Theories of Truth in Chinese Philosophy: A Comparative Approach by Alexus McLeod (review)

Similar documents
Trying Not to Try: The Art and Science of Spontaneity by Edward Slingerland (review)

Two Roads to Wisdom? Chinese and Analytic Philosophical Traditions, edited by Bo Mou (La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, 2001; pp. xvii, 381).

Zhu Xi's Reading of the Analects: Canon, Commentary, and the Classical Tradition (review)

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

SYLLABUSES FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS

Moral Geography and Exploration of the Moral Possibility Space

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

Dao Companions to Chinese Philosophy 4. Amy Olberding Editor. Dao Companion to the Analects

Moral Judgment and Emotions

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

How Semantics is Embodied through Visual Representation: Image Schemas in the Art of Chinese Calligraphy *

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

SINGAPORE MANAGEMENT UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF SOCIAL SCIENCES PHIL207 INTRODUCTION TO CLASSICAL CHINESE PHILOSOPHY

In The Meaning of Ought, Matthew Chrisman draws on tools from formal semantics,

Educating for Virtuoso Living: Papers from the Ninth East-West Philosophers' Conference

Hermeneutics from the Qing to the Present 'T\J. 52 Interpretation and Intellectual Change

Searching for the Way. Theory of Knowledge in Pre-modern and Modern China. Hong Kong: The Chinese University Press, Pp. xvi U.S. $52.00.

Perspectives on the Methods of Chinese Philosophy

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Humanities Learning Outcomes

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

TRAGIC THOUGHTS AT THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN:

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF. the oxford handbook of WORLD PHILOSOPHY. GARFIELD-Halftitle2-Page Proof 1 August 10, :24 PM

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

China. By Edward Slingerland. New York: Oxford University Press, Pp. xii +

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Literary Theory and Literary Criticism Prof. Aysha Iqbal Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Chapter 2: Reading for the Main Idea and Author s Purpose

CHINESE (CHIN) Courses. Chinese (CHIN) 1

CHAPTER TWO. A brief explanation of the Berger and Luckmann s theory that will be used in this thesis.

A New Perspective on the Scope and Meaning of Chinese Literature

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

observation and conceptual interpretation

A Step-by-Step Guide to Writing a Good History Day Paper

Face-threatening Acts: A Dynamic Perspective

On Interpretation and Translation

HEGEL S CONCEPT OF ACTION

CONFUCIANISM IS A LIVING tradition that contributes to contemporary

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Metonymy Research in Cognitive Linguistics. LUO Rui-feng

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Review of Li, The Confucian Philosophy of Harmony

On Recanati s Mental Files

Response to Seth D. Clippard, "Zhu Xi and the Instrumental Value of Nature"

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

On Jing 敬 Thinking Through Tang Junyi on Chinese Culture in Diaspora. Kwong-loi Shun. 1. Introduction: Tang Junyi on Chinese Culture in Diaspora

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Argumentation and Persuasion in Ancient Chinese Texts Introduction

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

Ren as a Communal Property in the Analects

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

Colonnade Program Course Proposal: Explorations Category

Principal version published in the University of Innsbruck Bulletin of 4 June 2012, Issue 31, No. 314

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

Pierre Hadot on Philosophy as a Way of Life. Pierre Hadot ( ) was a French philosopher and historian of ancient philosophy,

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Chinese Intellectual History

Ideological and Political Education Under the Perspective of Receptive Aesthetics Jie Zhang, Weifang Zhong

The Object Oriented Paradigm

scholars have imagined and dealt with religious people s imaginings and dealings

Student Performance Q&A:

Current Issues in Pictorial Semiotics

Early Daoism and Metaphysics

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Reviewed by Max Kölbel, ICREA at Universitat de Barcelona

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

Nature's Perspectives

Why Take Confucian Ethics Seriously?

