HISTORY OF ECONOMIC IDEAS HEI

Similar documents
The Shimer School Core Curriculum

Book Reviews: 'The Concept of Nature in Marx', & 'Alienation - Marx s Conception of Man in Capitalist Society'

Thomas Kuhn's "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions"

Writing an Honors Preface

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

CLASSICAL SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

Political Economy I, Fall 2014

The Meaning of Abstract and Concrete in Hegel and Marx

ADAM SMITH S ECONOMICS AND THE LECTURES ON RHETORIC AND BELLES LETTRES. THE LANGUAGE OF COMMERCE

Chapter 2: Karl Marx Test Bank

Marx, Gender, and Human Emancipation

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought

Louis Althusser s Centrism

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

UNIVERSITY OF WISCONSIN Department of History. Seminar on the Marxist Theory of History

Marxism and Education. Series Editor Anthony Green Institute of Education University of London London, United Kingdom

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Critical Theory for Research on Librarianship (RoL)

Oberlin College Department of Politics. Politics 218: Marxian Analysis of Society and Politics Fall 2011 Professor Marc Blecher

CUA. National Catholic School of Social Service Washington, DC Fax

Professor John Hall Spring Term 2013

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

THE RELATIONS BETWEEN ETHICS AND ECONOMICS: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS BETWEEN AYRES AND WEBER S PERSPECTIVES. By Nuria Toledano and Crispen Karanda

M E M O. When the book is published, the University of Guelph will be acknowledged for their support (in the acknowledgements section of the book).

Marx: A Very Short Introduction Free Download pdf

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

Louis Althusser, What is Practice?

Decolonizing Development Colonial Power and the Maya Edited by Joel Wainwright Copyright by Joel Wainwright. Conclusion

KARL MARXS THEORY REVOLUTION PDF

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

Review of Louis Althusser and the traditions of French Marxism

Gender, the Family and 'The German Ideology'

Is Capital a Thing? Remarks on Piketty s Concept of Capital

THE JOURNAL OF EPIGRAPHIC STUDIES

8/28/2008. An instance of great change or alteration in affairs or in some particular thing. (1450)

Watcharabon Buddharaksa. The University of York. RCAPS Working Paper No January 2011

Hegel and the French Revolution

PH 327 GREAT PHILOSOPHERS. Instructorà William Lewis; x5402, Ladd 216; Office Hours: By apt.

Marxist Criticism. Critical Approach to Literature

Value and Price in Marx's Capital [1] David Yaffe, Revolutionary Communist, n 1, 1974, pp31-49.

A Contribution to the Critique of the Political Economy of Academic Labour

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

[T]here is a social definition of culture, in which culture is a description of a particular way of life. (Williams, The analysis of culture )

History 495: Religion, Politics, and Society In Modern U.S. History T/Th 12:00-1:15, UNIV 301

Review of Maynard Keynes, An Economist's Biography by D. Moggridge

CANZONIERE VENTOUX PETRARCH S AND MOUNT. by Anjali Lai

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Philosophy of Economics

1. Two very different yet related scholars

None DEREE COLLEGE SYLLABUS FOR: PH 4028 KANT AND GERMAN IDEALISM UK LEVEL 6 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3. (Updated SPRING 2016) PREREQUISITES:

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History

The Influence of Chinese and Western Culture on English-Chinese Translation

Choosing your modules (Joint Honours Philosophy) Information for students coming to UEA in 2015, for a Joint Honours Philosophy Programme.

Categories and Schemata

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Critical Spatial Practice Jane Rendell

Lecture 24 Sociology 621 December 12, 2005 MYSTIFICATION

Also by Ben Fine. Marx's Capital

A New Reflection on the Innovative Content of Marxist Theory Based on the Background of Political Reform Juanhui Wei

Philip Joseph Kain. Santa Clara University Scotts Valley, CA Santa Clara, CA fax

Title. Author(s)OHMURA, Izumi. CitationActa Slavica Iaponica, 6: Issue Date Doc URL. Type. File Information

Capitalism And The Dialectic: The Uno-Sekine Approach To Marxian Political Economy. By John R. Bell

PH th Century Philosophy Ryerson University Department of Philosophy Mondays, 3-6pm Fall 2010

Marxism and. Literature RAYMOND WILLIAMS. Oxford New York OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS

OF MARX'S THEORY OF MONEY

Critical Political Economy of Communication and the Problem of Method

Was Marx an Ecologist?

