Sets, Symbols and Pictures: A Reflection on Euler Diagrams in Leonhard Euler s Tercentenary (2007)

Similar documents
RAFAEL BOMBELLI S ALGEBRA (1572) AND A NEW MATHEMATICAL OBJECT : A SEMIOTIC ANALYSIS

GESTALT CONFIGURATIONS IN GEOMETRY LEARNING

SYNTAX AND MEANING Luis Radford Université Laurentienne, Ontario, Canada

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

THE SENSUAL AND THE CONCEPTUAL: ARTEFACT-MEDIATED KINESTHETIC ACTIONS AND SEMIOTIC ACTIVITY

How the sense of mathematical objects changes when their semiotic representations undergo treatment or conversion

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Business Fun!! John Dewey Experiential learning

Postprint.

Permutations of the Octagon: An Aesthetic-Mathematical Dialectic

Language Value April 2016, Volume 8, Number 1 pp Copyright 2016, ISSN BOOK REVIEW

Pragmatism, Semiotic mind and Cognitivism

NON-EXAMPLES AND PROOF BY CONTRADICTION

By Tetsushi Hirano. PHENOMENOLOGY at the University College of Dublin on June 21 st 2013)

Problems of Information Semiotics

Visualizing Euclidean Rhythms Using Tangle Theory

Interactions between Semiotic Modes in Multimodal Texts. Martin Siefkes, University of Bremen

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Steven E. Kaufman * Key Words: existential mechanics, reality, experience, relation of existence, structure of reality. Overview

US_Math 4 1. Operations and Algebraic Thinking 4.OA 2. Number and Operations in Base Ten 4.NBT 3. Number and Operations - Fractions 4.

Learning Geometry and Music through Computer-aided Music Analysis and Composition: A Pedagogical Approach

INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL REASONING. Worksheet 3. Sets and Logics

Etna Builder - Interactively Building Advanced Graphical Tree Representations of Music

PANTOGRAPHS FOR GEOMETRICAL TRANSFORMATIONS: AN EXPLORATIVE STUDY ON ARGUMENTATION

Picture Descriptions and Centered Content

Lecture 7: Incongruent Counterparts

1/9. Descartes on Simple Ideas (2)

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Artefacts as a Cultural and Collaborative Probe in Interaction Design

Anne Freadman, The Machinery of Talk: Charles Peirce and the Sign Hypothesis (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2004), pp. xxxviii, 310.

INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON ENGINEERING DESIGN ICED 05 MELBOURNE, AUGUST 15-18, 2005 GENERAL DESIGN THEORY AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY

Interpreting Museums as Cultural Metaphors

Digital Text, Meaning and the World

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Nonfiction Text Features Chart

Peirce's Remarkable Rules of Inference

Musical Entrainment Subsumes Bodily Gestures Its Definition Needs a Spatiotemporal Dimension

Overview. Teacher s Manual and reproductions of student worksheets to support the following lesson objective:

TOWARDS AN EMBODIED, CULTURAL, AND MATERIAL CONCEPTION OF MATHEMATICS COGNITION

META-COGNITIVE UNITY IN INDIRECT PROOFS

OPERATIONS SEQUENCING IN A CABLE ASSEMBLY SHOP

UMAC s 7th International Conference. Universities in Transition-Responsibilities for Heritage

Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of California Los Angeles

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Keywords: semiotic; pragmatism; space; embodiment; habit, social practice.

