argamakova s (2018) criticism of the universal ambitions of Kuhn s image of science, but on the other hand, he wants to attribute to Kuhn the view that scientific revolutions are rare (Arnold 2018, 43). Arnold quotes with approval Argamakova s (2018, 54) claim that distinct breakthroughs in science can be marked as revolutions, but no universal system of criteria for such appraisal can be formulated in a normative philosophical manner (emphasis added). In other words, if Argamakova is right, then there can be no philosophical theory of scientific change in general, Kuhnian or otherwise. So Arnold cannot be in agreement with Argamakova without thereby abandoning the claim that Kuhn s image of science is an epistemology (Arnold 2018, 45) of scientific knowledge or a complex theory of science (Arnold 2018, 42). Arnold (2018, 45) also asserts that the allegation that Kuhn developed his theory on the basis of selected historical cases is refuted by Kindi (2018). Even if that were true, it would mean that Kuhn s theory has no inductive support, as I argue in Chapter 1 of the book (Mizrahi 2018b, 32-38). So I am not sure how this point is supposed to help Arnold in defending the Kuhnian image of science. For if there is no inductive support for the Kuhnian image of science, 2

as Arnold seems to think, and there is no deductive support either, as I (Mizrahi 2018b, 25-44) and Park (2018, 61-74) argue, then what evidence is there for the Kuhnian image of science? For present purposes, the important point is not how Kuhn developed his theory (Arnold 2018, 45) but rather what supports his theory of scientific change. What is the evidence for a Kuhnian theory of scientific change? If I am right (Mizrahi 2018b), or if Park (2018) is right, then there is neither deductive support nor inductive support for a Kuhnian theory of scientific change. If Argamakova is right, then there can be no general theory of scientific change at all, Kuhnian or otherwise. It is also important to note here that Arnold (2018, 45) praises both Kindi (2018) and Patton (2018) for offering a close reading of Kuhn s work, but he does not mention that they offer incompatible interpretations of that work, specifically, of the evidence for Kuhn s ideas about scientific change. On Kindi s reading of Kuhn, the argument for the Kuhnian image of science is a deductive argument from first principles, whereas on Patton s reading of Kuhn, the argument for the Kuhnian image of science is an inference to the best explanation (see Patton 2015, cf. Mizrahi 2018a, 12-13; Mizrahi 2015, 51-53). 2. Bryant on the Evidence for the Kuhnian Image of Science Like Arnold, Bryant (2018, 1) wonders whether Kuhn s views on scientific change can be pinned down and criticized or perhaps there are many Thomases Kuhn. Again, I think we do not want to make Kuhn s views too vague and/or ambiguous (Argamakova 2018, 47-50), and thus immune to criticism in a rather ad hoc fashion. For that, in addition to being based on dubious assumptions and fallacious argumentation, would be another reason to think that Kuhn s views are not worthy of acceptance. Bryant (2018, 1) also wonders whether the so-called Kuhnian image of science is really so broadly endorsed as to be the potential subject of (echoing Kuhn s own phrase) a decisive transformation. As I see it, however, the question is not whether the Kuhnian image of science is broadly endorsed. Rather, the question is whether we are now possessed by it. When Kuhn wrote that (in)famous first line of the introduction to The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, the image of science by which we were possessed was a positivist image of science according to which science develops by the accumulation of individual discoveries and inventions (Kuhn 1962/1996, 2). Arguably, philosophers of science were never possessed by such a positivist image of science as much as they are possessed by the Kuhnian image of science. This is evidenced by the fact that no positivist work in philosophy of science has had as much impact as Kuhn s seminal work (Mizrahi 2018a, 1-2). Accordingly, even if the Kuhnian image of science is not broadly endorsed, it is quite clear that philosophers of science are possessed by it. For this reason, an exorcism, or a decisive transformation, is required in order to rid ourselves of this image of science. And what better way to do so than by showing that it is based on dubious assumptions and fallacious argumentation. As far as the evidence (or lack thereof) for the Kuhnian image of science, Bryant (2018, 2) claims that Case studies can be interesting, informative, and evidential (emphasis added). I grant that case studies can be interesting and informative, but I doubt that they can be evidential. 3