SOC University of New Orleans. Vern Baxter University of New Orleans. University of New Orleans Syllabi.

T.M. Porter, The Rise of Statistical Thinking, Princeton: Princeton University Press, xii pp

Four kinds of incommensurability. Reason, Relativism, and Reality Spring 2005

MARXISM AND EDUCATION

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

The Path Choice of the Chinese Communist Party's Theoretical Innovation under the Perspective of Chinese Traditional Culture

DIALECTICS OF ECONOMICAL BASE AND SOCIO-CULTURAL SUPERSTRUCTURE: A MARXIST PERSPECTIVE

Marx s Theory of Money. Tomás Rotta University of Greenwich, London, UK GPERC marx21.com

Ten Essays in the Development of Economic Thought. Ronald L. Meek Tyler Professor of Economics at the University of Leicester

The Rich Human Being: Marx and the Concept of Real Human. (Paper for Presentation at Marx Conference, 4-8 May 2004 Havana,

The Nature Of Order: An Essay On The Art Of Building And The Nature Of The Universe, Book 1 - The Phenomenon Of Life (Center For Environmental

Introduction: Mills today

Increadible Sociological Reflections On The Neurosciences Advances In Medical Sociology

Asia-Pacific Development Journal Vol. 20, No. 2, December 2013

Unit 02: Revolutionary Period and Persuasive Writing

Course Description. Course objectives

FORUM: QUALITATIVE SOCIAL RESEARCH SOZIALFORSCHUNG

KEY ISSUES IN SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY Dept. of Sociology and Social Anthropology, CEU Autumn 2017

New York University Department of Media, Culture, and Communication Special Topics in Critical Theory: Marx

Philosophy Contemporary Perspectives On Perennial Issues

A Soviet View of Structuralism, Althusser, and Foucault

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

SOCI 301/321 Foundations of Social Thought

"History of Modern Economic Thought"

INTERVIEW: ONTOFORMAT Classical Paradigms and Theoretical Foundations in Contemporary Research in Formal and Material Ontology.

The concept of capital and the determination of the general and uniform rates of profit: a reappraisal

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

MARXIST LITERARY CRITICISM. Literary Theories

The Capitalist Unconscious Marx And Lacan

On Essence and Appearance

Credibility and the Continuing Struggle to Find Truth. We consume a great amount of information in our day-to-day lives, whether it is

Transcription:

issn 1122-8792 electronic issn 1724-2169 isbn 978-88-6227-340-4 HISTORY OF ECONOMICS IDEAS XVIII/2010/3 HISTORY OF ECONOMIC IDEAS HEI offprint XVIII/2010/3 Fabrizio Serra editore Pisa Roma

HISTORY OF ECONOMIC IDEAS History of Economic Ideas Online www.historyofeconomicideas.com Editors: Riccardo Faucci (University of Pisa) Roberto Marchionatti (University of Turin) Editorial Board: Richard Arena (University of Nice), Duccio Cavalieri (University of Florence), Marco Dardi (University of Florence), Peter D. Groenewegen (University of Sydney), Hansjörg Klausinger(University of Vienna), Enzo Pesciarelli (University of Ancona), Christian Seidl (University of Kiel) Advisory Board: M. M. Augello (University of Pisa),G. Becattini (University of Florence), A. A. Brewer (University of Bristol), B. J. Caldwell (Duke University), A. L. Cot (University of Paris i), N. De Vecchi (University of Pavia), R. W. Dimand (Brock University), S. Fiori (University of Turin), G. C. Harcourt (University of Cambridge, uk), A. Karayiannis (University of Piraeus), B. Ingrao (University of Rome «La Sapienza»), J. E. King (La Trobe University), S. Perri (University of Macerata), C. Perrotta (University of Lecce), P. L. Porta (University of Milan Bicocca), T. Raffaelli (University of Pisa), A. Salanti (University of Bergamo), W. J. Samuels (Michigan State University), A. S. Skinner (University of Glasgow), J. K. Whitaker (University of Virginia) Book Review Editor: Nicola Giocoli (University of Pisa) Editorial Assistants: Giandomenica Becchio (University of Turin) Giulia Bianchi (University of Pisa) Address: The Editor, History of Economic Ideas, Dipartimento di Scienze Economiche, Facoltà di Giurisprudenza, Via Curtatone e Montanara 15, i 56126 Pisa, tel. +39 050 2212845, fax +39 050 2212853, hei@ec.unipi.it History of Economic Ideas is an international peer-reviewed journal and it is indexed and abstracted in Current Contents/Arts & HumanitiesArt & Humanities Citation Index,, Social Science Citation Index and Journal Citation Report/Social Science Edition (isi Thomson Reuters). The econtent is archived with Clockss and Portico.

