Absurd Time: Understanding Camus Quantitative Ethics Through Bergsonian Duration

Similar documents
International Journal of Child, Youth and Family Studies (2014): 5(4.2) MATERIAL ENCOUNTERS. Sylvia Kind

Confronting the Absurd in Notes from Underground. Camus The Myth of Sisyphus discusses the possibility of living in a world full of

Hamletmachine: The Objective Real and the Subjective Fantasy. Heiner Mueller s play Hamletmachine focuses on Shakespeare s Hamlet,

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

Toward a Process Philosophy for Digital Aesthetics

The impact of World War II and literature on the concept of absurdity in the works of Boris Vian

Ingrid Monson, Saying Something. Jazz Improvisation and Interaction (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1996), p

The Spell of the Sensuous Chapter Summaries 1-4 Breakthrough Intensive 2016/2017

Meaning, Being and Expression: A Phenomenological Justification for Interdisciplinary Scholarship

THE MYTH OF SISYPHUS BY ALBERT CAMUS

The phenomenological tradition conceptualizes

Architecture is epistemologically

CHAPTER IV RETROSPECT

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Kant Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics, Preface, excerpts 1 Critique of Pure Reason, excerpts 2 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 9/19/13 12:13 PM

Metaphors we live by. Structural metaphors. Orientational metaphors. A personal summary

Deleuze on the Motion-Image

Sophia Project. Intuition Henri Bergson. Philosophy Archives

CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION. Grey s Anatomy is an American television series created by Shonda Rhimes that has

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

Page 1

CRITICAL THEORY BEYOND NEGATIVITY

Department of Media, Film and Cultural Studies, Lancaster University

An obedient participant in late capitalism explains art

Peter Ely. Volume 3: ISSN: INNERVATE Leading Undergraduate Work in English Studies, Volume 3 ( ), pp

The Theatre of the Absurd

Love, Language and the Dramatization of Ethical Worlds in Deleuze

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Georg Simmel's Sociology of Individuality

The Myth Of Sisyphus & Other Essays By Albert Camus

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

LATOUR, LE CORBUSIER AND SPIRIT OF THE TIME.

The Myth Of Sisyphus And Other Essays By Justin O'Brien, Albert Camus

Phenomenology Glossary

7. This composition is an infinite configuration, which, in our own contemporary artistic context, is a generic totality.

Existentialist Metaphysics PHIL 235 FALL 2011 MWF 2:20-3:20

Human Capital and Information in the Society of Control

(1) Writing Essays: An Overview. Essay Writing: Purposes. Essay Writing: Product. Essay Writing: Process. Writing to Learn Writing to Communicate

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

Rousseau on the Nature of Nature and Political Philosophy

The aim of this paper is to explore Kant s notion of death with special attention paid to

Architecture as the Psyche of a Culture

On the Pursuit of Happiness. Camus creates a uniquely absurdist view through much of his book, The Stranger

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

Post 2 1 April 2015 The Prison-house of Postmodernism On Fredric Jameson s The Aesthetics of Singularity

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

Personal Intervention

Hegel and Neurosis: Idealism, Phenomenology and Realism

The Doctrine of the Mean

ROLAND BARTHES ON WRITING: LITERATURE IS IN ESSENCE

New York University Department of Media, Culture, and Communication Special Topics in Cultural and Visual Studies: DELEUZE S AESTHETICS FALL 2012

But we always make love with worlds : Deleuze (and Guattari) and love

Humanities 116: Philosophical Perspectives on the Humanities

Albert Camus Biography: Part One. Kwabena, Carter, Rong, Dung, Sydney, Brianna

An Introprocession. Hubert Gendron-Blais, Diego Gil, Joel E. Mason

According to Maxwell s second law of thermodynamics, the entropy in a system will increase (it will lose energy) unless new energy is put in.

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

The Years of Uncertainty

Module 4: Theories of translation Lecture 12: Poststructuralist Theories and Translation. The Lecture Contains: Introduction.

1/9. Descartes on Simple Ideas (2)

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

Aristotle on the Human Good

Space is Body Centred. Interview with Sonia Cillari Annet Dekker

Slide 1. Slide 2. Slide 3 Historical Development. Formalism. EH 4301 Spring 2011

Simulated killing. Michael Lacewing

Existential Cause & Individual Experience

Response to Bennett Reimer's "Why Do Humans Value Music?"

Japan Library Association

I love stories. I have for my entire life. They were a constant presence in my life; whether

The Value of Mathematics within the 'Republic'

Wolfgang Tillmans at Fondation Beyeler, Basel

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE

Spatial Formations. Installation Art between Image and Stage.

LANGUAGE THROUGH THE LENS OF HERACLITUS'S LOGOS

What is the Object of Thinking Differently?

