Review of Albert Borgmann, Holding onto Reality. The Nature of Information at the Turn of the Millennium. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999.

Similar documents
Techné 6:1 Fall 2002 Mullins, Introduction: Getting a Grip / 3 seriously interested in Borgmann s philosophical perspective. 1 Hans Achterhuis, the on

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY


Surface Integration: Psychology. Christopher D. Keiper. Fuller Theological Seminary

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Hegel and the French Revolution

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

TRAGIC THOUGHTS AT THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

7. This composition is an infinite configuration, which, in our own contemporary artistic context, is a generic totality.

J.S. Mill s Notion of Qualitative Superiority of Pleasure: A Reappraisal

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

observation and conceptual interpretation

Review by Răzvan CÎMPEAN

A Process of the Fusion of Horizons in the Text Interpretation

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

Notes on Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful

Zadie Smith s Generation Why?, a film review of David Fincher s

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

Albert Borgmann, Holding on to Reality: The Nature of Information at the Turn of the Millennium, University of Chicago Press, 2000.

History Admissions Assessment Specimen Paper Section 1: explained answers

(1) Writing Essays: An Overview. Essay Writing: Purposes. Essay Writing: Product. Essay Writing: Process. Writing to Learn Writing to Communicate

Architecture as the Psyche of a Culture

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document

Narrating the Self: Parergonality, Closure and. by Holly Franking. hermeneutics focus attention on the transactional aspect of the aesthetic

Content. Philosophy from sources to postmodernity. Kurmangaliyeva G. Tradition of Aristotelism: Meeting of Cultural Worlds and Worldviews...

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2016, xiii+372pp., ISBN: Publishing offers us a critical re-examination of what the book is hence, the

What is the Object of Thinking Differently?

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Writing an Honors Preface

Humanities 4: Lecture 19. Friedrich Schiller: On the Aesthetic Education of Man

Philosophy in the educational process: Understanding what cannot be taught

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

Capstone Design Project Sample

Aristotle on the Human Good

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

Vinod Lakshmipathy Phil 591- Hermeneutics Prof. Theodore Kisiel

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1

Humanities Learning Outcomes

According to Maxwell s second law of thermodynamics, the entropy in a system will increase (it will lose energy) unless new energy is put in.

Intention and Interpretation

Texas Southern University. From the SelectedWorks of Anthony M Rodriguez Ph.D. Michael A Rodriguez, Ph.D., Texas Southern University

Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2d ed. transl. by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (London : Sheed & Ward, 1989), pp [1960].

PETER - PAUL VERBEEK. Beyond the Human Eye Technological Mediation and Posthuman Visions

Rousseau on the Nature of Nature and Political Philosophy

The phenomenological tradition conceptualizes

Lecture 24 Sociology 621 December 12, 2005 MYSTIFICATION

Early Daoism and Metaphysics

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

Chapter 2: Karl Marx Test Bank

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

RESPONSE AND REJOINDER

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

Excerpt: Karl Marx's Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Philosophical roots of discourse theory

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Any attempt to revitalize the relationship between rhetoric and ethics is challenged

Mimesis and World-building: Berger and Girard on the Sacred

Chapter 2 Christopher Alexander s Nature of Order

Always More Than One Art: Jean-Luc Nancy's <em>the Muses</em>

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

SECTION I: MARX READINGS

AXIOLOGY OF HOMELAND AND PATRIOTISM, IN THE CONTEXT OF DIDACTIC MATERIALS FOR THE PRIMARY SCHOOL

Moral Judgment and Emotions

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

Louis Althusser s Centrism

Culture and Art Criticism

CHAPTER SIX. Habitation, structure, meaning

FIFTY KEY CONTEMPORARY THINKERS

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

M E M O. When the book is published, the University of Guelph will be acknowledged for their support (in the acknowledgements section of the book).

Chapter Six Integral Spirituality

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

The Spell of the Sensuous Chapter Summaries 1-4 Breakthrough Intensive 2016/2017

Studia Philosophiae Christianae UKSW 49(2013)4. Michigan Technological University, USA

A C E I T A Writing Strategy Helping Writers Get that A And Avoid Plagiarism

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Emerging Questions: Fernando F. Segovia and the Challenges of Cultural Interpretation

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

托福经典阅读练习详解 The Oigins of Theater

Kansas Standards for English Language Arts Grade 9

American Literature 1920 to the Present. Dr. Alex E. Blazer English 4665/ August 2010

COURSE: PHILOSOPHY GRADE(S): NATIONAL STANDARDS: UNIT OBJECTIVES: Students will be able to: STATE STANDARDS:

CRITICAL THEORY BEYOND NEGATIVITY

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Mass Communication Theory

What most often occurs is an interplay of these modes. This does not necessarily represent a chronological pattern.