«History of Economic Ideas», xviii/2010/3 A SENTIMENTAL JOURNEY THROUGH MARXIAN ECONOMICS Sasan Fayazmanesh* California State University, Fresno Department of Economics A review essay on Michael A. Lebowitz, Following Marx: Method, Critique and Crisis, Leiden-Boston, Brill, 2009. N early a quarter of a century ago, I wrote a doctoral dissertation titled The Commodity as the Point of Departure of Capital: A Methodological Inquiry. This was an inquiry into how and why Marx began his Capital with «the commodity», a point of departure which appeared to be problematic and created numerous controversies. My work dealt with various aspects of Marx s method. Among these were numerous plans that Marx drafted in Grundrisse for writing his economic manuscript, the formation of the concept of commodity in Grundrisse, Marx s search for a proper beginning point, his distinction between scientific knowledge and common sense, and his method of presentation of the commodity as opposed to his method of inquiry. After finishing my dissertation, I revised it for publication. But, I «abandoned the manuscript to the gnawing criticism of the mice», to use Marx s explanation of what became of the criticism of post-hegelian philosophy that he wrote jointly with Engels.1 I felt that I had achieved my «main purpose self-clarification», as Marx explained further. I did continue to write a few pieces on Marx s method afterward.2 But, my youthful exuberance with Marxian economics somewhat faded as the years went by. There were several reasons for becoming less enchanted with Marxian economics. Among these was the sectarianism that is often associated with the name «Marx». Even though such sectarianism is found among the followers of many famous economists, it is more acute when it comes to Marx and Marxism. Marxism is, of course, somewhat akin to religion. Marx, as is well known, protested against French Marxists by stating that he is not a Marxist.3 His motto was also De omnibus dubitandum. Yet, there are many Marxists who have faith in Marx. They religiously and passionately follow * Address for correspondence: S. Fayazmanesh: sasanf@csufresno.edu 1 K. Marx, A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, New York, International Publishers, 1976, 22. 2 See, for example, «Marx s Semantics and the Logic of the Derivation of Value», Research in the History of Economic Thought and Methodology, v. 12, 1994, 65-91. 3 Marx-Engels Selected Correspondence, August 5, 1890, Moscow, Progress Publisher, 1975, 392-394.

210 Sasan Fayazmanesh every word of the master and never doubt anything that he has written. These Marxists repeatedly quote Marx s works in support of their own interpretation, as if the scripture was read and interpreted. On the other side, of course, there are the anti-marxists, those who detest everything that Marx has ever written, even if they have hardly read or understood any of it. They, too, quote a line or two from Marx, usually taken out of context, to prove how false the prophet was. In this religious climate those who believe in De omnibus dubitandum, and who might read Marx seriously but critically, could easily become alienated and fade away. Another possible reason for disenchantment could be the fact that there has been very little growth in the Marxian economics research agenda since the publication of Capital in 1867. Many of the issues discussed today appear to be the same as those discussed over a century ago. The falling rate of profit, transformation problem, derivation of value, young Marx versus mature Marx, Marx s debt to Hegel, and various points related to Marx s method, such as the distinction between essence and appearance, seem to be themes as dominant in the twenty-first century as they were in the twentieth century, or even in the nineteenth century. There seems to be no new discussions, vistas, discoveries, or growth of knowledge in the field of Marxian economics. To be sure, in the late twentieth century there were some seemingly novel research agendas, such as analytical Marxism. But, on a closer look these were mostly fluff, intended to give Marx, or perhaps the analytical Marxists, an aura of bourgeois respectability. There could, of course, be various other reasons for losing youthful exuberance when it comes to Marxian economics. For example, many young Marxist economists received their knowledge of history of economic thought and economic history through Marx. And Marx had the habit of reading history after his own theory. But, as one gets older, it becomes possible to read the history of economic thought and economic history independent of Marx. This might actually allow one to situate Marx himself in a broader context, both historically and theoretically. For example, looking back at the history of the development of labor theory of value it is easy to see how this theory could be used in the mid-nineteenth century to explain the revolutionary sentiment of the working class in Europe. In particular, given the role of the workers in such situations as the European Revolutions of 1848 or the Paris Commune of 1871, it is not difficult to see the reason for Marx s attraction to the labor theory of value, a theory which had the potential to explain the revolutionary tendencies of the working class at the time. Furthermore, reflecting on the history of Scientific Revolution, from Copernicus to Newton, it is not hard to notice the obsession of economic thinkers with science and scientific method of analysis. Economics, since the age of Physiocracy, has been slave to natural sciences and, particularly, to the Newtonian and energetic physics. Marx, one might argue, did not escape this obsession with scientism. Whatever the reason for shying away from Marxism, and becoming less exuberant about Marxian economics, it is hard to stay away from Marx for too long. Marx was indeed one of the main intellectual forces of the nine-