Symmetry and Transformations in the Musical Plane

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Theories and Activities of Conceptual Artists: An Aesthetic Inquiry

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Mensuration of a kiss The drawings of Jorinde Voigt

CPSC 121: Models of Computation. Module 1: Propositional Logic

Barbara Tversky. using space to represent space and meaning

Windows and Mirrors Biography and Autobiography

How Semantics is Embodied through Visual Representation: Image Schemas in the Art of Chinese Calligraphy *

Euler s Art of Reckoning 1

The Oxford Compendium of Visual Illusions (2017), A. Shapiro, & D.Todorovic (Eds.), Oxford University Press, New York,

Chrominance Subsampling in Digital Images

What is Rhetoric? Grade 10: Rhetoric

How the semiotic square came

No Proposition can be said to be in the Mind, which it never yet knew, which it was never yet conscious of. (Essay I.II.5)

Generally in English, Chema plays verbal and visual elements off against each other eg Everything Flies (1992) where the word History reads as Hearsay

Review of Illingworth, Shona (2011). The Watch Man / Balnakiel. Belgium, Film and Video Umbrella, 2011, 172 pages,

Automated extraction of motivic patterns and application to the analysis of Debussy s Syrinx

Z.13: Substances and Universals

VISUALISATION AND PROOF: A BRIEF SURVEY

CHILDREN S CONCEPTUALISATION OF MUSIC

Correlation to the Common Core State Standards

The Aristotle Index: Measuring Complexity in the Twenty-First Century. John N. Warfield

The hierarchy of classes of Johann Caspar Sulzer (1755)

206 Metaphysics. Chapter 21. Universals

Fuzzy Concept and Mathematics Education

Philosophy of Art and Aesthetic Experience in Rome PHIL 277 Fall 2018

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

COMPUTER ENGINEERING SERIES

Loughborough University Institutional Repository. This item was submitted to Loughborough University's Institutional Repository by the/an author.

Music and Mathematics: On Symmetry

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver

THEORY AND DECISION LIBRARY

Image and Imagination

Social Semiotic Techniques of Sense Making using Activity Theory

SEVENTH GRADE. Revised June Billings Public Schools Correlation and Pacing Guide Math - McDougal Littell Middle School Math 2004

Jokes and the Linguistic Mind. Debra Aarons. New York, New York: Routledge Pp. xi +272.


The theory of representations as viewed from the onto-semiotic approach to mathematics education

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Revitalising Old Thoughts: Class diagrams in light of the early Wittgenstein

of all the rules presented in this course for easy reference.

WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS

2 nd Grade Visual Arts Curriculum Essentials Document

Lesson 5: Events and Venn Diagrams

1/9. The B-Deduction

Intimacy and Embodiment: Implications for Art and Technology

CST/CAHSEE GRADE 9 ENGLISH-LANGUAGE ARTS (Blueprints adopted by the State Board of Education 10/02)

A new grammar of visual design Entrevista com Gunther Kress Helena Pires*

Adisa Imamović University of Tuzla

The Influence of Chinese and Western Culture on English-Chinese Translation

Architecture is epistemologically

Architecture as the Psyche of a Culture

Transcription:

Mediterranean Journal for Research in Mathematics Education Vol. 5, 2, 77-82, 2006 Sets, Symbols and Pictures: A Reflection on Euler Diagrams in Leonhard Euler s Tercentenary (2007) GIORGIO T. BAGNI: Department of Mathematics and Computer Science University of Udine (Italy). ABSTACT: The basic expressions of Set Theory are rooted in the linguistic structure of subject-predicate, and Euler-Venn diagrams should not be seen as means to replace the meaning of the predicative structure. In this paper we propose and discuss an example in order to show that the traditional representation by Euler-Venn diagrams cannot be considered, from the educational viewpoint too, completely equivalent to verbal or symbolic predicative expressions. In general, different systems of representation embody the students spatial and temporal mathematical experience in a variety of ways (Radford, 2002 and 2003a; Bagni, 2006) and the use of a particular representation links different conceptual aspects (an experimental research about the role of representations in students understanding of sets is discussed in: Gagatsis & Al., 2001). With reference to representative registers, Duval s use of the term register emphasizes the particular operational character of signs (Duval, 1995; it is worth noting that this idea of register is different from Halliday s: for the latter, a register is defined as a linguistic variety based on use linking the text, the linguistic and the social systems: Halliday, 1985; in this work the term register will be used in Duval s sense). We are going to propose a brief reflection on some features of the educational representation by Euler-Venn diagrams. In this paper we shall not propose a complete outline of the history of sets representations (see for instance: Baron, 1969). Nevertheless, let us notice that sometimes the denomination Euler diagram is referred to a diagram that does not visualize all the possible intersections of the considered sets, while a Venn diagram is a diagram in which all the possible intersections are visualized. For instance, in the following picture, a set is visualized as a (proper) subset of another set according to Leonhard Euler (1707-1783), on the left, and to John Venn (1834-1923), on the right (a part with is certainly non-empty; a shaded part is certainly empty):

