Kuhn s normal and revolutionary science

Similar documents
HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Introduction to the Philosophy of Science

Four kinds of incommensurability. Reason, Relativism, and Reality Spring 2005

Thomas Kuhn's "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions"

8/28/2008. An instance of great change or alteration in affairs or in some particular thing. (1450)

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Introduction to the Philosophy of Science

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE

Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology

Scientific Revolutions as Events: A Kuhnian Critique of Badiou

The UCD community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters!

Kuhn. History and Philosophy of STEM. Lecture 6

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

Words or Worlds: The Metaphysics within Kuhn s Picture of. Science. Justin Price

IX. The Nature and Necessity of Scientific Revolutions

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

Kuhn and the Structure of Scientific Revolutions. How does one describe the process of science as a human endeavor? How does an

Modeling Scientific Revolutions: Gärdenfors and Levi on the Nature of Paradigm Shifts

The Structure of Scientific Revolutions

The Structure of Scientific Revolutions


Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

THE STRUCTURE OF SCIENTIFIC REVOLUTIONS

In retrospect: The Structure of Scientific Revolutions

Conceptual Change, Relativism, and Rationality

Science: A Greatest Integer Function A Punctuated, Cumulative Approach to the Inquisitive Nature of Science

Relativism and the Social Construction of Science: Kuhn, Lakatos, Feyerabend

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Thomas Kuhn. 1. Life and Career

observation and conceptual interpretation

The (Lack of) Evidence for the Kuhnian Image of Science: A Reply to Arnold and Bryant

Thomas Kuhn s Concept of Incommensurability and the Stegmüller/Sneed Program as a Formal Approach to that Concept

Is There Anything Wrong with Thomas Kuhn? Markus Arnold, University of Klagenfurt

Incommensurability and the Bonfire of the Meta-Theories: Response to Mizrahi Lydia Patton, Virginia Tech

Kuhn and coherentist epistemology

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

TEST BANK. Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues

AN ABSTRACT OF THE THESIS OF

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

Triune Continuum Paradigm and Problems of UML Semantics

WHY STUDY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY? 1

THE LANGUAGE OF SCIENCE: MEANING VARIANCE AND THEORY COMPARISON HOWARD SANKEY *

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

Kuhn and the Question of Pursuit Worthiness

The Epistemological Status of Theoretical Simplicity YINETH SANCHEZ

Can Kuhn s Taxonomic Incommensurability Be an Image of Science?

Intersubjectivity and physical laws in post-kantian theory of knowledge: Natorp and Cassirer Scott Edgar October 2014.

Thomas S. Kuhn ( )

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

Kant on wheels. Available online: 24 Jun 2010

Thomas Kuhn and Perspectival Realism. A thesis presented to. the faculty of. the College of Arts and Sciences of Ohio University

SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE AND RELIGIOUS RELATION TO REALITY

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Review Articles KUHN*S SECOND THOUGHTS. Brit. J. Phil. Set. aa (1971), Printed in Great Britain 287

1 Kuhn on Specialization. dr. Vincenzo Politi

Architecture is epistemologically

Philosophy and History of Science: Beyond the Kuhnian Paradigm. Hans Radder*

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

AN ALTERNATIVE TO KITCHER S THEORY OF CONCEPTUAL PROGRESS AND HIS ACCOUNT OF THE CHANGE OF THE GENE CONCEPT. Ingo Brigandt

Is perspectivism realistic enough for science? Ed Brandon

INTRODUCTION TO THE POLITICS OF SOCIAL THEORY

INCOMMENSURABILITY AND RELATED MATTERS

An Alternative to Kitcher s Theory of Conceptual Progress and His Account of the Change of the Gene Concept

Aristotle. Aristotle. Aristotle and Plato. Background. Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle and Plato

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress: Reduction Between Incommensurable Theories in a Rigid Structuralist Framework

Normal Science and Normal Kuhn.