A sentimental journey through Marxian economics 211 teenth century who cannot be ignored. His name is bound to come up whenever three or four great economists of all time are mentioned. His uncompromising stance toward the ills of the capitalist economy, his biting criticism of bourgeois society, his insights, his discipline and determination to write a comprehensive critique of political economy, his prolific writing, his sharp wit and bitter sarcasm are such that sooner or later one is bound to grab one of his books to look up a passage or a quotation. Thus, after years of not reading much on Marxian economics, I looked forward to reading Following Marx: Method, Critique and Crisis by Michael A. Lebowitz. I hoped the book would acquaint me with any recent developments in the field of Marxian economics and excite me about reentry into the field. I did not get what I had hoped for, but I did take a sentimental journey through some of the popular Marxist literature of the second half of the twentieth century. Following Marx is a collection of various essays written in different periods, with different aims. Some of these essays are decades old, so old that Paul Craig Roberts gets a dishonorable mention in one article as a rightwing economist and Patrick Clawson an honorable mention or two as a leftwing economist. The former, of course, is nowadays writing for such outlets as CounterPunch and Antiwar.com, outlets that have been engaged in a struggle against us and Israeli policies of sanctions and wars in the Middle East. The latter, however, is the director of the Washington Institute for Near East Policy, a think tank affiliate of the American Israel Public Affairs Committee that promotes us and Israeli policies in the Middle East. Yet, some of these old articles are quite interesting for different generations of economic thinkers. For the old, as alluded to earlier, it is a nostalgic journey through much of the discussions and debates that went on in the second half of the twentieth century. For the new, these are some lessons in the history of Marxian economics. As a collection of essays, one should not look for a continuous and wellarticulated narrative in Following Marx. The author also does not follow one of the most interesting aspects of Marx s method of analysis, namely, first dealing with the theory and then reading the history of the theory. The fivepart, 19-chapter book jumps from one subject matter to another. The author himself suggests that if the reader is interested in continuity of certain subject matters for example, in Marx s method of analysis not reading the chapters sequentially, and skipping some in between, might be helpful. The lack of continuity makes the review of the book difficult. It might be best to follow the author s suggestion and read the chapters on methodology chs 1, 5, 6, 10 and 11 separately. After all, these appear to be the most important chapters in Following Marx, with some unifying concepts. Chapter 1, the «Fallacy of Everyday Notions», begins with the fallacy of composition. Lebowitz argues that Marx was well aware of this fallacy and criticized «any theory which proceeds from particular cases to establish general principles» (p. 7). Marx, the author writes, held that «the whole is not sum of the individual parts taken separately». Lebowitz sees a close relation between this knowledge and knowing «that the way things appear to the individual actors actually involved cannot be the basis for understanding of the whole». «There is in short, a big difference between Appearance and

