Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Similar documents
Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

observation and conceptual interpretation

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015):

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

Université Libre de Bruxelles

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Structural Realism, Scientific Change, and Partial Structures

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

In The Meaning of Ought, Matthew Chrisman draws on tools from formal semantics,

Author's personal copy

Incommensurability and the Bonfire of the Meta-Theories: Response to Mizrahi Lydia Patton, Virginia Tech

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

MODULE 4. Is Philosophy Research? Music Education Philosophy Journals and Symposia

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

26:010:685 Social Science Methods in Accounting Research

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

AN ALTERNATIVE TO KITCHER S THEORY OF CONCEPTUAL PROGRESS AND HIS ACCOUNT OF THE CHANGE OF THE GENE CONCEPT. Ingo Brigandt

Domains of Inquiry (An Instrumental Model) and the Theory of Evolution. American Scientific Affiliation, 21 July, 2012

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Ridgeview Publishing Company

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

All Roads Lead to Violations of Countable Additivity

The erratically fine-grained metaphysics of functional kinds in technology and biology

Editorial Policy. 1. Purpose and scope. 2. General submission rules

On Recanati s Mental Files

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

An Alternative to Kitcher s Theory of Conceptual Progress and His Account of the Change of the Gene Concept

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Contradictions, Dialectics, and Paradoxes as Discursive Approaches to Organizational Analysis

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Logic, Truth and Inquiry (Book Review)

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995.

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Aristotle on the Human Good

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Realism about Structure: The Semantic View and Non-linguistic Representations

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Ralph K. Hawkins Bethel College Mishawaka, Indiana

Realism about Structure: The Semantic View and Non-linguistic Representations*

Is Hegel s Logic Logical?

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

Habit, Semeiotic Naturalism, and Unity among the Sciences Aaron Wilson

Types of perceptual content

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE

Semantic Incommensurability and Scientific Realism. Howard Sankey. University of Melbourne. 1. Background

Designing a Deductive Foundation System

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver

SOCIAL AND CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner

M. Chirimuuta s Adverbialism About Color. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. I. Color Adverbialism

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Scientific Realism, the Semantic View and Evolutionary Biology

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive understanding.

STRUCTURALISM AND INFORMATION OTA VIO BUENO

Kant, Peirce, Dewey: on the Supremacy of Practice over Theory

44 Iconicity in Peircean situated cognitive Semiotics

Philosophical History and the Problem of Consciousness

Course Description: looks into the from a range dedicated too. Course Goals: Requirements: each), a 6-8. page writing. assignment. grade.

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

ANALOGY, SCHEMATISM AND THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

Semiotics of culture. Some general considerations

124 Philosophy of Mathematics

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Introduction to the Philosophy of Science

Qeauty and the Books: A Response to Lewis s Quantum Sleeping Beauty Problem

Why Music Theory Through Improvisation is Needed

Perceptions and Hallucinations

Wilfrid Sellars from Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man

THE EVOLUTION OF RELIGION AND THE EVOLUTION OF CULTURE TAYLOR THIEL DAVIS. B.Sc., The University of Georgia, 2000 M.A., Tufts University, 2011

In Search of Mechanisms, by Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden, 2013, The University of Chicago Press.

of perception, elaborated in his De Anima as an isomorphic motion of the soul. It will begin by

Scientific Models. Stephen M. Downes* University of Utah

No General Structure


Ontological and historical responsibility. The condition of possibility

Faceted classification as the basis of all information retrieval. A view from the twenty-first century

Aristotle The Master of those who know The Philosopher The Foal

Humanities Learning Outcomes

Meaning, Being and Expression: A Phenomenological Justification for Interdisciplinary Scholarship

Anne Freadman, The Machinery of Talk: Charles Peirce and the Sign Hypothesis (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2004), pp. xxxviii, 310.