Normative and Positive Economics

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

PHILOSOPHY. Grade: E D C B A. Mark range: The range and suitability of the work submitted

Rereading Kuhn REVIEW ARTICLE. Jouni-Matti Kuukkanen

(as methodology) are not always distinguished by Steward: he says,

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

Caught in the Middle. Philosophy of Science Between the Historical Turn and Formal Philosophy as Illustrated by the Program of Kuhn Sneedified

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique of Pure Reason for Describing Epistemological Trends in IS

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History

University of Bristol - Explore Bristol Research

Abstract. Background and Rationale

CRITIQUE OF PARSONS AND MERTON

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

Monadology and Music 2: Leibniz s Demon

Challenging the View That Science is Value Free

On The Search for a Perfect Language

Meaning Change in the Context of Thomas S. Kuhn s Philosophy. Jouni-Matti Kuukkanen

REVIEW. Patrick Enfield

Part IV Social Science and Network Theory

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Homework Due Thursday, Oct. 23. Please type your responses on a separate sheet.

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

Feminism, Underdetermination, and Values in Science

Transcription:

Kuhn s normal and revolutionary science Philosophy of Science (106a/124), Topic 4, 24 October 2017 Adam Caulton (adam.caulton@philosophy.ox.ac.uk) 1 A role for history Previous philosophers of science had emphasized a sharp separation between history of science and the philosophical theory of science (contexts of discovery and justification again). Their methodology: formulate a theory of science in particular, the justification of scientific claims with little emphasis on what scientists actually do or have done. Kuhn s methodology: provide a theorised account of science is actually done, based on a study of crucial episodes from its history (in particular: 18th Century Chemistry and Physics from the Early Modern Period to the 20th Century). This entails an indispensable role for history of science in the philosophy of science. And (Kuhn believed) elements of scientific practice that are key to science s success had been missed by ahistorical accounts, such as inductivism, hypothetico-deductivism and falsificationism. 1.1 The historiographic orthodoxy [A] concept of science drawn from [orthodox histories of science] is no more likely to fit the enterprise that produced them than an image of a national culture drawn from a tourist brochure or a language text. (p. 1) Kuhn was keen to avoid Whiggish history and the illusion that developments in the history of science had been inevitable. According to Kuhn, the old historiographic orthodoxy held that the historian of science had two main tasks: (i) to determine by whom and when each contemporary scientific fact, law & theory was discovered or invented; and (ii) to describe & explain the congeries of error, myth, and superstition that inhibited the more rapid accumulation of the constituents of the modern science text. This entails an explanatory asymmetry: success is explained by epistemic factors; failure is explained by social factors. Kuhn rejected this asymmetry. (This rejection is also the keystone of the strong programme in the sociology of scientific knowledge, associated with, amongst others, David Bloor, Barry Barnes and Harry Collins.) 1.2 The historiographic revolution Rather than seeking the permanent contributions of an older science to our present vantage, [we] attempt to display the historical integrity of that science in its own time. (p. 3) E.g. Not: What relation did Galileo s views have to modern science? But rather: What relation did Galileo s views have to his contemporaries? Or: What made Galilean dynamics more plausible than Aristotelian dynamics to his contemporaries? Two lessons of the historiographic revolution: 1. Under-determination of theory by data & method. The insufficiency of methodological directives... to dictate a unique substantive conclusion to many sorts of scientific questions. 2. Indispensability of auxiliary elements. The auxiliary elements that go into determining a unique view of the world are indispensable to the success of science: they ground and guide progress. (n.b. Importance of consensus.) 1

