The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Similar documents
What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

The UCD community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters!

Conceptual Change, Relativism, and Rationality

Environmental Ethics: From Theory to Practice

Semantic Incommensurability and Scientific Realism. Howard Sankey. University of Melbourne. 1. Background

Sidestepping the holes of holism

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Big Questions in Philosophy. What Is Relativism? Paul O Grady 22 nd Jan 2019

LeBar s Flaccidity: Is there Cause for Concern?

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

COURSE: PHILOSOPHY GRADE(S): NATIONAL STANDARDS: UNIT OBJECTIVES: Students will be able to: STATE STANDARDS:

Caught in the Middle. Philosophy of Science Between the Historical Turn and Formal Philosophy as Illustrated by the Program of Kuhn Sneedified

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Relativism and Reflexivity

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Thomas Kuhn s Concept of Incommensurability and the Stegmüller/Sneed Program as a Formal Approach to that Concept

Logic and argumentation techniques. Dialogue types, rules

Uskali Mäki Putnam s Realisms: A View from the Social Sciences

Chapter One. Introduction to the Dissertation: Philosophy, Developmental Psychology, and Intuition

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

The Concept of Nature

On The Search for a Perfect Language

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

INCOMMENSURABILITY AND RELATED MATTERS

Quine s Two Dogmas of Empiricism. By Spencer Livingstone

Twentieth Excursus: Reference Magnets and the Grounds of Intentionality

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Université Libre de Bruxelles

Argumentation and persuasion

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

Interpretive and Critical Research Traditions

BOOK REVIEWS. University of Southern California. The Philosophical Review, XCI, No. 2 (April 1982)

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

Moral Relativism. Entry for the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. By Max Kölbel

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Kuhn. History and Philosophy of STEM. Lecture 6

Relativism. Maria Baghramian LONDON AND NEW YORK

Realism and Representation: The Case of Rembrandt s

KANTIAN CONCEPTUALISM

Reviewed by Max Kölbel, ICREA at Universitat de Barcelona

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

Kuhn and coherentist epistemology

Humanities Learning Outcomes

Incommensurability and the Bonfire of the Meta-Theories: Response to Mizrahi Lydia Patton, Virginia Tech

Part IV Social Science and Network Theory

Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology

observation and conceptual interpretation

Thomas Szanto: Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes

A PRACTICAL DISTINCTION IN VALUE THEORY: QUALITATIVE AND QUANTITATIVE ACCOUNTS. Galen A. Foresman. A Dissertation

Four Characteristic Research Paradigms

Kant Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics, Preface, excerpts 1 Critique of Pure Reason, excerpts 2 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 9/19/13 12:13 PM

On Recanati s Mental Files

Undercutting the Realism-Irrealism Debate: John Dewey and the Neo-Pragmatists

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

Kant, Peirce, Dewey: on the Supremacy of Practice over Theory

The Culpable Inability Problem for Synchronic and Diachronic Ought Implies Can

What is the Object of Thinking Differently?

Types of perceptual content

Modeling Scientific Revolutions: Gärdenfors and Levi on the Nature of Paradigm Shifts

Constructive mathematics and philosophy of mathematics

Feminism, Underdetermination, and Values in Science

PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology

A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique of Pure Reason for Describing Epistemological Trends in IS

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Bad Art and Good Taste

Categories and Schemata

PHIL/HPS Philosophy of Science Fall 2014

Normal Science and Normal Kuhn.

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Relativism and the Social Construction of Science: Kuhn, Lakatos, Feyerabend

dialectica The Place of Subjects in the Metaphysics of Material Objects

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

COPYRIGHT 2009 ASSOCIAZIONE PRAGMA

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton


Kent Academic Repository

WHY STUDY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY? 1

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Abstract Several accounts of the nature of fiction have been proposed that draw on speech act

THE LANGUAGE OF SCIENCE: MEANING VARIANCE AND THEORY COMPARISON HOWARD SANKEY *

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

Transcription:

Majors Seminar Rovane Spring 2010 The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it. The central text for the course will be a book manuscript on the subject that I am now completing, supplements with background readings in semantics, philosophy of science, metaphysics and moral philosophy. Below please find the introduction to the book, followed by a brief account of the topics to be covered in it chapter by chapter. Introduction When philosophers argue against a metaphysical doctrine they do not usually rest with the mere claim that it is false, but claim as well that it is incoherent. In the case of relativism they often go even further, and charge that it cannot so much as be formulated to begin with. It should not be entirely surprising, therefore, that many contemporary defenders of relativism are not primarily concerned to defend its truth, but only to clarify what the doctrine consists in. What is surprising, though, is how little consensus there is among them about how the doctrine should be formulated, and what the fundamental dividing issue is between relativists and their opponents. In Part One of this book I shall develop and defend a somewhat novel formulation of the doctrine of relativsm, for which I claim the following virtues: first, it avoids the charge of incoherence that is so often levied against the doctrine; second, it captures one central intuition about what the doctrine consists in that drives a number of different accounts of it; third, it allows us to identify a clear dividing issue between relativists and their opponents that is worth taking seriously. Parts Two and Three go on to evaluate arguments for and against relativism once it is formulated along the lines I propose, in the domains of facts and morals, respectively. The concluding chapter explores the extent to which it is possible to live relativism and what it would mean to do so. In the remainder of these introductory remarks I ll survey some of the intuitions that govern our collective philosophical thinking about relativism, in order to set the stage for the arguments to come. Many contemporary philosophers who work in semantics associate the doctrine of relativism with the idea that truth is relative to context. Although these semantic relativists clearly have nomenclature on their side, not all contemporary relativists agree that relativism ought to be formulated in terms of this idea. Some propose instead to formulate the doctrine in terms of a quite different idea, which is that some disagreements can never be resolved. Such irresoluble disagreements are generally thought to be

possible only in the domain of values and not in the domain of facts and, indeed, it is primarily in the domain of values that this particular intuition about relativism predominates, with the result that if any theory in morals, politics or aesthetics should fail to rule out the possibility of irresoluble disagreement, it is generally regarded as threatening relativistic consequences. One of the raging disputes in contemporary discussions of relativism concerns the extent to which both of these intuitions can be retained together that relativism involves relative truth and that it arises with irresoluble disagreement. There is a third intuition about relativism that has garnered a much more impressive consensus, which is that relativists dispense with the particular forms of objectivity that we associate with realism, most especially scientific realism. This intuition about relativism has an extremely long history that arguably extends back to Protagoras, whose claim that truth is opinion is widely regarded as the first serious articulation of the relativists position. However, to the contemporary ear or at any rate, to my ear the Protagorean claim sounds more like nihilism than like relativism. If truth is opinion then there is no such thing as error, and if there is no such thing as error then there is no such thing as correctness either in short, no such thing as truth at all. A closer and more important historical source of this third intuition about relativism in is Kant. He did not argue that truth is opinion. But he did argue that we cannot make sense of truth within a realist metaphysics that portrays the objects of knowledge as radically mind-independent. As he put it, we cannot know things as they are in themselves but only as they appear to us given the particular forms of our sensibility and understanding. Rather than succumb to a skeptical conclusion that sees these subjective conditions on our knowledge as essentially distorting, he proposed a Copernican revolution that would cease to define knowledge in terms of objects but would instead define objects in terms of knowledge. The result was a new metaphysical position called transcendental idealism, according to which the world is the known world and, as such, subjectively conditioned. It would be going too far to suggest that Kant intended his transcendental idealist move to be a first step on the path to relativism. All the same, that is where it led, for it follows from transcendental idealism that if there were different kinds of subjects, with different forms of subjectivity, then they would quite literally know different worlds. Many of the accounts of relativism that emerged in the twentieth century are variations on this neo- Kantian theme, that the world is not entirely mind-independent and that there are, therefore, as many worlds as there are kinds of minds. I have in mind the accounts that arose in connection with logical positivism, cultural anthropology, philosophy of science and pragmatism. Thus, Carnap held that our beliefs cannot admit of objective confirmation or disconfirmation by experience except in the context of a particular linguistic framework that supplies a vocabulary and a logic in which to frame empirical claims; and it lies within our power to devise many such linguistic frameworks, each affording its own particular form of empirical objectivity. In similar fashion, early cultural anthropologists who flirted with relativism held that inhabitants of different cultures who speak different languages are thereby put in touch with different forms of reality. Kuhn famously held that scientists who work within different scientific paradigms inhabit different worlds. Richard Rorty took a similar view of all rational activity, which he saw as conditioned by social practices, broadly construed. Not only