G. T. Bagni Euler s representation was published in 1772 (see the Fig. 1, from the book Lettere ad una Principessa d Alemagna, Ferres, Napoli 1787, the first Italian edition of Lettres à une princesse d Allemagne; in the Fig. 2 we show the title-page of the work). Fig. 1 Fig. 2 From the educational viewpoint, it is well-known that Euler diagrams are particularly clear and intuitive. Concerning Venn diagrams, let us show in the following picture Edwards constructions referred to 3, 4, 5 sets (Edwards, 2004): 78

Sets, Symbols and Pictures Original construction by Venn (1880) is the following: Let us now consider the following example: A = {1, 5}; B = {1; 2}; C = {2; 3}; D = {3; 4}; E = {4; 5}; F = {2; 5}; G = {3; 5}; H = {1; 4}; I = {1; 3}; J = {2; 4} We are going to represent these sets by an Euler-Venn diagram. Let us point out two basic remarks: (1) If we write A = {1, 5}, B = {1; 2}, C = {2; 3}, D = {3; 4}, E = {4; 5}, F = {2; 5}, G = {3; 5}, H = {1; 4}, I = {1; 3}, J = {2; 4} we have to connect every element of {1; 2; 3; 4; 5} with each of the other elements of the same set. In other words, in order to trace an Euler-Venn diagram of a set wit two elements, we must realize a sort of graphic link of the considered elements (in general, a set is represented by a connected plane figure): (2) In order to avoid misunderstandings and mistakes, of course it is preferable that two disjoint sets are represented by disjoint plane figures (in an Euler diagram). For instance, the following representation of the sets G and J would cause misunderstandings to a pupil (as a matter of fact, is their intersection empty?): 79

G. T. Bagni Of course, in order to represent clearly the sets G = {3; 5} e J = {2; 4}, we can change the position of the points-elements; nevertheless, if we keep the original positions, the (unusual, but quite correct) representation can be the following: Let us now turn back to the exercise previously proposed. We have to trace a complete and planar (see previous remarks) graph with 5 points; but it is well-known that the complete graph K 5 (one of Kuratowski s graph) is not planar. For instance, with reference to the following figure, let us trace the nine sets to which the nine couples of elements linked by a segment belong (e.g. the set G = {3; 5} is represented by the dotted line). Now it is impossible to trace a connected representation of J = {2; 4} without graphical intersections that, from the educational viewpoint, can cause some misunderstandings (for instance, the wrong statement of a non-empty intersection of G = {3; 5} and J = {2; 4}). So the situation described by A = {1, 5}, B = {1; 2}, C = {2; 3}, D = {3; 4}, E = {4; 5}, F = {2; 5}, G = {3; 5}, H = {1; 4}, I = {1; 3}, J = {2; 4} cannot be represented by Euler diagrams without unusual graphic features. Of course we can ask ourselves: is connection a compulsory characteristic for Euler-Venn diagrams? Even if one does not consider the connection absolutely necessary, it is clear that a graphic representation of a set by two disconnected parts would induce several students to refer to two sets (see moreover: Chilakamarri, Hamburger & Pippert, 1996). 80