Qualitative Design and Measurement Objectives 1. Describe five approaches to questions posed in qualitative research 2. Describe the relationship betw

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

The Power and Wonder of Qualitative Inquiry. Jim Lane, Ed.D. University of Phoenix KWBA Research Symposium July 22, 2017

Archiving Praxis: Dilemmas of documenting installation art in interdisciplinary creative arts praxis

Philosophy of sound, Ch. 1 (English translation)

On Recanati s Mental Files

1/9. The B-Deduction

8. The dialectic of labor and time

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

people who pushed for such an event to happen (the antitheorists) are the same people who

Significant Differences An Interview with Elizabeth Grosz

CRISTINA VEZZARO Being Creative in Literary Translation: A Practical Experience

Mitchell ABOULAFIA, Transcendence. On selfdetermination

Towards a Digital Theory of Affect

In Utilitarianism, John Stuart Mill asserts that the principles of

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Kant IV The Analogies The Schematism updated: 2/2/12. Reading: 78-88, In General

Pierre Hadot on Philosophy as a Way of Life. Pierre Hadot ( ) was a French philosopher and historian of ancient philosophy,

Harris Wiseman, The Myth of the Moral Brain: The Limits of Moral Enhancement (Cambridge, MA and London: The MIT Press, 2016), 340 pp.

Transcription:

6 : Understanding Camus Quantitative Ethics Through Bergsonian Duration Thomas Ruan Only through time time is conquered T.S. Eliot In The Myth of Sisyphus, Albert Camus tries to work through what he calls the one truly serious philosophical problem : suicide (3). He begins by noting that the human experience is fundamentally marked by absurdity, which he defines as the opposition between the irrational nature of the world and man's innate desire to understand it. The absurd is not merely the passive indifference and irrationality of the world around us; it arises more specifically from our continual failure to make any kind of adequate sense of it. This is why Camus points out that 'It's absurd' means 'It's impossible' but also 'It's contradictory' (29). The simplest way to deal with absurdity, then, is to remove one term from the equation by committing suicide. Camus resists this solution, because suicide fails to pay heed to the power that the absurd can give to our lives. By living in absurdity, and accepting its fundamental contradiction, we revolt against the temptation to shy away from existence that revolt gives life its value (55). Living is keeping the absurd alive, and it is this affirmation of the absurdity of our condition that allows us to live purposive and meaningful lives. However Camus then makes a conclusion that seems quite troubling. He writes that, belief in the meaning of life always implies a scale of values, a choice, our preferences. Belief in the Thomas Lipa Ruan is a junior studying philosophy and chemistry at Swarthmore College. In his free time, he enjoys baking bread and playing the trumpet. As for the rest of his biography, it is shrouded in mystery...

Thomas Ruan 7 absurd, according to our definitions, teaches the contrary (60). That is to say, belief in the absurd necessarily cannot ground a value, for the absurd merely confers an equivalence of the consequences of [our] actions (67). To value something is to deem it better, greater, or 'more' than something else. If all the consequences of our actions are equivalent, how, then, can we decide what actions we should value? Camus asserts that what counts is not the best living but the most living Belief in the absurd is tantamount to substituting the quantity of experiences for the quality (60-61, italics added). At first glance, Camus appears to be advocating a kind of nihilistic hedonism: it doesn't matter which experiences one has, since no meaningful difference can be made between different kinds of experience what's really important is just to have a lot of them! This surface level interpretation seems well supported by the text, and yet the conclusions it draws are contrary to the existentialist project as such, which strives to give life a meaning and substance through fidelity to the absurd. The way through this apparent contradiction in Camus's 'ethics of quantity,' I argue, requires further investigation into the structure of temporality that The Myth of Sisyphus implies. What does Camus exactly mean by quantity, and how does it differ from the commonsense view of quantity? How does one engage in the most living? In what way does Camus conceive of temporality, especially in terms of our experience in/of it? Camus writes that during every day of an unillustrious life, time carries us. But a moment always comes when we have to carry it. We live on in the future yet a day comes when a man notices or says that he is thirty. Thus he asserts his youth. But simultaneously he situates himself in relation to time. He takes his place in it (13). Here, a clear distinction between being carried by time and carrying time is made. One can either be pushed along by the everyday flow of things, or one can assert oneself and make the choice to determine one s own course of actions. The major implication of this distinction is that time is not some impersonal, objective thing that flows along apart from us it is only in the sense that it is experienced. Furthermore, my experience of time changes depending on whether it is me or

