The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Similar documents
Frege s Philosophy. Course Outline and Selected Reading

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

The Senses at first let in particular Ideas. (Essay Concerning Human Understanding I.II.15)

Scientific Philosophy

Sidestepping the holes of holism

The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall Class #7 Final Thoughts on Frege on Sense and Reference

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall 2015

Frege on Numbers: Beyond the Platonist Picture

We know of the efforts of such philosophers as Frege and Husserl to undo the

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Twentieth Excursus: Reference Magnets and the Grounds of Intentionality

124 Philosophy of Mathematics

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Types of perceptual content

TERMS & CONCEPTS. The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the English Language A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

No Proposition can be said to be in the Mind, which it never yet knew, which it was never yet conscious of. (Essay I.II.5)

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

Cambridge Introductions to Philosophy new textbooks from cambridge

206 Metaphysics. Chapter 21. Universals

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Architecture is epistemologically

Kant s Critique of Judgment

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

The Embedding Problem for Non-Cognitivism; Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism

On Recanati s Mental Files

The Philosophy of Language. Frege s Sense/Reference Distinction

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

On The Search for a Perfect Language

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring Russell Marcus Hamilton College

A STEP-BY-STEP PROCESS FOR READING AND WRITING CRITICALLY. James Bartell

AN ALTERNATIVE TO KITCHER S THEORY OF CONCEPTUAL PROGRESS AND HIS ACCOUNT OF THE CHANGE OF THE GENE CONCEPT. Ingo Brigandt

An Alternative to Kitcher s Theory of Conceptual Progress and His Account of the Change of the Gene Concept

The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

138 Great Problems in Philosophy and Physics - Solved? Chapter 11. Meaning. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/knowledge/meaning

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

The Ancient Philosophers: What is philosophy?

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Background to Gottlob Frege

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

Metaphors we live by. Structural metaphors. Orientational metaphors. A personal summary

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

From Pythagoras to the Digital Computer: The Intellectual Roots of Symbolic Artificial Intelligence

Singular Propositions, Abstract Constituents, and Propositional Attitudes

Frege: Two Theses, Two Senses

QUESTIONS AND LOGICAL ANALYSIS OF NATURAL LANGUAGE: THE CASE OF TRANSPARENT INTENSIONAL LOGIC MICHAL PELIŠ

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

Individualism and the Aesthetic

CONTENTS II. THE PURE OBJECT AND ITS INDIFFERENCE TO BEING

2 Unified Reality Theory

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

Thinking of Particulars 1

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON ENGINEERING DESIGN ICED 05 MELBOURNE, AUGUST 15-18, 2005 GENERAL DESIGN THEORY AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions

In his essay "Of the Standard of Taste," Hume describes an apparent conflict between two

COURSE: PHILOSOPHY GRADE(S): NATIONAL STANDARDS: UNIT OBJECTIVES: Students will be able to: STATE STANDARDS:

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Frege: Two Kinds of Meaning

Quine s Two Dogmas of Empiricism. By Spencer Livingstone

Corcoran, J George Boole. Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2nd edition. Detroit: Macmillan Reference USA, 2006

In The Mind and the World Order, C.I. Lewis made a famous distinction between the

observation and conceptual interpretation

The Constitution Theory of Intention-Dependent Objects and the Problem of Ontological Relativism

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

The UCD community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters!

1 Objects and Logic. 1. Abstract objects

IMPORTANT QUOTATIONS

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

Steven E. Kaufman * Key Words: existential mechanics, reality, experience, relation of existence, structure of reality. Overview

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

On Meaning. language to establish several definitions. We then examine the theories of meaning

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

Kent Academic Repository

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Philosophy? BRANCHES OF PHILOSOPHY. Philosophy? Branches of Philosophy. Branches of Philosophy. Branches of Philosophy 1/18/2013

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

Phenomenology Glossary

Transcription:

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton This essay will explore a number of issues raised by the approaches to the philosophy of language offered by Locke and Frege. This will involve an exploration of, in particular, Frege's criticism of Locke's 'psychologism', and Frege's view that thought is objective and intrinsically public. The essay will also show that Frege's advances on Locke do not go far enough, or at least do not satisfactorily and unambiguously settle the problems which Frege detects in Locke. They do not go far enough if we want to achieve an effective account of the relationship between language, thought and the world. It is assumed here that the primary objective of a philosophy of language is to illuminate the role which language plays in linking thought with the world and that it should be judged in terms of its effectiveness in doing that. My contention will be that Frege is less than effective because of unresolved tensions in his philosophy of language. Locke is a good starting point for reflecting on language because he presents 'in a clear and simple way the background to analytic philosophy of language' (Morris 2007, p.5). As Morris puts it, 'Locke's general theory of language initially strikes many as extremely natural. His views about what words are and what language is for are shared with almost the whole analytic tradition' (Morris 2007, p.5). However, at the same time his approach has been the object of thoroughgoing critique, and 'Frege's philosophy of language can be said to begin with a rejection of what seem to be central features of Locke's view' (Morris 2007, p.5). What are those central features? The starting point for Locke's theory of language is his empiricism and rejection of innate ideas of the kind put forward in Descartes' rationalism. For Locke, unlike Descartes, the mind at birth is a tabula rasa which is subsequently populated through experience. The contrast with Descartes is stark. 'For Descartes, human minds are created already in possession of certain innate foundational ideas or primitive notions, such as those of God, self, existence, thought, extension, and the union of mind and body' (Phemister, Introduction to Locke's 'An Essay concerning Human Understanding,' 2008, p.xii). For Locke, a person's knowledge is acquired only through experience; that is, experience through the senses which results in our ideas. 'This great Source, of most of the ideas we have, depending wholly on our senses, and derived by them to the Understanding, I call SENSATION' (An Essay concerning Human Understanding Book 2, Chapter 1, paragraph 3). This causal theory of perception provides the basis for Locke's philosophy of language. There are a number of key points at the foundation of Locke's view of the relationship between language, thought, and experience. First, language is necessary for people to communicate with one another. It is a necessary condition of social cooperation as Locke points out. (See 'An Essay concerning Human Understanding' Book 3, Chapter 2, paragraph 1). Second- and this is critical for an understanding of the contrast between Frege and Locke- what is communicated are the private ideas of individual people. Ideas are 1

internal to individual minds and are intrinsically private. The privacy of individual ideas makes finding ways of communicating all the more necessary. Third, for Locke, it is ideas that are the basis of thought. Thought, therefore, consists of the ideas in individuals' heads. This is further underlined by Locke's claim that it is not actual objects in the world that we have knowledge of. We can never directly know those objects. Rather, what we know are our ideas about those objects in so far as we have engaged with them through the senses. In this way, Locke is firmly - contra Putnam and Kripke- in the 'internalist' camp of seeing meanings as being in the head.. Fourth, for Locke words are the basic atomic components of language. They are the way in which people communicate their ideas to others, and the meaning of a word is the idea it represents. This is consistent with Locke's underlying nominalism which sees reality as essentially atomistic and consisting of particulars. On this view words represent the particulars which are experienced through the senses. There is a commonsense simplicity and plausibility about Locke's view, but Frege's philosophy of language demonstrates a number of key problems. Frege's approach moves the understanding of language forward in highly significant ways which have subsequently been deeply influential. The key problems with Locke from a Fregean point of view are examined in what follows. For Frege, Locke's approach presents a deeply problematic view of the nature of meaning because of what he regards as Locke's 'psychologism'. To see why Frege arrives at this view of Locke we need to go back to the foundations of Frege's own thinking. The starting point of Frege's philosophy is his approach to the philosophy of mathematics, in particular arithmetic and his attempt, contra Kant, to develop an approach which rests on the assumption that arithmetic and logic fall within the same conceptual field. ('Frege Explained' Weiner 2004, chapter 2). As Frege himself puts it, there 'is no such thing as a peculiarly arithmetical mode of inference that cannot be reduced to the general inference-modes of logic'. (Quoted in Kanterian 2012, p.2). Frege's work on language, sense and reference, and his attacks on empiricists and others, flow from this fundamental concern with the logical basis of arithmetic and its implications for our broader understanding of meaning and thought. (Kanterian 2012, p.3). It is this preoccupation with the logical basis of mathematics and its extension into other branches of philosophical understanding, in particular language, which leads Frege to the view that it is necessary to develop a new language free from the ambiguity and confusion of ordinary language. 'With the aid of a calculus, such a language would enable us to settle the truth and validity of philosophical claims and arguments' (Kanterian 2012, p.7). Frege is explicit about this when he claims that 'we could reason in metaphysics and morals similarly to how we reason in 2