212 Sasan Fayazmanesh Essence», writes Lebowitz (ibidem). Much of the chapter is devoted to the issue of how things appear to the «actual agents of capitalist production», particularly in competition between capitals, and how the «vulgar economists» translate the «everyday notions» of these agents (p. 10). «The apparent movement of the sun around the earth» is used as the analogy to show how «everyday notions», even though «rooted in the real conditions facing individual capitals», persist (ibidem). The same analogy appears later again and again. neoclassical economics is seen here as a perfect example of vulgar economics, since «it starts from the way that things appear to the individual actors» and its assumptions are drawn «from appearances» (pp. 11-12). Lebowitz argues that going beyond the form of appearances of things is essential and quotes Marx as saying: «the essential relation must first be discovered by science» (p. 15). Chapter 5, «Following Hegel: The Science of Marx», returns to some of the same themes as the first chapter, particularly, the issue of appearance and essence. Marx s famous passage that «all science would be superfluous if the form of appearance of things coincided with their essence» is quoted and the movement of the Earth around the Sun is mentioned a number of times. «What made Marx so sensitive to the gap between essence and appearance?» asks Lebowitz (p. 72). And he answers by stating that «we cannot ignore the importance of Hegel» and his Science of Logic (ibidem). The answer is backed by an appeal to Lenin and his claim that understanding Marx s Capital is impossible without understanding the whole of Hegel s Logic. Marx s discussion of «scientifically correct method» of political economy at the beginning of Grundrisse namely, the method of «rising from the abstract to the concrete» is also mentioned in this chapter. The origin of this aspect of Marx s method, too, is seen to be Hegel. Moreover, Lebowitz believes that all such aspects of «scientifically correct method» were already present in embryo in the «young Marx s critique of political economy». Indeed, he argues there is «so much that can be found in the young Marx which helps us to understand Capital» (p. 79). Yet, Lebowitz argues, in 1844 Marx «began from the theories of political economists» rather than «real concrete», and it was not until 1857, when writing notebooks for his Grundrisse, that Marx absorbed himself in «real economic movements» (p. 80). Marx now reread Hegel s Logic and found it of «great use» in «method of treatment». According to Lebowitz, while Marx «was referring particularly at the time to his examination of the rate of profit, in fact the deepening of the influence of Hegel s dialectical method is evident throughout the Grundrisse» (ibidem).1 The Hegelian dialectical method leads Marx to begin his journey to understand capitalism with the «commodity», writes Lebowitz. This was an «obvious choice» for the point of departure, since Marx had a «growing recognition that the purchase of labor-power as a commodity is a unique characteristic of capitalism» (p. 81). From this concrete beginning, Marx went on, by way of ab- 1 Actually, Marx s letter refers to profit and not rate of profit: «I have overthrown the whole doctrine of profit as it has existed up to now» (Marx-Engels Selected Correspondence, 14 January, 1858, Moscow, Progress Publisher, 1975), 93.

A sentimental journey through Marxian economics 213 straction, to develop «concrete totality» (ibidem). In this Hegelian dialectical method Marx «discovers money as latent within the commodity» (p. 83). According to Lebowitz, «it is possible indeed to present Marx s dialectical derivation (in this case from the commodity to money) in a blatantly Hegelian manner namely, one that does far more than coquette with Hegel s mode of expression» (ibidem). Chapter 6, «Explorations in the Logic of Capital», apparently written in the 1970s as lecture notes, is mostly a Hegelian reading of the first few chapters of Capital dealing with the circuits C-M-C and M-C-M. Statements such as «exchange is the truth of the commodity», it «is Becoming of the commodity as a thing-in-and for-itself», or the «commodity is not a thing at rest; it is motion and its activity is the process of exchange», show the Hegelian flavor of this chapter. Chapter 10, «Marx s Methodological Project» continues with the theme of «Essence and Appearance» in the Hegelian sense. «Essence must appear», the author quotes Hegel (p. 196). The issue then becomes how «capital as a whole», or the «Essence», appears. This is where the 3rd volume of Capital enters the picture. Here surplus value, as Essence, appears on the surface as profit, and «inner connections revealed through the concept of value» are «obliterated when considering market prices and prices of production (the law or average around which market prices gravitate)» (p. 198). The discussion ends with dividing «Marx s methodological project as a whole» into four «moments». Moment i, observation of concrete; Moment ii, abstract thought; Moment iii, unity of Essence of Appearance; and Moment iv, «testing-reconciliation of the concept with its object» (pp. 199-203). Throughout this discussion, once again, Lenin is called upon to support the Hegelian reading of Marx. Chapter 11, «What is Competition», deals with how «inner truth» appears as competition between capitals (p. 206). The reading continues to be Hegelian and, therefore, Marx s volume iii of Capital where capital in general is divided and appears as many competing capitals is viewed as «Moment iii of Marx s methodological project» (p. 208). Marx s famous statement that a «scientific analysis of competition is possible if we can grasp the inner nature of capital» is repeated and the analogy of the apparent movement of the Sun around the Earth is recalled a number of times. «Insofar as capital exists in the form of many capitals», writes the author, «science is necessary». Much of Lebowitz s discussion concerning Marx s method of analysis, especially the issue of «essence and appearance», is well known to the students of Marx and commonly discussed in Marxian economics courses. Perhaps less common is a consistent Hegelian reading of Marx s method of analysis. In the 1st volume of Capital Marx explained that nearly thirty years earlier he had criticized the «mystifying side of Hegelian dialectic». But, when Hegel was treated as a «dead dog», Marx went on to say, I «openly avowed myself the pupil of that mighty thinker, and even, here and there in the chapter on the theory of value, coquetted with the mode of expression peculiar to him».1 1 K. Marx, Capital, vol. 1, New York, Vintage Books, 1977, 102-103.