did twentieth century relativists argue that there is a plurality of different subjective conditions on which reality might be said to depend, but also, there is no objective basis on which to say that any one of them is more or less valid than another. This contrasts with a realist metaphysical vision on which any claim must answer to the mindindependent facts in order to be true, and this is so no matter what subjective conditions might hold when someone makes the claim. That is the form of objectivity that relativists are typically thought to challenge. This third intuition about relativism, then, is a point of convergence between the contemporary debates about relativism and its precursors in the last century. When we think about relativism in this way, we presume that the first step in any argument for relativism must be a rejection of the realist thesis that reality is radically mindindependent, and the second step will be to argue for a plurality of conditions on which reality (or realities) might depend. Insofar as it is now thought that relativism is more plausible in the domain of value than in the domain of fact, it is because such a challenge to realism is thought to be more plausible there. However, there are also important points of divergence between the twentieth century debates about relativism and the current ones. The former did not generally share the other two intuitions that now predominate that is, relativism was not generally portrayed as involving the idea that truth is relative, nor as involving the idea that some disagreements can never be resolved. Intuition centered on another idea altogether, which is that there are alternatives. That is why Donald Davidson s famous argument against relativism targeted what he called alternative conceptual schemes. In his view, all of the various subjective conditions I just alluded to above that figured in twentieth century accounts of relativism linguistic frameworks, cultures, scientific paradigms, social practices are all supposed to provide such alternative conceptual schemes. But as he himself complained, it isn t entirely clear what this idea of alternativeness really comes to. It was often associated with another idea which also wasn t entirely clear, namely, incommensurability. The intuition that relativism arises with incommensurable alternativeness no longer holds such a central place in our thinking about relativism as it once did. I shall approach the task of formulating the doctrine of relativism by first examining the three intuitions that inform the current debates -- concerning relative truth, disagreement, and the presumed opposition between relativism and realism. We shall see that there are serious difficulties that stand in the way of arriving at a formulation along these lines that is both coherent and also manages to capture anything that intuitively deserves to be called relativism. We ll also see that a solution to these difficulties is afforded by a return to the older idea of alternativeness that predominated however unclearly and ineffectively in the twentieth century debates. We ll also see that when we try to make sense of alternativeness, we end up with a formulation that requires us to revise our understanding of what really should be at stake in debates about relativism. What is most fundamentally at stake is the oneness of the world, or as I shall call it, unimundilalism. In other words, insofar as the relativist is committed to alternativeness, the relativist is denying that there is only one world and affirming a multimundial view instead. We ll

see that this dividing issue between relativists and their opponents is at once a logical issue, a metaphysical issue and also a practical issue. When we formulate the doctrine of relativism as multimundialism, it turns out that we must give up all three of the other intuitions that now predominate in discussions of relativism: it does not involve the idea that truth is relative, nor that there can be irresoluble disagreements, nor even that relativism stands opposed to realism. In connection with this last point, we shall see that scientific realism in particular does not suffice to rule out relativism in the domain of facts, but may actually invite it. Davidson s argument is, by contrast with more standard realist arguments, much more effective against the relativist. However, this is so only in the domain of facts, for there are significant obstacles that stand in the way of carrying Davidson s argumentative strategy over to the domain of value. On balance, we ll see that there are much stronger reasons for taking relativism seriously in the domain of morals than in the domain of facts. But contrary to the prevailing received view about prospects for moral relativism, the reasons for taking it seriously have nothing to do with a failure of moral realism, or with a failure of moral objectivity more broadly construed. They have to do rather with the situatedness and locality of moral truth. Chapter One: Relative Truth, Anti-Realism and Disagreement Relative truth doesn t necessarily imply relativism (Indexicals and Space-Time) Why anti-realism is thought to generate relativism: irresoluble disagreement Problem: if both parties to a disagreement are right, that violates non-contradiction Two ways to remove disagreement: Relativize truth or disambiguate terms Do we lose relativism if we lose the appearance of disagreement? The deeper point: there is no point in registering disagreement anyway This is a symptom of what I call normative insularity : some truth-value-bearers fail to stand in logical relations Chapter Two: Unimundialism vs. Multimundialism Proposal: Relativism doesn t require disagreement but alternatives Alternatives are truths that cannot be embraced together There is a dilemma for alternativeness: any pair of truth-value-bearers is either inconsistent or consistent; if they are inconsistent they can t both be true; if they are consistent they can be embraced together If relativism arises with disagreement, the first horn is mistaken but there is a violation of non-contradiction If there is normative insularity, however, there is a third possibility that the dilemma overlooks: some truth-value-bearers are neither inconsistent nor consistent The real dividing issue: do logical relations run everywhere, among all truth-value bearers If they do, there is single and complete body of truths (=one world) If they do not, there are many incomplete bodies of truths (=many worlds) The practical meaning of unimundialism and multimundialism