geometry and analysis'. (Quoted in Kanterian 2012, p.7). 1 This is the thinking behind Frege's 'logicism'. The connection between Frege's logicism and his critique of Locke is clear. Reducing thought to its logical foundations is, for Frege, to display the conditions of objective thought. But if, as for Locke, thought consists only of the subjective 'ideas' in people's heads, and if language provides, as it does for Locke, symbolic expression of those subjective ideas, there is no guarantee that our language will express objective truth. It is subverted by Locke's 'psychologism' and the associated pitfalls of ordinary language. As Dummett has put it, for Frege natural 2 language 'came to appear to him more of an obstacle than a guide in logical and philosophical enquiries' (Dummett 1993, p.5). We need to penetrate beneath ordinary language to its inner logical and objective truths. Or, as Dummett has put it, Frege saw the need to achieve 'the extrusion of thoughts from the mind' (Dummett 1993, p.22). The objectivity of a thought for Frege is further captured by Dummett. Frege 'allows that grasping a thought is a mental act: but is an act whereby the mind apprehends that which is external to it in the sense of existing independently of being grasped by that or any other subject' (Dummett 1993, p.22). Put simply, this amounts to the claim that what is true is the case whether or not subjects consider it to be true. For example, the number '1' symbolises the abstract and real entity 1 but is not the same as that entity. In Frege's philosophy of language the True and the False are the objective referents of all propositions and, so it seems, exist in some way 3 which is independent of the subjective mind. Frege himself sums up his position in the following principle: 'Always to separate sharply the psychological from the logical, the subjective from the objective'. (Quoted in Miller 2007, p.37). These issues resurface in relation to Frege's concept of sense and his account of the relationship between sense and reference. As Michael Beaney has put it: 'The distinction between Sinn and Bedeutung is undoubtedly the most widely and influential element of Frege's philosophy, and...it was certainly viewed by Frege as playing a crucial role in the justification of his logicist roject' (Beaney 1996, p.151). He uses the concept of sense to tackle a number of puzzles about direct reference; for example, puzzles relating to bearerless names, substitution in belief contexts, negative existentials, and the informativeness of identity statements. In 1 In this respect Frege was influenced by Leibniz. (See Kanterian 2012, p.8-9). 2 A W Moore has described Frege's attitude towards natural language as follows: 'He was largely contemptuous of natural language, which he held to suffer from all sorts of defects which hamper clear thinking' (Moore 2012 p.197). 3 The 'in some way' expression is used here given the different interpretations that have been offered of Frege's account of objectivity. For some, Frege posits some kind of Platonic 'third' realm, while others (including Dummett in Dummett 1993) seek to demythologise Frege's account of objectivity. For discussion see Tyler Burge 'Frege on Knowing the Third Realm' Mind, vol. 101, No. 404, October 1992, pp.633-650; also B. Scot Rousse 'Demythologising the Third Realm: Frege on Grasping Thoughts' Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, Volume 3, Number 1, 2015, pp. 1-14. 3