214 Sasan Fayazmanesh Many Hegelians, however, don t take Marx s no for an answer and believe that he did much more than simply coquette with Hegel s mode of expression. Marx, they assert, basically followed Hegel s Logic. Sometimes the authority of V. I. Lenin is used to support this contention, as if Lenin was a great expert in analyzing Marx s Capital. As I have argued in some of my writings, there is little evidence that Marx did anything more than what he said he did, namely, coquette a bit with the mode of expression peculiar to Hegel in the chapter on the theory of value. Indeed, a careful reading of Grundrisse, which was primarily the focus of my earlier research, shows that both in terms of economic concepts and method of analysis Marx started as no more than a Ricardian and finished the work as something very different. Marx s new theory and method of analysis was due mostly to reworking for himself the puzzle of the capitalist economy and not the appropriation of Hegel s Logic. If the latter was the case, we would have seen in Grundrisse the development of a relatively straight forward theory and plan for presenting an economic manuscript. What we see instead is a gradual development of an embryonic theory and numerous, changing, and, at times, incongruent plans for an economic manuscript. For example, Marx s ultimate decision to start Capital with the «commodity», contrary to Lebowitz s assertion was anything but an «obvious choice». Anyone who has closely followed Marx s twists and turns in Grundrisse to find a proper beginning point, or has followed numerous controversies that have surrounded Marx s multiple points of departure in Capital, can attest to the fact that his ultimate choice was not an obvious and trouble-free one. Hegel also cannot be the source of Marx s distinction between the socalled essence and appearance, a distinction that actually could best be expressed as one between scientific knowledge and sense perception of reality. This distinction does not exist, at least blatantly, in Marx s writings prior to Grundrisse, even though Marx knew Hegel s Logic. We can t find the distinction at the beginning of Grundrisse either. It is only after Marx had started to solve for himself the riddle of the capitalist economy in Grundrisse that the distinction starts to appear; and it becomes stronger in Marx s later writings. As I once traced the distinction, starting from the middle of Grundrisse to the end of his more mature economic writings, there are, respectively, at least 58 and 43 different expressions that Marx uses to designate, refer to, or describe sense perception and scientific knowledge. It is hard to imagine this multiplicity of expressions if Marx had simply appropriated Hegel s «Essence and Appearance». Moreover, the distinction between scientific knowledge and sense perception of the reality is much older than Hegel s Logic; it goes back to the Scientific Revolution and, particularly, the Copernican revolution. Consider, for example, this statement in Galileo s Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems: I can never «sufficiently admire the acumen of those who have taken hold of this opinion [the heliocentric view] and accepted it as true; they have through sheer force of intellect done such violence to their own senses as to prefer what reason told them over that which sensible experience plainly showed them to the contrary». Some economists, even before Marx, were