Karen Hutzel The Ohio State University, Columbus, Ohio REFERENCE BOOK REVIEW 327

A Hybrid Theory of Metaphor

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

Two-Dimensional Semantics the Basics

The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall 2015

Guide to Citations Using the APA Style

Kant, Peirce, Dewey: on the Supremacy of Practice over Theory

Conceptual Change, Relativism, and Rationality

Interpreting Confucius: the Aesthetic Turn and Its Challenges

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

A Metalinguistic Approach to The Color Purple Xia-mei PENG

Phenomenology Glossary

Review of "The Unexplained Intellect: Complexity, Time, and the Metaphysics of Embodied Thought"

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

Research Projects on Rudolf Steiner'sWorldview

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

Significant Differences An Interview with Elizabeth Grosz

Twentieth Excursus: Reference Magnets and the Grounds of Intentionality

BDD-A Universitatea din București Provided by Diacronia.ro for IP ( :46:58 UTC)

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong

CHRIS FRASER ZHUANGZI, XUNZI, AND THE PARADOXICAL NATURE OF EDUCATION. Introduction

Transcription:

Theories of Truth in Chinese Philosophy: A Comparative Approach by Alexus McLeod (review) Frank Saunders Jr. Philosophy East and West, Volume 68, Number 1, January 2018, pp. 324-327 (Review) Published by University of Hawai'i Press DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/pew.2018.0027 For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/682219 Access provided by National Taiwan University (12 Apr 2018 09:11 GMT)

Kwong-loi Shun s chapter 11, On Anger: An Essay on Confucian Moral Psychology, is a philosophical construction of the problem of anger by appealing not only to Zhu Xi s account but also to Confucian views, broadly construed, showing how Chinese ideas may serve as the ground for some new perspectives on the subject of anger, which is so much a part of our psychological discourse, be it moral or cognitive. The last chapter, Spiritual and Bodily Exercise: The Religious Significance of Zhu Xi s Reading Methods, by Peng Guoxiang, argues that Zhu s engagement with texts is anchored in the ultimate goal of moral self-cultivation, such that reading is never merely a disembodied theoretical discursive exercise but an experience that requires and eventuates in the reader s indwelling and realization of the truths encased in words, which is Confucian religiosity in a nutshell. Jones and He have given us a well-curated and well-conceived collective study of Zhu Xi, making the volume a place of profit not only for those already persuaded by the gravity of the subject matter but also for those who are looking for a way into the Song master s ideas and the ambient world of Neo-Confucian thought. No doubt other works will continue to return to Zhu Xi, but their journeys must go through the interpretive territories of this very compilation. Theories of Truth in Chinese Philosophy: A Comparative Approach. By Alexus Mc- Leod. London: Rowman and Littlefield International, 2016. Pp. 197. Paper $39.95, isbn 978-1-78348-345-7. Reviewed by Frank Saunders Jr. University of Hong Kong Frank.Saunders.Jr@outlook.com Did ancient Chinese philosophers offer theories of truth? Some scholars hold that they did not. Alexus McLeod s Theories of Truth in Chinese Philosophy: A Comparative Approach offers an ambitious response to these scholars by arguing that ancient Chinese philosophers both employed multiple truth concepts and offered theories of truth. McLeod begins with a discussion of the relationship between truth and philosophy followed by a critical discussion of the interpretive debate over the status of truth in ancient China (Introduction; chap. 1). He then offers novel interpretations of early Chinese philosophical texts ranging from the Warring States period to the Han dynasty that he believes display a theoretical interest in truth (chaps. 2 6). Overall, McLeod s two best-supported claims are (1) that ancient Chinese philosophers both had and used terms that assessed the semantic adequacy (i.e., truth) of language and therefore count as truth concepts (pp. 18 20), and (2) that an interest in the pragmatic adequacy of language did not prevent ancient Chinese thinkers from having a pragmatic theory of truth (pp. 16 18, 64 66). The first point he argues for 324 Philosophy East & West Volume 68, Number 1 January 2018 324 327 2018 by University of Hawai i Press