2 Three phases of science 1. Immature science. No, or very little, agreement over fundamentals; a plurality of different standards and worldviews. 2. Normal science. [R]esearch firmly based upon one or more past scientific achievements [this is one precisification of Kuhn s notion of paradigm ], achievements that some particular scientific community acknowledges for a time as supplying the foundation for its further practice. 3. Revolutionary science. A wholesale shift in: which problems are available to scientific scrutiny (what is worth doing); standards for legitimate solutions; the world in which scientific work is done (i.e. the dominant Weltanschauung); the impression of previous theories (e.g. the reasons widely cited for their success). (For 2 vs. 3, think e.g.: Le Verrier and Neptune vs. Einstein and Mercury.) 3 Paradigms & normal science 3.1 Paradigms Normal science is characterized by research done in a paradigm, or collection of paradigms. Paradigm (at least before Kuhn) means an example, or template; e.g. grammatical paradigms. For Kuhn it means: a scientific achievement that serves to shape future theoretical development. A better example than grammatical paradigms might be case law, as opposed to statutory law. Normal science consists in the actualization of [the] promise [of early achievements], an actualization achieved by extending the knowledge of these facts that the paradigm displays as particularly revealing, by increasing the extent of the match between those facts and the paradigm s predictions, and by further articulation of the paradigm itself. (p. 24) Kuhn also claims that paradigms structure evidence: which facts are particularly revealing, and how the facts are to be interpreted. ( Kant on wheels Peter Lipton) 3.2 The advantage of paradigms Normal science is characterized by wide consensus on the prevailing paradigm or paradigms. This consensus is not easily challenged indeed it partly constitutes community membership. (Contrast with falsificationism.) This permits specialization. By focusing attention upon a small range of relatively esoteric problems, the paradigm forces scientists to investigate some part of nature in a detail and depth that would otherwise be unimaginable. (p. 25) New paradigms are associated with the formation of new specialized journals and societies even (sometimes) with a new name (e.g. bioinformatics, nanoscience, quantum information theory ). Examples given by Kuhn include: Aristotle s theory of motion; Ptolemy s computations of planetary orbits; Lavoisier s application of the balance; and Maxwell s mathematization of the electromagentic field. 2

3.3 Experimental work during normal science The collection of facts that are (according to the paradigm) particularly revealing of the nature of things. (E.g.: stellar positions & magnitudes, orbits, specific gravities, conductivities, combustion & combining weights, boiling & melting points, structural formulae,... ) The collection of facts that are easy to compare with predictions. Further articulation of the paradigm. Paradigms help here in narrowing down what there is to look for. (E.g.: resolving ambiguities; measuring physical constants; formulating mini-laws, such as Boyle s Law or Coulomb s Law.) 3.4 Theoretical work during normal science Generating predictions of factual information of intrinsic value (e.g. mass of Earth; moment of inertia of a cube; the electron s magnetic moment). Generating predictions for experimental testing. This might be a new application of the paradigm, or an increase in precision of previous applications. It involves designing experiments (guided by the paradigm) and extracting observable predictions (harder than it sounds!) Further articulation of the paradigm. This involves increased rigor of mathematical framework (as with, e.g. the rigorization of the differential calculus and Hamilton-Jacobi theory), and the subsumption of new systems under the prevailing paradigm (e.g. Newtonian point masses continuous fluids). 3.5 Normal science as puzzle-solving Kuhn describes work in a paradigm as puzzle-solving. Why? Puzzles have an assured solution ( unlike cancer or world peace ). Other problems are deemed metaphysical or insoluble. Puzzles are associated with a limited collection of rules, standards and acceptable steps in seeking and appraising a solution. Puzzles are small enough to give individuals a sense of achievement in their careers. 3.6 Paradigms, not rules Lack of a standard interpretation or of an agreed reduction to rules will not prevent a paradigm from guiding research. Normal science can be determined in part by the direct inspection of paradigms, a process that is often aided by but does not depend upon the formulation of rules and assumptions. Indeed, the existence of a paradigm does not even imply that any full set of rules exists. (p. 44) (Compare the later Wittgenstein on game.) Why paradigms and not rules? 1. Rules are hard to discover. 2. Humans (including scientists!) learn by doing, not by internalizing explicit rules. 3. Rules are unnecessary (and even limiting) in times of consensus. 4. Consensus over rules is hard to achieve: paradigms impose milder constraints. Explicit rules tend to be demanded only in cases of strife or disagreement (i.e. just before or during revolutionary science). 3