From Scientific episode E has property F, it does not follow that F is a characteristic of scientific episodes in general. As far as Kuhn is concerned, it is clear that he used just a few case studies (e.g., the phlogiston case) in support of his ideas about scientific change and incommensurability. The problem with that, as I argue in Chapter 1 of the book (Mizrahi 2018b, 32-38), is that no general theory of scientific change can be derived from a few cherry-picked case studies. Even if we grant that the phlogiston case is a genuine case of a so-called Kuhnian revolution and taxonomic incommensurability, despite the fact that there are rebutting defeaters (Mizrahi 2018b, 33-36), no general conclusions about the nature of science can be drawn from one (or even a few) such cases (Mizrahi 2018b, 36-37). From the fact that one (or a few) cherrypicked episode(s) from the history of science exhibits a particular property, it does not follow that all scientific episodes have that property; otherwise, from the Piltdown man episode we would have to conclude that fraud characterizes scientific discovery in general (Mizrahi 2018b, 37-38). Speaking of scientific discovery, Bryant (2018, 2) takes issue with the fact that I cite just two authors, Eric Oberheim and Paul Hoyningen-Huene, who use the language of discovery to characterize incommensurability. For Bryant (2018, 2), this suggests that it isn t clear that the assumption Mizrahi takes pains to reject is particularly widespread (emphasis added). I suppose that the assumption in question here is that Kuhn discovered incommensurability. If so, then I would like to clarify that I mention the fact that Oberheim and Hoyningen-Huene talk about incommensurability in terms of discovery, and claim that Kuhn discovered it, not to argue against it (i.e., to argue that Kuhn did not discover incommensurability), but rather to show that some of the elements of the Kuhnian image of science, such as incommensurability, are sometimes taken for granted. When it is said that someone has discovered something, it gives the impression that what has been discovered is a fact, and so no arguments are needed. When it comes to incommensurability, however, it is far from clear that it is a fact about scientific change, and so good arguments are needed in order to establish that episodes of scientific change exhibit taxonomic incommensurability. If I am right, or if Park (2018) and Sankey (2018) are right, then there are no good arguments that establish this. In light of the above, I think that the questions raised in the edited volume under review remain urgent (cf. Rehg 2018). Are there good reasons or compelling evidence for the Kuhnian model of theory change in science? If there are no good reasons or compelling evidence for such a model, as I (Mizrahi 2018b), Park (2018), and Sankey (2018) argue, what s next for philosophers of science? Should we abandon the search for a general theory of science, as Argamakova (2018) suggests? Are there better models of scientific change? Perhaps evolutionary (Marcum 2018) or orthogenetic (Renzi and Napolitano 2018) models? Acknowledgments I would like to thank Markus Arnold and Amanda Bryant for their thoughtful reviews. I am also grateful to Adam Riggio and Eric Kerr for organizing this book symposium and for inviting me to participate. 4

References Argamakova, Alexandra. Modeling Scientific Development: Lessons from Thomas Kuhn. In The Kuhnian Image of Science: Time for a Decisive Transformation?, edited by Moti Mizrahi, 45-59. London: Rowman & Littlefield, 2018. Arnold, Markus. Is There Anything Wrong With Thomas Kuhn? Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 7, no. 5 (2018): 42-47. Bryant, Amanda. Each Kuhn Mutually Incommensurable. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 7, no. 6 (2018): 1-7. Kindi, Vasso. The Kuhnian Straw Man. In The Kuhnian Image of Science: Time for a Decisive Transformation?, edited by Moti Mizrahi, 95-112. London: Rowman & Littlefield, 2018. Kuhn, Thomas S. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Third Edition. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1962/1996. Marcum, James A. Revolution or Evolution in Science? A Role for the Incommensurability Thesis? In The Kuhnian Image of Science: Time for a Decisive Transformation?, edited by Moti Mizrahi, 155-173. London: Rowman & Littlefield, 2018. Mizrahi, Moti. A Reply to Patton s Incommensurability and the Bonfire of the Meta-Theories. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 4, no. 10 (2015): 51-53. Mizrahi, Moti. Introduction. In The Kuhnian Image of Science: Time for a Decisive Transformation?, edited by Moti Mizrahi, 1-22. London: Rowman & Littlefield, 2018a. Mizrahi, Moti. Kuhn s Incommensurability Thesis: What s the Argument? In The Kuhnian Image of Science: Time for a Decisive Transformation?, edited by Moti Mizrahi, 25-44. London: Rowman & Littlefield, 2018b. Park, Seungbae. Can Kuhn s Taxonomic Incommensurability be an Image of Science? In The Kuhnian Image of Science: Time for a Decisive Transformation?, edited by Moti Mizrahi, 61-74. London: Rowman & Littlefield, 2018. Patton, Lydia. Incommensurability and the Bonfire of the Meta-Theories: Response to Mizrahi. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 4, no. 7 (2015): 51-58. Patton, Lydia. Kuhn, Pedagogy, and Practice: A Local Reading of Structure. In The Kuhnian Image of Science: Time for a Decisive Transformation?, edited by Moti Mizrahi, 113-130. London: Rowman & Littlefield, 2018. Rehg, William. Kuhn s Image of Science. Metascience (2018): https://doi.org/10.1007/s11016-018-0306-2. 5

Renzi, Barbara G. and Giulio Napolitano. The Biological Metaphors of Scientific Change. In The Kuhnian Image of Science: Time for a Decisive Transformation?, edited by Moti Mizrahi, 177-190. London: Rowman & Littlefield, 2018. 6