primarily by citing examples from the Lunyu, Mencius, Xunzi, Lüshi chunqiu, and Lunheng, while the second one he argues for using Mohist writings. This review will focus on the first point, since it makes up the majority of the book. McLeod begins by contending that the concept of truth, as well as a number of related categories, is essential to any project of intellectual production (p. x), and is therefore important in ancient Chinese thought (pp. ix xv, 33 34). He worries that the scholars he criticizes primarily Hansen and Hall and Ames who see philosophers in ancient China as either lacking or uninterested in the concept of truth, rely upon narrow and Western-centric conceptions of truth, as well as monolithic views of ancient Chinese thought (pp. 21 26, 64 65). According to McLeod, since truth is a universal philosophical concept, we should expect that ancient Chinese philosophers utilized and theorized about it. However, in offering his critique and alternative, McLeod replaces his opponents generalizations about Chinese thought with an even more ambitious generalization about all philosophy, which he then uses to guide his interpretations. McLeod therefore adopts a methodology of positing a priori axioms and interpreting texts in accordance with them, which raises serious hermeneutical challenges, as he thereby encloses himself in a narrow interpretive space without room to adequately consider alternative interpretations. For example, against Hall and Ames claim that in ancient Chinese philosophy there was no appearance-reality distinction a distinction that McLeod holds is deeply related to the concept of truth McLeod cites the butterfly dream story from Book 2 of the Zhuangzi (pp. 23 25). He argues that since the story explicitly concerns the appearance-reality distinction, it would have had no intelligible dialectical context unless there was an appearance-reality distinction in the discourse already. However, rather than use textual evidence from the dialectical context and secondary literature to support his view, McLeod argues that the necessity of the appearance-reality distinction guarantees that his interpretation is sound. It does not, though. Interpretations that do not prioritize the concepts of appearance and reality may do a better job of explaining this text 1 as well as more general early Chinese theories of cognition, perception, knowledge, and error. 2 Alternative interpretations take the point of the passage to be that individual perspectives are irreducibly plural and limited, so no one perspective can legitimately claim normative or epistemic priority over another. These and similar interpretations still explain the text s main worry as epistemic uncertainty, but of a different kind than that arising from the appearance-reality distinction. Indeed, in spite of his arguments that scholars such as Hansen or Hall and Ames may neglect the tradition s philosophical insights by denying that it utilizes concepts such as truth, McLeod does not consider whether these scholars instead point out the possibility of a rich philosophical discourse based in different but intelligible fundamental concepts, methods, and concerns. This is an exciting prospect even if it does not utilize concepts many of us consider fundamental. Methodologically, the book suffers from resisting this possibility because of McLeod s convictions about the concept of truth. This problem manifests itself regularly in McLeod s interpretations of texts, which are often grammatically unsound or less persuasive than alternatives that he does not Book Reviews 325

