SNP Best-set Typesetter Ltd. Article No.: 583 Delivery Date: 31 October 2005 Page Extent: 4 pp

Similar documents
Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Image and Imagination

On Recanati s Mental Files

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions

McDowell, Demonstrative Concepts, and Nonconceptual Representational Content Wayne Wright

6 Bodily Sensations as an Obstacle for Representationism

COGNITION AND IDENTIFYING REFERENCE. Gary Rosenkrantz

Sidestepping the holes of holism

In The Meaning of Ought, Matthew Chrisman draws on tools from formal semantics,

Exploring touch: A review of Matthew Fulkerson s The First Sense

In his essay "Of the Standard of Taste," Hume describes an apparent conflict between two

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

Perceptual Presence. Jason Leddington. [Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 90 (2009) ]

Types of perceptual content

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Assistant Professor in Philosophy, Cornell University (reappointed in 1969 to second 3-year term, resigned in 1970).

Spectrum inversion as a challenge to intentionalism

Varieties of Nominalism Predicate Nominalism The Nature of Classes Class Membership Determines Type Testing For Adequacy

Perception and Mind-Dependence Lecture 3

Areas of Specialization: Philosophy of Mind (empirically informed), Phenomenology, Ethics of Virtual Reality

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

Scientific Philosophy

My thesis is that not only the written symbols and spoken sounds are different, but also the affections of the soul (as Aristotle called them).

Emotions from the Perspective of Analytic Aesthetics

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

SYMPOSIUM: REID ON VISIBLE FIGURE REID ON THE PERCEPTION OF VISIBLE FIGURE. GIDEON YAFFE University of Southern California

Abstract Several accounts of the nature of fiction have been proposed that draw on speech act

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Penultimate Draft- Final version forthcoming in Philosophical Psychology

The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong

Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008

PH 360 CROSS-CULTURAL PHILOSOPHY IES Abroad Vienna

Comments on Bence Nanay, Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery

THE CONCEPT OF CREATIVITY IN SCIENCE AND ART

"The mind is a fire to be kindled, not a vessel to be filled." Plutarch

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography

Varieties of Tone Presence: Process, Gesture, and the Excessive Polyvalence of Pitch in Post-Tonal Music

The Embedding Problem for Non-Cognitivism; Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press,

A New Approach to the Paradox of Fiction Pete Faulconbridge

A Succession of Feelings, in and of Itself, is Not a Feeling of Succession

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Musical Meaning and String Quartets

A DEFENCE OF AN INSTITUTIONAL ANALYSIS OF ART ELIZABETH HEMSLEY UNIVERSITY OF EDINBURGH

The Unity of the Manifest and Scientific Image by Self-Representation *

The Problem of Known Illusion and the Resemblance of Experience to Reality. 20 minute presentation. target 2000 words.

Art, Mind and Cognitive Science

THE FICTION OF FICTIONALISM

Two-Dimensional Semantics the Basics

Perceptions and Hallucinations

Four Theories of Amodal Perception

4 Embodied Phenomenology and Narratives

Chudnoff on the Awareness of Abstract Objects 1

WHAT IS WRONG WITH THE RELATIONAL THEORY OF CHANGE? Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra Hertford College, Oxford

Introduction. Fiora Salis University of Lisbon

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Against the Intrinsic Value of Pleasure

Five Theses on De Re States and Attitudes* Tyler Burge

CONRAD AND IMPRESSIONISM JOHN G. PETERS

I n t r o d u c t i o n t o a n d C o m m e n t a r y o n J e n n i f e r H o r n s b y s Truth: The Identity Theory GILA SHER

Diachronic and synchronic unity

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO INSTRUCTORSHIPS IN PHILOSOPHY CUPE Local 3902, Unit 1 SUMMER SESSION 2019

Pictures, Perspective and Possibility 1

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

RESPONSE AND REJOINDER

24.500/Phil253 topics in philosophy of mind/perceptual experience

6AANB th Century Continental Philosophy. Basic information. Module description. Assessment methods and deadlines. Syllabus Academic year 2016/17

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

What s Really Disgusting

Review of Carolyn Korsmeyer, Savoring Disgust: The foul and the fair. in aesthetics (Oxford University Press pp (PBK).

Symposium on Disjunctivism Philosophical Explorations

A Confusion of the term Subjectivity in the philosophy of Mind *

IS THE SENSE-DATA THEORY A REPRESENTATIONALIST THEORY? Fiona Macpherson

All Roads Lead to Violations of Countable Additivity

Moral Judgment and Emotions

Emotion, an Organ of Happiness. Ruey-Yuan Wu National Tsing-Hua University

Naturalizing Phenomenology? Dretske on Qualia*

A Higher-order, Dispositional Theory of Qualia. John O Dea. Abstract

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Faculty of Philosophy, University of Cambridge Part IB: Metaphysics & Epistemology

The Culpable Inability Problem for Synchronic and Diachronic Ought Implies Can

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall Class #7 Final Thoughts on Frege on Sense and Reference

A Functional Representation of Fuzzy Preferences

ARTEFACTUALISM AS AN ONTOLOGY OF ART

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

PART ONE: PHILOSOPHY AND THE OTHER MINDS

Perceptual Considerations in Designing and Fitting Hearing Aids for Music Published on Friday, 14 March :01

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN:

On The Search for a Perfect Language

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995.

Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science

By Tetsushi Hirano. PHENOMENOLOGY at the University College of Dublin on June 21 st 2013)

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

Beyond A- and B-Time Reconsidered

CHAPTER 15. Five Theses on De Re States and Attitudes. Tyler Burge

Transcription:

SNP Best-set Typesetter Ltd. Journal Code: ANAL Proofreader: Elsie Article No.: 583 Delivery Date: 31 October 2005 Page Extent: 4 pp

anal_580-594.fm Page 22 Monday, October 31, 2005 6:10 PM 22 andy clark Geach, P. 1967. Intentional identity. Journal of Philosophy 74: 627 32. Reprinted in his Logic Matters, 146 53. Oxford: Basil Blackwell 1972. Henkin, L. 1961. Some remarks on infinitely long formulae. In Infinitistic Methods, 167 83. New York: Pergamon Press. Hintikka, J. 1974. Quantifiers vs. quantification theory. Linguistic Inquiry 5: 153 77. Hintikka, J. 1976. Partially ordered quantifiers vs. partially ordered ideas. Dialectica 30: 89 99. Krynicki, M. and M. Mostowski 1995. Henkin quantifiers. In Quantifiers: Logics, Models and Computation, Volume I, ed. M. Krynicki et al., 193 262. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Quine, W. V. 1969. Existence and quantification. In his Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, 91 113. New York: University of Columbia Press. Walton, K. L. 1990. Mimesis as Make-Believe. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Wiggins, D. 1995. The Kant-Frege-Russell view of existence: toward the rehabilitation of the second-level view. In Modality, Morality and Belief. Essays in Honor of Ruth Barcan Marcus, ed. W. Sinnott-Armstrong, D. Raffman and N. Asher, 93 116. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Blackwell Publishing Ltd.Oxford, UK and Malden, USAANALAnalysis0003-26382005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.January 20066612225ArticlesAndy Clark That lonesome whistle That lonesome whistle: a puzzle for the sensorimotor model of perceptual experience Andy Clark Might perceptual experience consist in an agent s expectations concerning the ways sensory stimulation will vary with movement? Such, in barest outline, is the intriguing proposal of the sensorimotor model of perceptual experience (also known as sensorimotor contingency theory ) (O Regan and Noë 2001, Noë 2004). Thus consider a certain visual shape. According to O Regan and Noë: the visual quality of [that very] shape is precisely the set of all potential distortions that the shape undergoes when it is moved relative to us, or when we move relative to it. (O Regan and Noë 2001: 942. Emphasis in original) This account, we are told, yields a satisfying explanation of perceptual presence: the sense that we have of, for example, right now seeing a whole tomato even though only one side is currently stimulating the retina. The sensorimotor model depicts this sense of presence as rooted in knowledge of patterns of sensorimotor contingency, e.g. our implicit understanding Analysis 66.1, January 2006, pp. 22 25. Andy Clark

anal_580-594.fm Page 23 Monday, October 31, 2005 6:10 PM that lonesome whistle 23 (our expectation) that movements of our body to the left or right, say, will bring further bits of the tomato into view (Noë 2004: 63). The same general argument is deployed to give an account of the perceptual presence of detail in the visual scene: we implicitly know how eye and head movements would bring different details into focus (2004: 55 59) and this known pattern of accessibility yields (or better, constitutes) our veridical experience of detail. But consider a case of perception in a non-visual modality. In particular, consider the following description of the auditory perception of a long and drawn-out sound such as a sustained note in an opera: There you are at the opera house. The soprano has just hit her high note a glass shattering high C that fills the hall and she holds it. She holds it. She holds it. She holds it. She holds it. She holds the note for such a long time that after a while a funny thing happens: you no longer seem only to hear it, the note as it is currently sounding... in addition, you also seem to hear something more... the note now sounds like it has been going on for a very long time... what you hear no longer seems to be limited to the pitch, timbre, loudness and other strictly audible qualities of the note. You seem in addition to experience, even to hear, something about its temporal extent. (Kelly Forthcoming: ms: 1) This description strikes me as phenomenologically accurate, and very close in spirit to the descriptions Noë himself gives of the perceptual presence of that which is strictly speaking out of present view. Yet the case poses a prima facie challenge. If the perceptual experience depicts the sound as, in some real sense, right now (this instant) sounding as if it has been going on for a long time, then this is one case where we cannot, even in principle, unpack that aspect of the phenomenology by invoking capacities of access or exploration. For that which makes the note long is all in the past (we can assume it is ending right now) and simply cannot be present to perception as accessible (Noë 2004: 63). There is, in short, a prima facie problem in accounting for the feeling of presence of a note that literally sounds as if it has been going on for a long time. It seems that we cannot do so by appeal to any sense of the potential availability of the missing parts of the temporally extended sound stream, nor can we know (indeed, it is barely intelligible to ask) how those missing parts of the soundstream would vary or come into focus as we move our head or body. A first response, on the part of the fan of the sensorimotor model, might be to try to explain the phenomenology by appeal to more advanced aspects of (in this case) our acquired musical understanding. Thus Noë (personal communication) compares the case to the hearing of