Methodological problem: each side can successfully beg the question Solution: neither side can shift the burden of proof Chapter Three: Relativism and Science Carnap: scientific objectivity requires empirical confirmation; empirical confirmation can take place only within a linguistic framework, there are no objective bases to choose between frameworks but only evaluative (including aesthetic and pragmatic) considerations; linguistic frameworks are normatively insulated Kuhn: Scientific paradigms are normatively insulated due to holism (it is unclear whether they should be countered as alternatives are they all true, or is it merely the case that they we have no rational basis for choosing between them?) Feyerabend: We can still try to find decisive experiments Scientific realism reasserts itself: the convergence and success of scientific theories is evidence that we are tracking mind-independent reality Mind-independence is not the same thing as Oneness (the unimundial idea that logical relations run everywhere) What relativism really rules out is not the View from Nowhere but the View from Everywhere Chomsky: extending the mind-independence idea to mind itself Minds are limited and different from each other, and have epistemic access to different things Casts doubt on whether there can be a View from Everywhere Why this concession to relativism in the domain of facts has no practical import Chapter Four: Relativism and Holism I: Facts Quine vs. Carnap: Holism Why Holism might be thought to generate relativism How Davidson brought holism to bear against relativism (third dogma of empiricism) Davidson s misconception of issue of relativism: not scheme-content distinction but ubiquity of logical relations What is shared between Davidson s vision of meaning and the more naturalistic vision of the scientific vision: knowing other minds requires believing what they believe Chapter Five: Harman s Defense of Moral Relativism Self-interest as a basis for moral bargaining Relativity of moral obligation to moral agreement No multimundial conclusion: moral agreements are not normatively insulated Chapter Six: Prospects for Rationalist Moral Theory Harman took Egoism for granted in his attempt to argue for moral relativism and, in doing so, he took for granted that Egoism is dictated by rationality

However, Kantians and Utilitarians see their core moral values as dictated by rationality universalizability and the greatest aggregate good, respectively Why all three of these major moral theories is partly right: the values of self-interest, universalizability and the greatest good are all values that we arrive at by reflecting on the nature and form of practical reason (its perspectival character, its generality, and its employment of a thin notion of good in order to rank and weigh disparate goods on a single scale) Why each of these theories expects to rule out relativism: each puts forward a single moral value to which all other moral values must relate How each of these theories misconstrues what it means for a moral value to have an a priori basis in reason: it commands categorically Why this cannot be: Kantian, Utilitarian and Egoistic moral values all have an a priori basis in reason; they all provide conflicting instructions about what to do; therefore, none can command categorically Chapter Seven: Relativism and Holism II: Values Some moral values have an a priori basis in reason alone Other moral values have an empirical basis in human nature Still other values have an empirical basis in history, culture and other social conditions How social conditions might generate local holisms How this precludes the Davidsonian strategy against relativism in the domain of value The moral irrelevance of a view from everywhere in the moral domain Chapter Eight: Is it Possible to Live Relativism? The multimundial stance is not liberal toleration The multimundial stance is not subjectivist: moral values may be local and yet objective Why the multimundial stance seems morally unattractive Constraints on moral proselytizing: moral values may not be transportable and translatable; we can have no reason to spread our values unless we have the power to produce the conditions in which they have objective significance Higher order moral luck