Critical Theory, Poststructuralism and the Philosophy of Liberation. By Douglas Kellner (

GABRIEL TARDE AND THE END OF SOCIAL By Bruno Latour

Mary Evelyn Tucker. In our search for more comprehensive and global ethics to meet the critical challenges of our

Where the Organ Meets the Outside World. Part I. If I had to summarize Ruth Finnegan's The Hidden Musicians in a single sentence, I would say

Transcription:

Review of Albert Borgmann, Holding onto Reality. The Nature of Information at the Turn of the Millennium. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999. Douglas Kellner (http://www.gseis.ucla.edu/faculty/kellner/kellner.html) Albert Borgmann's new book Holding onto Reality. The Nature of Information at the Turn of the Millennium (1999) continues the interrogation of the epochal significance of new information technology he began in Crossing the Postmodern Divide (1992). For Borgmann, the postmodern divide involves, among other things, a shift from involvement with "focal" things and practices (i.e. activities such as eating, gardening, running, and the like), to immersion in media fantasies, or the thrills of cyberspace and virtual reality. Borgmann continues his defense of "reality" against the champions of the hyper or virtual realities of cyberspace and new technologies, focusing on the concept of information and its vicissitudes under the impact of new computer and information technology. Borgmann's latest book also has millennial echoes, signalled in the book's subtitle, suggesting ways to survive the new era of information technology. Borgmann reminds us that the concept "millennium" contains a sense of both crisis and renewal, of a breaking down of the old order and the creation of a new one. It has overtones of apocalypse, that the breakdown may be catastrophic and that the emergent order may not be preferable to the old order and may indeed be inferior, perhaps disastrously so. This is indeed the thrust of a series of books that present the technological revolution as a philosophical and human catastrophe, a collapse of the real, identity, meaning, the subject and the human, as the explorers of technoculture get lost in byways of cyberspace and the information superhighway.1 On the other hand, a new millennium suggests the possibility of a better future, an overcoming of the limitations and problems of the past epoch in the transition to a preferable new age. Borgmann, however, is neither an optimist, a utopian, nor a visionary of a better future. The title of his recent book Holding onto Reality succinctly epitomizes his position concerning his preferred response to the radical effects of new information technology. Hence, "holding onto reality" in the face of the seductions of virtual reality, hyperreality, and the new worlds of cyberspace amounts to Borgmann's fundamental position and advice. Borgmann bases his analysis on distinctions between three types and levels of signs, of information -- natural, cultural, and technological. Natural information for Borgmann is "information about reality," involving "natural signs," like signs of weather, the environment, or the presence of animals or other human beings. "Cultural information" arose in the transition between oral and written culture, involving the production of conventional signs in the form of writing, art works, or diagrams such as architectural drawings or musical scores which allow one to reproduce cultural forms and products. "Cultural information" can thus be for, as well as about, reality, informing practice and constructing tradition. Much of Borgmann's text is about the genesis and structure of "cultural information," including

studies of "producing information" that focus on "writing and structure" (Chapter 6) and "measures and grids" (Chapter 7), as well as studies of "realizing information" that analyze "reading," "playing" (i.e. musical scores), and "building" (Chapters 8-10). The modes of producing information analyze the structures and constituents of information, while the latter three modes of realizing information refer to their fundamental embodiment in focal human activities (reading, playing, and building), Borgmann's riff on Heidegger's trinity of living, building and dwelling. Borgmann provides strong historical and philosophical analyses of the origins of writing, of grids and graphics, of print and book culture, drawing on classical and contemporary philosophical sources to illuminate the structure and evolution of what he calls cultural information. Yet his analyses tend to summarize existing material on these topics rather than breaking new ground. Hence, while one might learn much from Borgmann's account of the genealogy of different forms of cultural information, a thorough-going history and philosophical critique of information for the present age remains to be written. Yet it is perhaps the third part of his book on technological information, or "information as reality," that constitutes the heart of Borgmann's analysis of the information revolution where the stakes of his undertaking become evident. His project, as signalled in the introduction, is to provide "both a theory and an ethics of information -- a theory to illuminate the structure of information and an ethics to get the moral of its development. My hope is that the theory will lend perspicuity to the ethics, that the ethics will give the theory some force, and that, once we have understand information, we will see that the good life requires an adjustment among the three kinds of information and a balance of signs and things" (6). Borgmann's worry is that with the advent to cultural dominance of information technology, we will lose touch with nature and natural information, as well as culture and our embodied social lives. Continuing a set of reflections delineated in Crossing the Postmodern Divide, Borgmann worries about losing touch with concrete reality and everyday life, substituting virtual relations, communities, and reality for face-to-face social interaction and enjoyment and preservation of nature. He believes that an imbalance is emerging whereby technological information overpowers concrete "reality," substituting hyperreality and virtual reality for the sort of natural and cultural forms of reality and interaction upon which the human being was focused during past millennia. To delineate his argument, Borgmann provides in the third part of the book a philosophical genealogy of what he calls "technological information," drawing on philosophical and historical sources, replicating the procedure that he provided in his analysis of natural and cultural information. Technological information, for Borgmann, is described as "information as reality" and here his critique finds its edge. Once again, one can learn much about the genesis of information technology, its mode of information and differences from natural and cultural signs, and the epochal significance of the information revolution, although, again, there is not that much new in the way of a philosophical critique of informational technology. Throughout, Borgmann deploys a structural analysis of signification in which signs are related to things whereby "intelligence" enables a person to be informed about a thing within a certain