A sentimental journey through Marxian economics 215 familiar with these notions and even tried to emulate the method of analysis employed in physics and astronomy. For example, in his Essays on the History of Astronomy, Adam Smith stated that the «learned give up the evidence of their senses to preserve the coherence of the ideas of their imagination».1 Or, he stated that there is a propensity, natural to all men, «to account for all appearances from as few principles as possible».2 As such, Smith praised Newton and Newtonian system for laying «down certain principles known or proved in the beginning, from whence we account for several phenomena, connecting all together by the same chain».3 This was, indeed, what Smith tried to do in The Wealth of Nations before he adopted the «vulgar» method of analysis. Marx, too, was familiar with such notions and that is why, when discussing scientific knowledge, he often used the analogy of the movement of the Earth around the Sun. Indeed, in developing the distinction between the so-called scientific knowledge of the capitalist society and sense perception of it, Marx perfected the Copernican-Galilean-Newtonian method of analysis in economics. However, the influence of physics on economics did not end with Marx. Physics became entangled with neoclassical economics in different ways. For example, in developing utility theory, as I have argued in different places, neoclassical economics simply asked: What is the economic interpretation of the path of a trajectory and its time rate of change? Energetic physics, too, exerted considerable influence on the development of neoclassical theories.4 Given such ties to physics, a methodological analysis of neoclassical economics becomes far more complicated than treating it as merely «vulgar» economics, as Lebowitz does. Indeed, these ties would pose some interesting questions: Why has there been so much fascination in economics with natural sciences, particularly physics, and can there ever be a theory of the capitalist economy that is non-scientific? Actually, certain parts of Marx s Capital that are merely reflecting history show us the direction in which such a theory might be developed.5 In sum, the most important chapters in Following Marx, those dealing with methodology, seem to treat Marx s method of investigation and presentation in a simple way, setting aside complex issues. The rest of the book, as stated earlier, is a mix of different papers, written in different times, with little unifying themes. The topics dealt with include criticisms of neo-ricardians and «analytical Marxists», arguments concerning the falling rate of profit and 1 A. Smith, Essays on Philosophical Subjects, ed. by W. P. D. Wightman and J. C. Bryce, vol. iii of the Glasgow Edition of the Works and Correspondence of Adam Smith, Indianapolis, Liberty Fund, 1982, 61. 2 Idem, Theories of Moral Sentiments, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1976 [1759], 14. 3 Idem, Lectures on Rhetoric and Belles Letters, ed. by J. C. Bryce, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1983. 4 See, for example, Ph. Mirowski, More Heat than Light, New York, Cambridge University Press, 1989. 5 See S. Fayazmanesh, Money and Exchange: Folktales and Reality, London, Routledge, 2006, particularly the discussion concerning Marx s distinction between «dialectical» and «historical» method of analysis.

216 Sasan Fayazmanesh Marx s theory of crisis in general, a biographical discussion of Paul Sweezy and his economic contributions, a critique of an obscure theory called «blindspot» paradigm, an assessment of Baran-Sweezy s theory of monopoly capital, another critique of «analytical Marxism», and a critique of Robert Brenner s analysis of global crisis in the late 1990s. The last four chapters, including one on «Uno-ism», are the only chapters in which Lebowitz presents a critical analysis of Marx and some Marxists. The critique is based on what Lebowitz considers to be the «silence of Capital» or «one-sided Marxism». He argues that Capital concentrates too much on capital, leaving out the «worker as subject» and «class struggle» (pp. 311 and 356). Marx, as Lebowitz points out, had planned to write a separate book on «wage-labor». The book, according to Marx s letter to Engels, on April 2, 1858, was to appear in the series: «1. On Capital. 2. Landed Property. 3. Wage Labor. 4. State. 5. International Trade. 6. World Market». Marx explained the order by arguing that the transition from capital to landed property and wage-labor «is not only dialectical but historical».1 This was all in accord with his concept of «scientific method» of presentation. However, Marx never finished his project and never wrote the book on wage-labor. Why this was the case, we may never know. Lebowitz, however, has an answer: «the completion of his [Marx s] epistemological project interested him less than his revolutionary project» (p. 358). That is, Marx was more a revolutionist than a scientist. But this is odd, given Lebowitz s earlier and repeated praises for Marx the scientist. I believe that Marx himself bears some responsibility for this oddity, since it is not clear whether the science of political economy which resembles Newtonian physics and astronomy should be dispassionate, or whether it should take sides in the class struggle between capital and wage-labor. The problem, it seems, goes to the very heart of Marxian economics, which, as I stated earlier, shares with all other modern schools of economic theory an obsession with being scientific. Hopefully, if I take another journey through Marxian economics, I will see a discussion of this important issue. 1 Marx-Engels Selected Correspondence, Moscow, Progress Publisher, 1975, 97.