Sets, Symbols and Pictures Can we conclude that traditional Euler-Venn diagrams (and by this we mean diagrams traced by using connected figures) have an epistemological status that is completely different from the status of symbolic or verbal expressions, referred to the relation of belonging? Surely these systems of representation (in particular, Euler diagrams) have different features, and express different information. It is worth noting that every kind of notation and representation implies some ties: for instance, when I draw a circle, during the resolution of a geometric problem, I introduce a tie: I should not be able to draw another circle whose diameter is 1/1000000 of the diameter of the circle previously drawn, although of course this is a situation that, from the theoretical viewpoint, can be considered. In cases like this it is necessary to overcome difficulties by some cunning; so it is important to realize the presence of those ties, from the educational viewpoint, too. However, in our opinion, we can state that different representation registers are not equivalent ; and the students were affected by signs (Radford, 2002) in the sense that signs offered them new paths of conceptual development (Gagatsis & Al., 2001; Bagni, 2006). Since the functioning of our mind (following: Duval, 1995) is indivisibly linked to the existence of several representation registers, it is very important to develop students ability to use and to co-ordinate different registers (Bagni, 2005); nevertheless we must reflect carefully about this co-ordination: is it always possible? Completely or not? And we can finally ask ourselves: what do these (different) representations represent? Propositions, according to Richard Rorty, cannot be conceived (only) as simple expressions of our experience, or as representations of an extra-experiential reality, a reality out there, with our mind as a great mirror containing various representations (Rorty, 1979); they are sequences of signs and sounds used by human beings in order to develop social practices (Rorty, 1992), and representations oh mathematical objects can be framed into this approach. Every kind of representation has typical features, contains particular kinds of information, and is connected to particular uses, to particular social practices (Radford, 2003b). It is wrong, and useless, to make reference to different systems of representation as different forms of a universal mathematical language by which the mathematical objects can be introduced into our mind. ACKNOWLEDGMENTS: The Author would like to thank Claudio Bernardi (University of Rome La Sapienza ) for the very valuable help provided for improving this paper. 81

G. T. Bagni REFERENCES Bagni, G.T.: 2005, The historical roots of the limit notion. Cognitive development and development of representation registers. Canadian Journal of Science, Mathematics and Technology Education 5, 4, 453-468. Bagni, G.T.: 2006, Some cognitive difficulties related to the representations of two major concepts of set theory. Educational Studies in Mathematics 62, 3, 259-280. Baron, M.E.: 1969, A note on the historical development of logic diagrams: Leibniz, Euler, and Venn. Mathematical Gazette 53, 113-125. Chilakamarri, K.B., Hamburger, P. & Pippert, R.E.: 1996, Venn diagrams and planar graphs. Geometriae Dedicata 62, 73-91. Duval, R.: 1995, Sémiosis et pensée humaine. Lang, Paris. Edwards, A.W.F.: 2004, Cogwheels of the mind: the story of Venn diagrams, Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore and London. Gagatsis, A. & Al.: 2001, The role of representations in gymnasium students understanding of sets and their operations. In: Gagatsis, A. (Ed.), Learning in Mathematics and Science and Educational Technology. Intercollege Press, Nicosia, I, 349-367. Halliday, M.A.K.: 1985, An introduction to functional grammar. Arnold, London. Radford, L.: 2002, The seen, the spoken and the written. A semiotic approach to the problem of objectification of mathematical knowledge. For the Learning of Mathematics 22, 2, 14-23. Radford, L.: 2003a, Gestures, speech and the sprouting of signs. Mathematical Thinking and Learning 5, 1, 37-70. Radford, L.: 2003b, On the epistemological limits of language: mathematical knowledge and social practice during the Renaissance. Educational Studies in Mathematics 52, 123-150. Rorty, R.: 1979, Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton University Press, Princeton. Rorty, R.: 1992, Twenty-Five Years After. The University of Chicago, Chicago. Venn, J.: 1880, On the diagrammatic and mechanical representation of propositions and reasonings. The London, Edinburgh, and Dublin Philosophical Magazine and Journal of Science 9, 1-18. 82