context. Different signs inform differently and Borgmann is concerned to distinguish between three types of information and signs and how they relate to "reality." For his project to work, Borgmann must develop a robust conception of reality to, first, overcome the postmodern dictum that reality (and language, consciousness, et al) is a social construct, a mere effect of a specific culture or discourse system. But he also needs to demonstrate that a more fundamental and compelling "reality" is being overcome and displaced by the new (hyper/virtual)realities of cyberspace, informational technology, and new multimedia, and must persuade his readers to take more seriously and ground their lives in this more primal "reality." Borgmann's conception of reality involves philosophical analysis with theological underpinnings and attempts at phenomenological evocation of focal and resonant natural and cultural reality. For Borgmann, "reality" consists of structure, "the how and lawfulness of a thing" (99), and contingency, "the what and idiosyncrasy of a thing" (99). In this conception, "Reality is both knowable and unsurpassable" (99). "Reality" is also contested, with different conceptions competing for allegiance. For Borgmann, "reality" has a "commanding presence" and "real gravity" (189), as opposed to the "lightness" of virtual reality. Theological underpinnings run throughout Borgmann's arguments. Reality and things are eloquent because they are created; nature and natural reality are eloquent because they are the direct product of the Creator, God, while humans, in the Christian framework in which Borgmann operates, are also created by God, although there are intimations their own human creations can be divorced from reality, fallen into the realm of culture and eventually cyberspace and hyperreality. For Borgmann, as medieval philosophers, the significance of things "has priority over the significance of words, and the significance of things in turn arises from divine eloquence" (88). Throughout, Borgmann cites biblical and theological sources to illustrate his points and closes his book with cryptic religious millennial ruminations concerning a coming potential salvation whereby "our souls will be rocked in the bosom of Abraham" (233). There is thus in Borgmann a sense that the ascent into cyberspace is a fall for the human being, creating a fatal imbalance between nature, culture, and technology. For Borgmann, "Righting the balance of information and reality is the crucial task. It amounts to the restoration of eminent natural information" (221). Borgmann is reasonable enough to acknowledge that: "There is no danger that technological information might entirely displace natural or cultural information" (219). Yet he fears that: "There is a real possibility, however, that natural and cultural information will decline to mere utilities, tools we need but fail to sustain as signs of irreplaceable kinds of excellence" (219). I think few will disagree with Borgmann that we need to balance the types of information -- natural, cultural, and technological -- that we utilize and that as we venture through the realms of technological culture we need to be conscious of the importance of the natural and socio-cultural environment with its myriad forms of information and experience. Indeed, our challenge is to produce a cultural ecology that achieves that sort of balance that Borgmann wisely affirms. Yet I do not think that Borgmann himself delineates a sustainable balance as he fails, in my view, to adequately analyze and appraise the possibilities of the new technological environment. Throughout, Borgmann frequently engages in denigration and dismissal of salient aspects of the new cyberculture and displays a technophobic negativity toward this realm of experience, despite