anal_580-594.fm Page 24 Monday, October 31, 2005 6:10 PM 24 andy clark speech. When we hear speech (in a language we know) we seem to hear meanings as well as sound. Similarly, perhaps we have here a kind of musical understanding that allows us to assimilate the final note to a temporally extended pattern. The test for this proposal, Noë suggests, would be that such effects should not occur for non-music or non-speech sounds. But surely we do get the very same effects in domains where this appeal to more recondite forms of understanding (even assuming that such an appeal is not itself in danger of compromising the sensorimotor model) is not plausible. Thus consider the child who hears, for the first time, the long drawn out wail of the steam-whistle of an American locomotive. The child will, I submit, experience the wail (towards the end) as having been going on for a long time. But in this case there is (let s assume) no body of acquired steam-whistle understanding underpinning this experience. Noë (personal communication) disputes this possibility. Either, he suggests, the experience must present itself to the child as white noise or she must fit the sensory inputs into some pattern of sensory expectations. It is easy to see why the proponent of a sensorimotor model is forced into such a view. For there is a general puzzle, for such accounts, concerning first-time or genuinely novel experiences. In such cases there seems to be no background of sensorimotor understanding available to support (to constitute, on these accounts) the perceptual experience. But there seems to be no reason (apart from prior acceptance of the very model that the examples aim to call into question) to assume that we cannot experience a totally novel soundstream as structured, or a novel shape as shaped, or a novel taste as tasting thus-and-so, and so on. As it happens, I remember quite vividly the first time I heard a steam whistle, and it was not white noise that I heard. Indeed, I would venture to suggest that steam whistles still sound the same to me as when I first heard one: a result that seems doubly incompatible with any model that assimilates my experience to expectations concerning sensorimotor dependencies. It seems doubly incompatible because first, it should not have sounded like structured noise the first time around, and second, because, although I now have expectations that I then lacked, it still (or so I claim) sounds the same to me as it did then. The case of the first-time steam whistle thus combines several challenges for the sensorimotor model in a single package. First, there is the need to account for novel perceptual experience. A corollary of this is the need to allow for the possibility of having structured perceptual experiences while learning the sensorimotor contingencies themselves. Second, there is the need to allow for sameness of later experience despite changes in our sensory expectations. And third, there is the need to accommodate

anal_580-594.fm Page 25 Monday, October 31, 2005 6:10 PM that lonesome whistle 25 cases where our sense of the missing parts, that seem nonetheless to be informing some experience, cannot be unpacked by reference to any potential for bringing such parts into view (such parts being now in the past). A more general lesson, I think, is that not all forms of mature perceptual experience look equally likely to involve (in any profound or potentially constitutive fashion) expectations concerning the results of active exploration. Thus consider the feeling of orgasm, the taste of a chili pepper, or the pain of a toothache. While there are no doubt many ways in which such experiences will morph and alter in response to subtle movements of the body, it seems far less plausible to suppose that the perceptual experiences themselves are, in these cases, fully (or even partially) constituted by our expectations concerning the ways movement would bring about such effects. So how should we accommodate the case of the lonesome steam whistle? The very simplest way to do so would be a straightforward appeal to representational content. As the sound continues, we begin (even, indeed perhaps especially, on first hearing) to represent it as having been going on for a long while. That is, after all, just how it sounds! But there are other options too. The perceptual experience might gain its character not from some simple representational tokening, but from the way we are disposed to identify the sound with other (equally long and drawn out) sounds, from the way we are disposed to reproduce the sound, by means of a long drawn out whistle that we ourselves make, and so on. That is to say, we might seek an account (such as Pettit 2003) that is still broadly speaking skill-based, but that depicts the skills in question as skills of matching, sifting, sorting, re-identifying and the like rather than as skills of active exploration or by appeal to detailed expectations concerning how sensory stimulation would vary with movement. One way or another though, a satisfying account of perceptual experience should surely make room for that lonesome whistle. School of Philosophy, Psychology and Language Sciences (PPLS) University of Edinburgh Edinburgh EH8 9JX, UK andy.clark@ed.ac.uk References Kelly, S. Forthcoming. The puzzle of temporal experience. In Philosophy and Neuroscience, ed. A. Brook and K. Akins. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Noë, A. 2004. Action in Perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. O Regan, J. K. and A. Noë. 2001. A sensorimotor approach to vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24: 939 73. Pettit, P. 2003. Looks as powers. Philosophical Issues 13: 221 52.