8 time that is doing the carrying. Though this may seem fairly obvious, this point is often obscured when time is thought of as a purely objective phenomenon. For the most part, we tend to think of time in terms of seconds, minutes, and hours, as something that exists independently from any given subject's experience of it. This way of thinking about time, which I call everyday temporality, conceals the phenomenological fact that temporality is, at base, a subjective and experiential phenomenon. Camus's ethics of quantity cannot be understood in terms of everyday temporality. Instead, it calls for a richer account of the phenomenology of temporality. Henri Bergson's theory of the duration provides a useful way for us to do this. At the beginning of his essay, Introduction to Metaphysics, Bergson contrasts two ways of knowing an entity: The first implies that we move round the object; the second that we enter into it. The first depends on the point of view at which we are placed and on the symbols by which we express ourselves. The second neither depends on a point of view nor relies on any symbol. The first kind of knowledge may be said to stop at the relative; the second, in those cases where it is possible, to attain the absolute (21). Everyday temporality (what Bergson calls spatialized time ) is thus relative: we use certain symbols (second, minute, hour) to designate specific periods of time, and all clocks are relatively tuned to a central one in London. By describing everyday temporality as relative, Bergson hints at the disconnect between symbolic representations and actual lived experiences of time. For example, what exactly is an hour? 60 minutes, or 3600 seconds. This isn't a very satisfying answer, because immediately afterward we must ask: But what is a minute, or a second? Going all the way back to the atomic definition of a second (yearly agreed upon by a committee of French physicists) is not particularly elucidating, either at the end of the day, to use the words second, minute, or hour is to, to use Bergson's words, move round some object. Yet, this object, time as such, is not an object that is, to put it crudely, 'out there in the world.' The relative under-

Thomas Ruan 9 standing of time neglects the fundamentally subjective nature of time. On the other hand, an absolute understanding of time comes out of the experience of being in time. When I insert myself in [an object] by an effort of imagination, then I gain absolute knowledge of it. What I experience will depend neither on the point of view I may take up in regard to the object, since I am inside the object itself (Bergson 21), nor on the way the experience is translated into symbols, because absolute knowledge is not expressed symbolically. Bergson's name for this 'insertion' is intuition, and an intuition of time yields what he calls duration, or pure time. Since duration is constantly evolving one moment slips into the next with no clear division in between intuition must also adjust with(in) the duration that is being examined. This means that [whereas] analysis operates always on the immobile intuition places itself in mobility, or, what comes to the same thing, in duration (41). It is impossible to explain a duration in words, because to do so would fix it in place. A description of a duration cannot at all stand in for a duration itself. Again, this may seem plainly obvious, but as Bergson points out frequently, we tend to think that accurately formed concepts can adequately substitute for the things that they symbolise, which is plainly not the case with duration. Duration is a heterogeneous flux or becoming (Bergson 12). This means that a duration is a heterogeneous multiplicity of unequal moments, and that it itself is unstable. Rather than an hour, which will always be comprised of sixty minutes, any particular duration expands or contracts depending on the intuitive experience that a self has within it. It is important to note that it is incorrect to posit a self that is given prior to its experience in duration, or vice versa a subject is only in duration, but a duration is only as it is unfolded through a self. Duration is a becoming because it is not static the durational self is always pushing forward, always moving towards new expressions of being. The heterogeneous character of duration implies that intuition of a duration can be directed in two directions, either up or down : In the first we advance to a more and more attenuated

10 duration, the pulsations of which, being more rapid than ours, and dividing our simple sensation, dilute its quality into quantity Advancing in the other direction, we approach a duration which strains, contracts, and intensifies itself more and more; at the limit would be an eternity of life (48-49). The duration does not have some fixed quantity of time apportioned to it by an external symbolisation rather, the intuition itself of a duration is what gives that duration its quantity. This is the first way in which Bergson's theory of temporality contributes to a radical reinterpretation of Camus's ethics of quantity: the quantity of a period of time is determined by an embodied experience within it. Camus writes, Monday Tuesday Wednesday Thursday Friday and Saturday according to the same rhythm this path is easily followed most of the time. But one day the 'why' arises and everything begins in that weariness tinged with amazement (12-13). What he seems to be getting at here is that certain experiences free us from conceiving of time solely in terms of everyday temporality Bergson calls these experiences intuitions. When I have an intuition of time, I realise that temporality, as duration, is heterogeneous, that its quantity is not at all fixed once and for all. Above all, freedom means awareness of existence and a life of lucidity; quantity without awareness is worthless (Sagi 85). It is this awareness that makes the ethics of quantity so powerful, for when I exercise freedom in a duration, I take control of our ability to determine the quantity of my experiences this is not to say that I have complete freedom when it comes to the quantity of my duration. Since my experience in the world is absurd, it is not as helpful to talk about the quality of a duration; one duration is just as good as another. To think of duration in terms of its quantity, however, is to pay attention to its capacity for new modes of becoming, new possibilities of being. When Bergson writes that quantity is always quality in a nascent state (52), he lays out a vital consequence of an ethics of durational quantity: the quantity, or experience, of a duration is what gives the self that exists within it the freedom to become. Camus's ethical injunction, then, is to live each duration to the fullest quantity.