CONTENTS papers Erdem Ozgur, Charles Babbage: an inadvertent development economist 11 Steven Kates, Influencing Keynes: the intellectual origins of the General Theory 33 paul a. samuelson (1915-2009): theorist, historian and intellectual Steven G. Medema, Anthony M. C. Waterman, Paul Anthony Samuelson: historian of economic thought 67 Andrew Farrant, Edward McPhail, No good deed goes unpunished? Revisiting the Hayek-Samuelson exchange over Hayek s alleged inevitability thesis 87 Gavin Kennedy, Paul Samuelson and the invention of the modern economics of the Invisible Hand 105 Pedro Garcia Duarte, Beyond Samuelson s chapter on Ramsey 121 Craig Freedman, The Chicago School. A conversation with Paul Samuelson 161 Giuseppe Bertola, Samuelson and switching of techniques 187 reviews article Duccio Cavalieri, Neoliberalism under debate 199 Sasan Fayazmanesh, A sentimental journey through Marxian economics 209 book reviews Marion Fourcade, Economists and Societies. Discipline and Profession in the United States, Britain, & France, 1890s to 1990s (Bianchi) 219 Murray Milgate and Shannon C. Stimson, After Adam Smith: A Century of Transformation in Politics and Political Economy (Rassekh) 223 R. Scazzieri, A. Sen and S. Zamagni (eds), Markets, Money and Capital. Hicksian Economics for the Twenty-first Century (Di Matteo) 226 Cyrille Ferraton, Les valeurs guident et accompagnent notre recherche : L institutionnalisme de Myrdal (Dostaler) 232 Tony Aspromourgos, The Science of Wealth-Adam Smith and the Framing of Political Economy (Vaggi) 234 Michael B. Gill, The British Moralists on Human Nature and the Birth of Secular Ethics (Drakopoulou Dodd) 236

History of Economic Ideas is published three times a year by Fabrizio Serra editore, Pisa Roma, P. O. Box no. 1, Succ. no. 8, i 56123 Pisa, tel. +39 050 542332, fax +39 050 574888, fse@libraweb.net, www.libraweb.net Pisa Offices: Via Santa Bibbiana 28, i 56127 Pisa, fse@libraweb.net Rome Offices: Via Carlo Emanuele I 48, i 00185 Roma, fse.roma@libraweb.net Print and/or Online official subscription rates are available at Publisher s website www.libraweb.net. Reduced rate for eshet members: 95,00; Reduced rate for storep members: 95,00. Subscriptions should be paid as follows: by cheque/international money order payable to Fabrizio Serra editore ; postal giro account no. 17154550; by credit card (American Express, Eurocard, Mastercard, Visa). Copyright 2010 by Fabrizio Serra editore, Pisa Roma. Printed in Italy issn 1122-8792 electronic issn 1724-2169 isbn 978-88-6227-340-4 Direttore responsabile: Lucia Corsi Autorizzazione del Tribunale di Pisa n. 10 del 2/5/1994

Papers: Erdem Ozgur, Charles Babbage: an inadvertent development economist Steven Kates, Influencing Keynes: the intellectual origins of the General Theory Paul A. Samuelson (1915-2009): theorist, historian and intellectual: Steven G. Medema, Anthony M. C. Waterman, Paul Anthony Samuelson: historian of economic thought Andrew Farrant, Edward McPhail, No good deed goes unpunished? Revisiting the Hayek-Samuelson exchange over Hayek s alleged inevitability thesis Gavin Kennedy, Paul Samuelson and the invention of the modern economics of the Invisible Hand Pedro Garcia Duarte, Beyond Samuelson s chapter on Ramsey Craig Freedman, The Chicago School. A conversation with Paul Samuelson Giuseppe Bertola, Samuelson and switching of techniques Reviews Articles: Duccio Cavalieri, Neoliberalism under debate Sasan Fayazmanesh, A sentimental journey through Marxian economics Book Reviews.