Análisis Filosófico ISSN: Sociedad Argentina de Análisis Filosófico Argentina

Similar documents
What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

The Semantic Significance of Frege s Puzzle

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Two-Dimensional Semantics the Basics

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Is Hegel s Logic Logical?

On Recanati s Mental Files

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Introduction. Fiora Salis University of Lisbon

The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1

An autonomist view on the ethical criticism of architecture

Reviewed by Max Kölbel, ICREA at Universitat de Barcelona

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

REFERENTS AND FIXING REFERENCE 1

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN:

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Department of American Studies M.A. thesis requirements

The Debate on Research in the Arts

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

THE PROPOSITIONAL CHALLENGE TO AESTHETICS

Nissim Francez: Proof-theoretic Semantics College Publications, London, 2015, xx+415 pages

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

Replies to the Critics

The Influence of Chinese and Western Culture on English-Chinese Translation

LOGICO-SEMANTIC ASPECTS OF TRUTHFULNESS

Giving Reasons, A Contribution to Argumentation Theory

Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates Republic Symposium Republic Phaedrus Phaedrus), Theaetetus

Instantiation and Characterization: Problems in Lowe s Four-Category Ontology

Types of perceptual content

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Holism, Concept Individuation, and Conceptual Change

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

Abstract Several accounts of the nature of fiction have been proposed that draw on speech act

Predication and Ontology: The Categories

A Meta-Theoretical Basis for Design Theory. Dr. Terence Love We-B Centre School of Management Information Systems Edith Cowan University

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Composition, Counterfactuals, Causation

IN DEFENSE OF ESSENTIALISM 1. L. A. Paul University of Arizona Australian National University/RSSS

Categories and Schemata

In Parts of Animals I 1 (and elsewhere) Aristotle makes it clear that his goal in the study of nature is a

Quine s Two Dogmas of Empiricism. By Spencer Livingstone

Kant IV The Analogies The Schematism updated: 2/2/12. Reading: 78-88, In General

Logic and argumentation techniques. Dialogue types, rules

CRITICAL STUDIES/BOOK REVIEWS

The Philosophy of Language. Frege s Sense/Reference Distinction

The Prenective View of propositional content

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

ABELARD: THEOLOGIA CHRISTIANA

Cyclic vs. circular argumentation in the Conceptual Metaphor Theory ANDRÁS KERTÉSZ CSILLA RÁKOSI* In: Cognitive Linguistics 20-4 (2009),

Kripke, Chalmers and the Immediate Phenomenal Quality of Pain

TRUTH AND CIRCULAR DEFINITIONS

BOOK REVIEW. William W. Davis

Virtue Theory and Exemplars

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

Lecture 10 Popper s Propensity Theory; Hájek s Metatheory

Humanities Learning Outcomes

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

On Meaning. language to establish several definitions. We then examine the theories of meaning

The (Lack of) Evidence for the Kuhnian Image of Science: A Reply to Arnold and Bryant

On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Digital Images in Mobile Communication as Cool Media

The ambiguity of definite descriptions

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

MONOTONE AMAZEMENT RICK NOUWEN

Lecture 24: Motivating Modal Logic, Translating into It

in this web service Cambridge University Press

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

The red apple I am eating is sweet and juicy. LOCKE S EMPIRICAL THEORY OF COGNITION: THE THEORY OF IDEAS. Locke s way of ideas

The Art of Time Travel: A Bigger Picture

Beyond A- and B-Time Reconsidered

Issue 5, Summer Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Moral Judgment and Emotions

Haecceities: Essentialism, Identity, and Abstraction

Perception and Mind-Dependence Lecture 3

WITHOUT QUALIFICATION: AN INQUIRY INTO THE SECUNDUM QUID

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

Revitalising Old Thoughts: Class diagrams in light of the early Wittgenstein

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Aristotle s Metaphysics

SAINSBURY ON THINKING ABOUT AN OBJECT

days of Saussure. For the most, it seems, Saussure has rightly sunk into

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals

Partial and Paraconsistent Approaches to Future Contingents in Tense Logic

Peirce s Final Account of Signs and The Philosophy of Language ALBERT ATKIN

International Journal of Library and Information Studies. An User Satisfaction about Library Resources and Services: A Study

Identity and Individuation

Transcription:

Análisis Filosófico ISSN: 0326-1301 af@sadaf.org.ar Sociedad Argentina de Análisis Filosófico Argentina ZERBUDIS, EZEQUIEL INTRODUCTION: GENERAL TERM RIGIDITY AND DEVITT S RIGID APPLIERS Análisis Filosófico, vol. XXIX, núm. 2, noviembre-, 2009, pp. 193-199 Sociedad Argentina de Análisis Filosófico Buenos Aires, Argentina Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=340030300007 How to cite Complete issue More information about this article Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Scientific Information System Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative

SECOND SYMPOSIUM GENERAL TERMS: THE RIGID/NON-RIGID DISTINCTION INTRODUCTION: GENERAL TERM RIGIDITY AND DEVITT S RIGID APPLIERS* EZEQUIEL ZERBUDIS Universidad de Buenos Aires - ANPCyT - GAF ezerbu@yahoo.com Abstract In this essay, I present a problem that originates in Kripke s contention, in Naming and Necessity, that natural kind terms are rigid, namely, the problem of how to understand the notion of rigidity when it is applied to general terms. I also give an account, in a principled way, of the main theoretical options that seem to be available to solve that problem, and sketch the main features of Michael Devitt s proposal against that background. KEY WORDS: General term; Designation; Rigidity; Essence. Resumen En este trabajo, hago una presentación de un problema que Kripke deja planteado al sostener, en El nombrar y la necesidad, que los términos de género natural son rígidos, a saber, el de cómo debería ser entendida la noción de rigidez cuando ésta es aplicada a los términos generales. Asimismo, trazo un panorama de las distintas opciones teóricas disponibles, y presento las tesis centrales de la propuesta de Michael Devitt a la luz de este marco. PALABRAS CLAVE: Término general; Designación; Rigidez; Esencia. 1. In this introduction, I would like to present the general background against which the discussion that will take up in the following pages is to be understood. I will try to do so by presenting the main features of Devitt s conception of Rigid Application, which will be the main topic of these discussions, and by placing it in the context of the other proposals * I would like to thank Michael Devitt and Eleonora Orlando for comments on an earlier version of the present introduction. Research leading to this paper has been partly funded by the CONICET and the University of Geneva (Coimbra Scholarship). ANÁLISIS FILOSÓFICO XXIX Nº 2 - ISSN 0326-1301 (noviembre 2009) 193-199

194 EZEQUIEL ZERBUDIS that have been presented to try to solve the same problem it tries to solve, namely, that of making sense of Kripke s contention, made in the third of the lectures that were to become Naming and Necessity, that not only proper names, but also some general terms, in particular natural kind ones, should be taken to be rigid (cf. Kripke 1980, pp. 115-140, and particularly p. 136, where he explicitly affirms of some natural kind terms that they are rigid). As is widely known, and I have already suggested, this Kripkean contention has been thought, ever since he first presented it, to be problematic. And it seems that one of the main reasons why commentators have thought so lies in the fact that it is not clear how to put the two following features together: on the one hand, the fact that the definition of the notion of rigidity originally given by Kripke seems to involve, in an essential way, the notion of designation; on the other hand, the fact that natural kind terms are usually taken to be predicative expressions (that is, either predicates or general terms), and that it is not at all clear whether, and in what sense, the notion of designation could be used to characterize their behaviour. That the notion of designation is essential to the original definition of rigidity may be seen from the fact that what Kripke defines is, indeed, the notion of a rigid designator: Let s call something a rigid designator if in every possible world it designates the same object, a non-rigid or accidental designator if that is not the case (1980, p. 48). This being so, the first issue that we must face in order to examine whether, and how, the notion of rigidity can be extended to predicative expressions consists in trying to determine whether, and in what sense, the notion of designation can be used to characterize the semantic behaviour of such expressions. 1 The reason why this is somewhat problematic is closely related to the fact that there seem to be at least two different kinds of relation to non-linguistic items that general terms could 1 I use designation in a rather broad way, as a word that applies to any kind of semantically relevant relation that might take place between linguistic expressions and appropriate items in the world, while I reserve reference to describe the more specific kind of relation that is supposed to take place between, say, names, on the one hand, and, on the other hand, the objects they stand for. It should be noted here that such a terminology is by no means universally accepted; Devitt himself seems to favour a very different use of the terms, according to which, for instance, reference stands for the more general notion we called designation (cf. Devitt 1998).