Thomas Ruan 11 Everyday temporality posits an external flow of time that a self happens to be placed inside. This implies a particular image of time. We tend to think of time as the connection of homogeneous or equivalent units within some already given whole; we think of a world in which there is time, or a world that then goes through time. We put being before becoming (Colebrook 41). As we have seen, this is not really the way in which time is experienced. Rather than being an extensive connection of well-defined units, time actually is an intensive series of durations that are heterogeneous, and always becoming. A duration is an inexhaustible source of freedom (Bergson 13), it is always fluxing, flowing, transforming not every duration is equivalent. The French post-modern philosopher Gilles Deleuze emphasises the ethical and political aspect of durational time. For him, self and duration are strictly inseparable. Climate, wind, season, hour are not of another nature than the things, animals, or people that populate them, follow them, sleep and awaken within them (Deleuze and Guattari 263). Again, the line between quality and quantity is blurred. What matters is not the quality of time that is being spent, as it might even be meaningless to make such a distinction. Instead, what is important is that the self becomes aware of its own possibilities of unfolding within a duration in Camus's words, that the self accepts its absurdity in a meaningless world and yet still chooses to exercise freedom. Experiencing the intensive time of specific durations... fosters intuitive awareness of the creative possibilities unique to those durations with their specific convergence of unfolding forces (Lorraine 89). It is through an awareness of absurdity in duration that the self can be most free. Each duration contains within it many different paths of being that can be taken. Absurdity tells us that there is no qualitative difference between these paths it is by choosing one in the face of absurdity, with an awareness of absurdity, that one can live with purpose and meaning in intensive time. Rather than thinking of a present time that is static and divorced from our being in it, Deleuze urges us to see that the present as durational whole carries with it virtual tendencies that

12 intensify toward thresholds of actualization in keeping with its dynamic unfolding (Lorraine 9). To be aware of these thresholds of actualization is to be aware of the absurdity of existence, to tackle it face on instead of shying away from it. This is what Camus means when he claims that, the absurd man is he who is not apart from time (72). The opposite of being apart from time is being within it, unfolding intensively in it, being aware of the creative possibilities unique to any given duration. All this must be done with the awareness of absurdity. For Camus, the character of Don Juan exemplifies the absurd life by passionately living in the present. Interestingly enough, Don Juan is an absurd hero even though he acts just the same as any other seducer. He is an ordinary seducer. Except for the difference that he is conscious, and that is why he is absurd [He realises] an ethic of quantity in action (72). To be ethically in a duration is to affirm its absurdity, its infinite capacity for becoming. The purpose of this inquiry was to attempt to understand Camus's assertion that Belief in the absurd is tantamount to substituting the quantity of experiences for the quality. Absurdity dictates that it is pointless to talk about the quality of experiences. All we have left is the experiences themselves, and more importantly, the duration within which these experiences unfold. In the face of the absurd, one must unfold new possibilities of being within their own duration. In other words, we must pursue quantity of experience. To think that quantity is strictly given by a certain number of hours, or years, is a mistake. Bergson and Deleuze show us that it is our intuitive, intensive experience of unfolding within time that gives life its quantity, duration its weight. This explains how at the end of The Stranger, Meursault can feel ready to start life all over again, even though his execution is imminent. By being acutely aware of the absurdity of his unfolding existence, he affirms his freedom, the fact that he determines the quantity of his own duration. He does all of this, in spite of that fact that he does not have much time left. We do not have much time either our lifetimes, seen in spatialized time, are relatively short. However, our duration is as infinite as

Thomas Ruan 13 our experience within it, and it is in there that we must passionately unfold.

14 References Bergson, Henri, and Thomas A. Goudge. An Introduction to Metaphysics. Trans. T. E. Hulme. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1999. Print. Camus, Albert. The Myth of Sisyphus, and Other Essays. Trans. Justin O'Brien. New York: Vintage, 1991. Print. Camus, Albert. The Stranger. Trans. Matthew Ward. New York: Vintage International, 1989. Print. Colebrook, Claire. Gilles Deleuze. London: Routledge, 2002. Print. Deleuze, Gilles, and Fe lix Guattari. A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Trans. Brian Massumi. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota, 1987. Print. Lorraine, Tamsin. Deleuze and Guattari's Immanent Ethics: Theory, Subjectivity, and Duration. Albany: State U of New York, 2011. Print. Sagi, Abraham. Albert Camus and the Philosophy of the Absurd. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 2002. Print.