developing the notion of sense, Frege moves well beyond Locke (and Mill) by recognising that: 'In addition to having semantic values, expressions also have semantic properties which determine what those semantic values are. The property which determines semantic value is the property of having sense' (Miller 2007, p.28). Frege also says that sense is 'the mode of presentation' of the referent, and his use of the Hesperus/Phosphorus distinction is often cited as an example of this. In terms of his critical stance on Locke, what is important is Frege's claim that the sense of a sentence is a thought (Miller 2007, p.34), and a thought is neither subjective nor psychological. As Dummett puts it, a 'thought for Frege, is a timeless object' (Dummett 1993 p.61). Moreover, it is in principle accessible by anybody; that is, it is publicly accessible. Frege's position is, therefore, radically different from Locke's for whom an idea is an inner mental phenomenon inaccessible by others. In arguing for the public accessibility of thought, Frege on the face of it provides a compelling response to the obvious limitations of the Lockean position for which the possibility of effective communication over shared meaning is on shaky ground. However, a question arises as to how effectively Frege has moved beyond Locke and whether his theory provides us with a compelling account of both meaning and communication. The suggestion argued for in this essay is that Frege ends up between a rock and a hard place with the implication that some further philosophising is required to get beyond the difficulties. The issue is as follows. Frege's philosophy faces a dilemma in setting out the conditions of the objectivity of sense. One possibility which much of his writing suggests is to assume that sense can be explained as some sort of Platonic 'third realm'. He has been interpreted as holding such a position. As A W Moore has put it: 'The objectivity that [Frege] accords [senses] is not just thorough; it is Platonic.' He sees senses as abstract entities whose existence is completely independent of us' (Moore 2012, p.212). (See also Burge 1992). The obvious problem is that it is difficult to defend the existence of such a realm. How would we ever know whether the sense of an expression derived from access to a third dimension of abstract reality or whether it was just the outcome of some sort of shared understanding within a linguistic community? Platonic realms of abstract objects are hard to defend metaphysically and present severe epistemological challenges. The alternative is to posit the notion of a linguistic community, and Frege seems at times to imply such a notion. 'For one can hardly deny that mankind has a common store of thoughts which is transmitted from one generation to another' (Quoted in Miller 2007, p.39). This is the view that the sense of an expression lies in the common language of a community. Dummett arguing against a Platonic interpretation of Frege, claims that this is precisely what Frege sees as the source of objectivity. 'One in this position has therefore to look about him to find something non-mythological but objective and external to the individual mind to embody the thoughts which the individual subject grasps and may assent to or reject. Where better to find it than in the institution of a common language?' ((Dummett 1993, p.25). 4

Several problems arise from the above for Frege's attempt to move beyond Locke. One is that his attempt to establish the objectivity of sense either falls at the Platonic hurdle, or founders on the rock of historical relativism since 'shared conceptions' inevitably change over time. Second, if sense is connected to 'shared conceptions' there is no guarantee that there will always be agreement over them. Frege, thus, has the same problem as Locke, namely differences of opinion over the meaning of terms and the consequent problems for communication. Third, while a common language exists independently of any one particular individual's thought, it only exists because there are thinking individuals who draw on and make use of a common language. There is a sense, then, that the common language is intimately connected with individual thought processes and cannot be conceptualised independently of them. Thus thought cannot be wholly extruded from the mind. In conclusion, what has been discussed above resolves into a number of key points. First, Frege undoubtedly forces our thinking about the meaning of expressions beyond consideration of the private domain of individuals' ideas. The notion of shared and publicly accessible conditions of thought and meaning makes more sense than the individualistic empiricism of Locke. Second, however, Frege's attempt to ground thought on logic looks problematic. It is not clear how he could make the leap from his account of logic to the defense of a Platonic third realm. Nor is it clear that his recognition of the role of 'a common store of thoughts which is transmitted from one generation to another' enables him to sustain the distinction between a formal language and natural language given that 'a common store of thought' resides in natural languages. Third, it seems that further philosophical work is needed to move beyond Frege's dilemma and the apparent failure of his commitment to logic to yield the conclusions about meaning and language which he seeks. Frege offers useful insights into the relationship between language, thought and the world but leaves crucial questions unresolved. References Michael Beaney Frege: Making Sense, Duckworth 1996 Michael Dummett Origins of Analytical Philosophy Duckworth 1993 Edward Kanterian Frege: a Guide for the Perplexed Continuum 2012 A W Moore The Evolution of Modern Metaphysics: Making Sense of Things Cambridge 2012 M Morris An Introduction to the Philosophy of Language, Cambridge 2007 Alexander Miller Philosophy of Language McGill-Queen's University Press 2007 Tyler Burge 'Frege on Knowing the Third Realm' Mind, vol. 101, No. 404, October 1992, pp.633-650 B. Scot Rousse 'Demythologising the Third Realm: Frege on Grasping Thoughts' Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, Volume 3, Number 1, 2015, pp. 1-14 Joan Weiner Frege Explained Open Court 2004 5