4 Revolutionary science 4.1 Anomalies & the emergence of scientific discoveries An anomaly is a phenomenon that (at least prima facie) cannot be incorporated into the current paradigm. The appearance of anomalies is the source of new scientific discoveries, whether these anomalies are eventually incorporated into the prevailing paradigm or (otherwise) they lead to a rejection of that paradigm. Discovery commences with the awareness of anomaly, i.e., with the recognition that nature has somehow violated the paradigm-induced expectations that govern normal science. It then continues with a more or less extended exploration of the area of anomaly. And it closes only when the paradigm theory has been adjusted so that the anomalous has become the expected. (p. 53) What has been discovered is understood only after this adjustment. Kuhn uses three main examples: Priestley and Lavoisier on Oxygen (1770s 1820s); Roentgen on X-rays (1895); and Leyden jars & the fluid theory of electromagnetism. 4.2 Crisis & the emergence of scientific theories Crisis arises when the accommodation of anomalies becomes especially difficult or complex especially where that complexity has little benefit elsewhere (cf. Popper s ad hoc modifications). Crisis is characterized by widespread professional dissatisfaction, and a plethora of rival, heterodox theories, resembling pre-paradigm science. (n.b.: Crisis is not defined as preceding a revolution: Kuhn intends his claim that crisis leads to revolution to be empirical; see e.g. p. 90.) Key examples are: phlogistion theory (Priestley, Lavoisier); The Copernican revolution; and ether theory (Maxwell, Fresnel, Lorentz, FitzGerald). 4.3 When does a revolution happen?... [S]cientific revolutions are here taken to be those non-cumulative developmental episodes in which an older paradigm is replaced in whole or in part by an incompatible new one. (p. 92)... [O]nce it has achieved the status of paradigm, a scientific theory is declared invalid only if an alternative candidate is available to take its place. No process yet disclosed by the historical study of scientific development at all resembles the methodological stereotype of falsification by direct comparison with nature (p. 77) The parallel with political revolutions is deliberate: (i) they occur in response to crises, in which the dominant structure is widely believed not to be responsive to felt needs; (ii) they are characterised by a lack of any supra-institutional framework for the adjudication of revolutionary differences ; and (iii) they involve the need to resort to techniques of mass persuasion often including force. According to Kuhn, no compelling argument can be given for abandoning one paradigm in favour of another: it is not a rational process. The best that can be done is for practitioners in a new paradigm to demonstrate practice in the new paradigm, and hope to convert more practitioners. (Later, e.g. Kuhn 1977, Kuhn characterises this as being due to the impossibility of neutrally interpreting and giving appropriate weight to a number of theoretical virtues, such as simplicity, scope and fruitfulness.) 4

5 Science isn t cumulative? 5.1 Newton vs. Einstein But doesn t (e.g.) Einsteinian relativity reproduce the successes of Newton s theory of gravitation? (That is, can t Newtonian predictions be derived from Einstein s theory?) Derivation is possible only in a limited domain of application (e.g. when velocities are very small compared to light; also distances must not be too large). This limitation can be sensibly imposed only in hindsight: the attempt to impose limitations during normal science restricts the progress of normal science. If positivistic restrictions on the range of a theory s legitimate applicability are taken literally, the mechanism that tells the scientific community what problems may lead to to fundamental change must cease to function. And when that occurs, the community will inevitably return to something much like its pre-paradigm state, a condition in which all members practice science but in which their gross product scarcely resembles science at all. Is it really any wonder that the price of significant scientific advance is a commitment that runs the risk of being wrong? (p. 101) The derivation achieved is suspect: we recover the form but not the content of the previous paradigm s laws. This is tied to a holist account of the meaning of scientific terms. Our argument has, of course, explained why Newton s Laws ever seemed to work. In doing so it has justified, say, the automobile driver in acting as though he lived in a Newtonian universe. (p. 102) 5.2 Paradigms as a source of meaning Since new paradigms are born from old ones, they ordinarily incorporate much of the vocabulary and apparatus, both conceptual and manipulative, that the traditional paradigm had previously employed. But they seldom employ these borrowed elements in quite the traditional way. Within the new paradigm, old terms, concepts, and experiments fall into new relationships one with the other. The inevitable result is what we must call, though the term is not quite right, a misunderstanding between the two competing schools. (p. 148) The near-tautologies of a new paradigm may have been near-contradictions in the previous paradigm (e.g.: The Earth moves, Space is curved by the presence of matter ). Kuhn s account of the meaning-giving, or world-structuring, power of paradigms owes much to a holist account of meaning. This account (articulated further in Kuhn 1983) is put under significant pressure by the externalist theories of reference of e.g. Kripke (1980) and Putnam (1975). Kuhn also depends on some rather tenuous analogies (barely described as such) with recently discovered psychological phenomena, such as the Bruner and Postman experiment. 5.3 Paradigms as a source of standards... [T]he case for cumulative development of science s problems and standards is even harder to make than the case for cumulation of theories. The attempt to explain gravity, though fruitfully abandoned by most eighteenth-century scientists, was not directed to an intrinsically illegitimate problem; the objections to innate forces were neither inherently unscientific nor metaphysical in some pejorative sense. There are no external standards to permit a judgment of that sort. (p. 108) 5