INTRODUCTION: GENERAL TERM RIGIDITY AND DEVITT S RIGID APPLIERS 195 be said to stand in, both of which could be considered as semantically relevant designation relations: on the one hand, (1) there is the relation to the properties that they are supposed to express and ascribe to the individuals they are applied to; on the other hand, (2) there is the relation to the individuals that these expressions are applied to truly. Moreover, those individuals can be taken (2a) to form a set, that is, they can be thought of as a single individual constituting the extension of the general term, or (2b) as just as many separate individuals the predicate is true of. So, for instance, if we take the predicative expression red as an example, we might say (1) that it expresses the property of being red, (2a) that it has as its extension the set of red things, and (2b) that it is true of each of the particular red individuals. Now, it is possible to understand the different proposals that have been made in the literature concerning how to extend Kripke s notion of rigidity to general terms as arising from favouring one or the other of those semantic relations as the notion of designation relevant for an evaluation of their rigidity. It is reasonable to expect to find, accordingly, three different proposals corresponding to the three semantic relations we have distinguished above. And indeed we find, in the first place, some authors that defend a view, the so-called identity of designation view, which ascribes rigidity (or non-rigidity) to predicative expressions by examining the way they relate to the properties that they are supposed to express and that, according to the upholders of the proposal, they should also be taken to designate (cf. the relation (1) we introduced above). 2 According to this kind of proposal, then, a general term is characterized as rigid if and only if it expresses (or designates) the same property in all possible worlds. A second proposal that has been defended in the literature evaluates the rigidity (or non-rigidity) of a predicative expression by examining the relation that obtains between the term and each of the individuals it applies to (cf. the relation (2b) we introduced above). According to this kind of proposal, which can be characterized as the essentialist view, a predicative expression is to be considered as rigid in case it applies to an object as though it expressed an essential property of that object, that is, in case it applies to it in all the counterfactual situations in which it exists (we will see a more formal 2 I shall assume here that kinds are no more than a special class of properties. The most important upholders of identity of designation views include Linsky (1984), LaPorte (2000), Salmon (2005) and López de Sa (2008a, 2008b). 3 Devitt (2005) and Gómez-Torrente (2006) have presented the most fully developed versions of essentialist views of predicative expression rigidity.

196 EZEQUIEL ZERBUDIS characterization of this requirement below). 3 Besides, what we have said above seems to make room for a third kind of proposal, namely, one that ascribes rigidity (or non-rigidity) to predicative expressions by examining the relations that such terms have to their extensions (considered as sets). But this last position has been very early dismissed as a non-starter, and for obvious reasons: no general term, but those for kinds of necessary existents, would come out rigid on that account, as the extension of most general terms varies from world to world; accordingly, we may safely leave that option aside. Finally, we could discern in the relevant literature a further position that consists in simply denying that the notion of rigidity can have any meaningful application to general terms, either because there would seem to be no way of deciding which of the above-mentioned proposals should be regarded as the genuine extension of rigidity, or because it is thought that all of them are objectionable on other grounds (for instance, because they fail to make a theoretically interesting, non-trivial, distinction). 4 2. The proposal that Devitt presented in his (2005) paper Rigid Application belongs in the group of the essentialist views. As we said earlier, the intuitive idea behind those proposals is that a rigid predicative expression should be understood as an essentialist one, that is, as an expression that behaves as if it stood for a property that is essential to anything that has it. But Devitt seems to prefer to avoid the talk of properties, let alone essential ones. For him, a general term (the kind of predicative expression for which he defines the notion) is to count as rigid if it is a rigid applier, a notion he defines as follows: [A] general term F is a rigid applier if and only if it is such that if it applies to an object in any possible world, then it applies to that object in every possible world in which the object exists (2005, p. 146). In the paper, Devitt tries to defend his view against two objections raised against it by Schwartz (2002). The first one amounts to the claim that any notion of rigidity that fails to distinguish natural kind terms from all other general terms should be considered as theoretically useless; the second is that a proposal such as Devitt s fails in fact to distinguish between natural kind terms and all other general terms. With regard to the first charge, Devitt thinks that it is a mistake to suppose that the main work of a rigidity distinction should be that of 4 A prominent sceptic is Soames; see his (2002).