his attempts to fairly and cogently address the nature and exigencies of the new information technology and cyberculture. There are frequent exaggerated claims concerning the dangers and negativities of cyberculture and information technology, and some dogmatic assertions of his critical stance that will not stand up to more perspicuous critique. For instance, in appraising claims for the positive effects of information technology, Borgmann argues that growth in bandwidth, information-storing capacity, and processing power "suggests that freedom of choice today is as likely stifling as liberating" (139). But who exactly is "stifled" by such technological progress and how? Here and elsewhere Borgmann engages in rhetorical assertion rather than deploying evidence and argumentation to make his case. In general, Borgmann asserts the "decline of meaning with rise of information" (232, passim), but this is never clearly explicated or demonstrated, and one could argue that information technology provides new venues and opportunities for the production of meaning, as well as new forms of experience and reality. Throughout, one gets the sense that information technology is an inferior source of knowledge and experience for Borgmann as when he writes that compared to lecture halls, libraries and labs: technological information, to the contrary, comes endlessly and relentlessly pouring forth from one source to address an immobilized body via one sense. Or so it would if personal computers were a truly rich information source. As it is, the prohibitive imbalance between abundant information and severely stunted capacity is righted by reducing information to a thin trickle, tricked up into colorful bubbles (208). In passages like this, Borgmann reveals bias and prejudice that he tries to avoid in his more rigorous philosophical and historical studies. In doing computer research, one is not necessarily more "immobilized" than in reading books, one may access a multitude of sources, including some of the world's great libraries, and with multimedia technology more than "one sense" is in play. Multimedia may enrich information with sights, sounds, and graphics, that are more than a "thin trickle" or "colorful bubbles." In such passages, Borgmann relies more on questionable rhetorical excess than philosophical argumentation, revealing a prejudice against a technology and mode of culture that he finds threatening and foreign. To restore the balance, Borgmann sometimes exaggerates the primacy of nature over other domains, arguing, for instance: "Nothing so engages the fullness of human capabilities as a coherent and focused world of natural information" (219). Whereas in many contexts and epochs this is no doubt true, there are times when humans are fully engaged in social activity (war, labor, invention, cultural production, etc), and for many the world of cyberculture is fully engaging. A genuine balance between such things as natural, cultural and technological information requires that each realm be respected as equals, that all realms be accorded appropriate validity, significance, and reality, and that specific realms not be elevated over and against competing cultural forms and realms of life which are correspondingly downplayed and degraded. Whereas champions of new information technology often make overstated claims for the

benefits of cyberculture over previous natural and social forms of culture and life, Borgmann frequently makes the opposite error, downplaying or denigrating technological experience and reality in contrast to natural or cultural reality. Moreover, Borgmann's critique rests on a series of binary oppositions between reality and hyper/virtual reality, and natural/cultural vs. technological information, in which metaphysical and moral primacy is bestowed on the first term of the opposition, while the latter is seen to be derivative and inferior (curiously, the distinction between focal things and practices versus the domain of technological devices which was central to his earlier thought does not surface in a major way in his latest book). A deconstructive critique could argue that "reality" and "nature" are more highly constructed than in Borgmann's account, while hyper and virtual reality, or technological information, also are salient forms of reality. Borgmann has thus not really grounded his conceptions of reality and the ethics of information in an adequate metaphysical or normative conception. Occasionally, he provides theological underpinnings to his apparatus, but does not adequately develop a robust concept of reality to play against hyper/virtual reality, nor does he provide grounding for an ethics of information that would provide the sort of normative perspective to make his arguments. Hence, Borgmann's perspectives are somewhat free-floating, rooted more in assertion, rhetoric, and theological spin, rather than evidence or solid argumentation. Thus, while intuitively one would be willing to agree with Borgmann that we need appropriate scale in our adventures with new technologies, it is not clear that he has provided an adequate account of its novelties, benefits, and possibilities, or a genuinely balanced account of harmonious relations between our natural, cultural, and technological environments. Yet Borgmann is constantly provocative and his new book should help generate informed debate over the benefits and dangers of the shape and effects of a new mode of information and the need to harmoniously integrate this sphere into the broader dimensions of natural and cultural life. Note 1. Such technophobic books include Martin Heidegger (1977) The Question Concerning Technology. New York: Harper and Row; Jacques Ellul (1964) The Technological Society. New York: Knopf; and a series of books by Paul Virilio including (1996) Cybermonde, la politique de pire. Paris: Textuel; (1997) Open Sky. London: Verso; and (1998) Polar Inertia. London: Sage. U.S.-written jeremiads against new technologies include Mark Slouka (1995) War of the Worlds. New York: Harper and Row; Clifford Stoll (1995) Silicon Snake Oil: Second Thoughts on the Information Highway. New York: Doubleday and Borgmann's earlier (1992) Across the Postmodern Divide Chicago: University of Chicago Press.