consider. His interpretations of texts that mention the word shi 實 ( stuff / objects ) is particularly worrying given its importance to his thesis. Early in the book, McLeod introduces the idea that shi is the late Han dynasty thinker Wang Chong s truth concept, and then infers from historical continuity that shi must have functioned similarly during the Warring States period (pp. 10, 16, 20). However, on plausible readings of a number of important passages McLeod works with, the connection between shi and truth is difficult to motivate. For example, McLeod translates Mencius 4B17 as, Words without shi are not auspicious. The fruit (shi) of not being auspicious is obscuration of the fittingness of the sages activity (p. 54). McLeod understands shi as a property of a statement (yan 言 ) that has some kind of positive value.... [T]his certainly shows that early Chinese thought, by the time of Mengzi, has the ability to express a truth property as belonging to assertoric linguistic entities (p. 54). However, a more natural understanding of shi in this context would be simply that it is what names or statements refer to, or, as the Later Mohists defined it, what is called/deemed ( 所謂 ) (Canons A81). In context, statements without stuff (shi) probably refers to nonsense, empty speech, exaggeration, overstatement, or even failing to live up to what one says rather than false statements. In any case, I see no compelling reason to read shi here as a property of yan. McLeod s discussion of shi in the Xunzi is similarly forced. For example, he translates a passage from Xunzi, Book 22, as Names are without intrinsic connection to reality (shi). Agreement on them is made through fiat concerning reality (shi). When there is agreement, they are established, and customs are completed, this is called giving reality (shi) to names ( 名無固實, 約之以命實, 約定俗成, 謂之實名 ) (p. 96; my parentheses). McLoed s readings of 固實 as intrinsic connection to reality and 約之以命實 as agreement on them is made through fiat concerning reality are not grammatically justified by the source text. On a safer parsing, we should translate this passage as Names have no inherent stuff (shi); we agree on them in order to name stuff; agreements being settled and customs formed call them the names of stuff. Though McLeod discusses English-language secondary literature to support his interpretation, his argument suffers for not explaining why he rejects a more grammatically plausible reading like this one. While I disagree with McLeod s understanding of shi in the Warring States period, McLeod s strongest example of an early Chinese philosopher interested in truth-like concepts is the Han dynasty thinker Wang Chong. This chapter (chap. 6) argues that the close connection between shi 實 and both the normative concept of shi 是 ( this / right ) and the descriptive concept ran 然 ( so ) in Wang Chong is evidence that he conceived of shi as a second-order pluralist truth concept (pp. 158 164). While this chapter cites the most primary source material that supports McLeod s interpretation, there is still a sense that McLeod is translating the concept of truth into the text by translating shi as truth at the expense of other interpretations. Consider his translation of 實 [ 事 ] 不能快意... 是故才能之士, 好談論者, 增益實事 : The truth (shi) isn t easily [or quickly] believed.... This is why scholars with talent, who enjoy discussion, add things to and exaggerate the truth (shi 實 ) about 326 Philosophy East & West

affairs (p. 154). First, the version of the sentence McLeod discusses has a typographical error. The first 事 (bracketed above) is omitted in McLeod s version, so to discuss 實 on its own in this passage is a mistake, since the combination 實事 appears twice in the original sentence. In any case, McLeod s translation of the combination is forced. The grammar of the combination is more likely to be a modifying adjective, 實 ( genuine, real ), in front of a noun, 事 ( affairs, things ), rather than two nouns ( the truth about affairs ). A safer reading of the combination is affairs ( 事 ) as they really are ( 實 ), or just reality. The relationship between reality and truth ought to be close, but the grammatical subject here is not a true statement, but is rather affairs ( 事 ). On a plausible, alternative reading, then, we get Reality is unable to be easily apprehended.... [T]his is why talented and able scholars who are fond of debate add to and exaggerate reality. Indeed, in other cases where McLeod translates shi as truth, it seems that reality or genuineness would work just fine, and it is not clear to me what would be lost (pp. 153, 160). In spite of what I take to be its methodological shortcomings, McLeod s book raises some of the deepest methodological issues in comparative philosophy. In particular it highlights the crucial question of how different we ought to expect conceptual frameworks to be from our own. For example, where shi does seem to have some kind of positive value when connected to statements in the appropriate way, ought we consider it a different version of a more general and basic concept of truth, or a concept all its own that has some similarities with but also differs from the concept of truth? More generally, on what grounds do we choose to see a concept as a different version of the same concept, or a numerically different but similar concept? Although I do not think that McLeod successfully answers these questions here, this work certainly forces the reader to think long and hard about them for herself. Notes I would like to thank Chris Fraser and Loy Hui-Chieh for comments on previous drafts of this review. 1 Tim Connolly, Perspectivism as a Way of Knowing in the Zhuangzi, Dao 10 (2011): 487 505. 2 Chris Fraser, Knowledge and Error in Early Chinese Thought, Dao 10 (2011): 127 148. Book Reviews 327