INTRODUCTION: GENERAL TERM RIGIDITY AND DEVITT S RIGID APPLIERS 197 providing a principled way of distinguishing between natural kind terms and all other general terms. He urges us instead to take a look at the more clear case of singular terms to see what kind of work the notion of rigidity does for them, and suggests as a methodological criterion that any acceptable extension of rigidity to general terms should be one that played an analogous role. Devitt then finds that there is, on the one hand, some primary work that the notion of rigidity does for singular terms, which consists in identifying terms that are not synonymous with descriptions and hence refuting description theories of meaning for those terms (2005, p. 144). On the other hand, he finds that there are four pieces of secondary work that the notion of rigidity is expected to perform, namely, explaining four different contrasts that are found in the modal behaviour of those terms. The contrasts that are to be explained by rigidity are the following: the fact that, while the truth of a sentence with a name in subject position depends, in different possible worlds, on what happens with a single object in all of them (namely, that rigidly designated by the name), the truth of a sentence with a description in subject position may depend on what happens with different objects in different worlds; the fact that, while a sentence like The last great philosopher of Antiquity might not have been the last great philosopher of Antiquity has a true reading, this is not so with Aristotle might not have been Aristotle ; the fact that, while It might have been the case that the last great philosopher of Antiquity was not a philosopher has two non-equivalent readings (depending on the relative scope of the modal operator and the first description), this is not so if the first description is replaced by Aristotle ; and finally, the fact that, while true identity sentences between rigid names are necessary, this is not so with identities that include non-rigid singular terms. As we said, Devitt thinks that it would certainly constitute a good reason to accept a specific notion of rigidity for general terms if its adoption enabled us to explain some phenomena that take place in the case of those terms (namely, some contrasts between natural and nominal kind terms) just as the adoption of a notion of rigidity for singular terms did enable us to explain some allegedly parallel phenomena taking place in the case of them (namely, some contrasts between names and descriptions). And he thinks moreover that his preferred account of rigidity is in fact successful as regards this requirement, except for the fact that it cannot perform the last of the four explanatory tasks which are the general term analogues of those we already mentioned concerning singular terms. For instance, in relation to the primary work, he says that, while gold does not fail to apply to actual pieces of gold with respect to counterfactual situations

198 EZEQUIEL ZERBUDIS in which they exist but have a different appearance, the typical descriptive predicates true of pieces of gold in the actual world could in some cases fail to do so therefore showing that the term and the description aren t synonymous. Besides, he presents some other examples to show that his account of rigidity also explains the phenomena alluded to in the first three pieces of secondary work. I will like to point out that, although Devitt is right that his preferred view only fails concerning the necessitation of true identification statements, it seems to me that he has somehow downgraded this failure: from my perspective, the phenomenon of the necessitations seems significant to Kripke s whole project and may deserve to be given more weight. 5 We could take the second criticism made by Schwartz, as I think Devitt himself does in the paper, as saying that, no matter what we end up thinking concerning the theoretical work that a rigidity distinction should be able to perform, Devitt s proposal fails concerning the demand, that it would be reasonable to make on independent grounds, to the effect that rigid general terms should (approximately) coincide with the class of natural kind terms (what I will call the condition of extensional adequacy). I will not deal with this problem in any detail here because I will do so below, in my contribution to the present symposium, but I would like to draw attention to the fact that, contrary to what some other authors have done, namely, refusing to accept as valid the very condition of extensional adequacy, 6 Devitt addresses the objection and tries to defend his view against it, thereby apparently assuming that the satisfaction of the condition should be taken, if not as mandatory, at least as desirable for any conception of rigidity for general terms. *** I have tried to present here, then, in a brief outline, the main solutions that have been offered to the problem of how to extend the notion of rigidity to predicative expressions, together with the main theses defended by Devitt on the topic. Of course, I could not address most of the 5 Gómez-Torrente (2006) has recently presented a defence of the essentialist proposal in which he tries to show that an essentialist conception of predicate rigidity would be able to explain the necessity of true identification sentences or, at least, that it could explain such necessities to the same extent than the standard conception of singular term rigidity explains the necessity of true identities. 6 I think here mainly of some identity of designation theorists, such as LaPorte (2000), Salmon (2005) and López de Sa (2008a).

INTRODUCTION: GENERAL TERM RIGIDITY AND DEVITT S RIGID APPLIERS 199 many interesting issues he raises in his paper in this introduction; some of them, in any case, will be given some attention in the discussion that follows. But I hope that what I have said is enough to help a reader who is not acquainted with the present debate to better understand the papers that follow. References Devitt, M. (1998), Reference, in Craig, E. (ed.), Routledge Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, London, Routledge. (2005), Rigid Application, Philosophical Studies, 125, pp. 139-165. Gómez-Torrente, M. (2006), Rigidity and Essentiality, Mind, 115, pp. 227-259. Kripke, S. (1980), Naming and Necessity, Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press. LaPorte, J. (2000), Rigidity and Kind, Philosophical Studies, 97, pp. 293-316. López de Sa, D. (2008a), The Over-Generalization Problem: Predicates Rigidly Signifying the Unnatural, Synthese, 163, pp. 263-272. (2008b), Rigidity for Predicates and the Trivialization Problem, Philosophers Imprint, 8, Nº 1. http://www.philosophersimprint.org/008001. Linsky, B. (1984), General Terms as Designators, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 65, pp. 259-276. Salmon, N. (2005), Are General Terms Rigid?, Linguistics and Philosophy, 28, pp. 117-134. Schwartz, S. (2002), Kinds, General Terms and Rigidity: A Reply to LaPorte, Philosophical Studies, 109, pp. 265-277. Soames, S. (2002), Beyond Rigidity, Oxford, Oxford University Press.