No paradigm ever solves all the problems it defines, and no two paradigms leave the same problems unsolved. Associated with the latter is the idea of a Kuhn loss, a problem solved by a defunct paradigm (but many, if not all, purported examples of this are controversial). So a choice of paradigm is, in part, a choice of which problems are most significant. The correctness of that choice has no external criteria: rival paradigms are incommensurable. 5.4 A change of paradigm as a change of world? Examining the record of past research from the vantage of contemporary historiography, the historian of science may be tempted to exclaim that when paradigms change, the world itself changes with them. (p. 111) According to Kuhn, what one directly perceives changes in a paradigm shift: this is, apparently, not merely a change in interpretation. Note that Kuhn rejects the positivists observational/theoretical distinction, and their commitment to a neutral observation language. Despite the analogy with gestalt shifts, paradigm shifts are, for Kuhn, more extreme, since there is no unequivocally stable body of data between paradigms: The operations and measurements that a scientist undertakes in the laboratory are not the given of experience but rather the collected with difficulty. (pp. 125-6) But this is hard to swallow in e.g. the case of Eddington s 1919 expedition to test the general theory of relativity against Newtonian gravitation theory. Kuhn s talk of changing worlds makes it hard to interpret him as giving an almost wholly internalist account of science. Yet in other passages it seems that this is exactly what he aims to do: In the sciences there need not be progress of another sort [than that offered by changes of paradigm]. We may, to be more precise, have to relinquish the notion, explicit or implicit, that changes of paradigm carry scientists and those who learn from them closer to the truth. (p. 169) (Kuhn s account as more properly Darwinian than Popper s falsificationism?) 6 Suggested reading Chalmers, A., What Is This Thing Called Science? (4th Edition; Hackett, 2013), Chs. 8 9. Godfrey-Smith, P., Theory and Reality (University of Chicago Press, 2003), Chs. 5 6. Hoyningen-Huene, P., Kuhn s conception of incommensurability, Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 21 (1990), pp. 481 492. Kuhn, T. S., The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (First Edition, 1962; 50th Anniversary Edition with an Introduction by Ian Hacking, 2012; University of Chicago Press). Kuhn, T. S., Commensurability, Comparability, Communicability, PSA 198: Proceedings of the 1982 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, edited by P. Asquith & T. Nickles (East Lansing MI: Philosophy of Science Association), pp. 669 88. Kuhn, T. S. Objectivity, Value Judgment, and Theory Choice, in his The Essential Tension (University of Chicago Press, 1977), pp. 320 39. Kripke, S., Naming and Necessity (Harvard University Press, 1980). Newton-Smith, W. H., The Rationality of Science (Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1981), Ch. 5. Putnam, H., The meaning of meaning, in his Mind, Language, and Reality: Philosophical Papers Vol. 2 (CUP, 1975). Putnam, H. Reason, Truth and History (CUP, 1981), Chapter 5. 6