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

Current Issues in Pictorial Semiotics

Natural Kinds and Concepts: A Pragmatist and Methodologically Naturalistic Account

Replacing Recipe Realism

Transcription:

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative 21-22 April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh Matthew Brown University of Texas at Dallas Title: A Pragmatist Logic of Scientific Practice ABSTRACTS Abstract: Philosophy of science in practice advocates "a philosophy of scientific practice, based on an analytic framework that takes into consideration theory, practice and the world simultaneously"(spsp, "Mission statement"). I would like to offer up classical pragmatism as one candidate for such an analytic framework. According to John Dewey, "pragmatism" is "the logic and ethics of scientific inquiry." C.S. Peirce describes it as "nothing else than the logic of abduction." I follow their lead, setting out a pragmatist account of the "logic" of scientific practice, i.e., a general theory of the forms of scientific inquiry or inference. On my account of the pragmatic logic of scientific practice, scientific inquiry is a response to practical problems, to perplexities in scientific practices of prediction, explanation, and control, which are themselves situated in and responsive to a broader social situation. The general features of scientific inquiry (problem-statement, data, facts, hypothesis, theory, reasoning, experimentation) are forms that arise in the course of scientific inquiry and are defined functionally in terms of their role in resolving the practical problems which occasion inquiry. This form of pragmatism has much to recommend it as a general framework for philosophy of scientific practice. In particular, I will focus on how the pragmatist framework I describe provides accounts of evidence, testing, and knowledge particularly suited to resolving some classic problems about the nature of scientific evidence. David Danks Carnegie Mellon University Title: Unifying Pragmatic Theories Abstract: One common claim about pragmatic accounts of scientific theories¾often presented as an objection to those accounts¾is that they necessarily imply that science is disunified. Pragmatic accounts are thought to be incompatible (in some sense) with the very possibility of unified, coherent scientific theories of any significant scope. Roughly, the usual argument here is that the pragmatic accounts imply that different goals, technology, social structures, or other

factors typically lead to scientific theories that posit different objects, laws, relations, or structures, where those resulting scientific contents are rarely, if ever, reconcilable. In contrast, this talk will explore the possibility of unified pragmatic theories. I begin by developing a general account of theoretical unification guided by intertheoretic constraints. On this model, constraints provide the primary intertheoretic glue that binds compatible theories together, and shows where incompatible theories conflict. This focus suggests that the key to the unification question is whether the intertheoretic constraints implied by particular pragmatic theories or claims are actually incompatible with one another. If so, then we have disunification; if not, then we have at least the possibility of unification. When we focus on intertheoretic constraints, we find that there is an important distinction between different pragmatic accounts of science, centered on the particular underlying reasons or motivations for the pragmatism. At a high level: (a) pragmatism based in epistemic considerations (e.g., explanatory power, ontological truth/accuracy) leads to theories that are likely incompatible; (b) pragmatism based on practical considerations (e.g., control, data predictability) usually leads to compatible theories. That is, the connection between pragmatism and disunity is much more complex than usually assumed. Throughout this talk, I will draw examples from multiple scientific domains. Richard Healey University of Arizona Title: Laws and Chance: A Pragmatist Alternative to Metaphysics Abstract: The status of laws and chance has been the locus of a lively debate in recent philosophy. Most participants have assumed laws and chance play an important role in science and sought their objective ground in the natural world, though some skeptics (Giere, van Fraassen) have questioned this assumption. So-called Humeans seek such a basis in particular facts such as those specified in David Lewis s Humean mosaic. Their opponents (e.g. Maudlin) argue that such a basis is neither necessary nor sufficient to support the independent existence of objective scientific laws and chance. This essentially metaphysical debate has paid scant attention to the details of scientific practice. It has mostly focused on so-called fundamental laws, assumed to take a particular form (such as Maudlin s FLOTEs). I propose a pragmatist alternative not as another position in the debate but as an alternative to the debate itself. This pragmatist alternative offers a view that questions the representational conception of objectivity presupposed by all participants to the debate. Statements of law and chance serve many different purposes in science, some of which I ll illustrate. But their central role is in inference, primarily to guide the expectations of an agent whose situation limits what information is accessible to that agent. Probabilistic laws do not state chances. Chance is single-case probability, a concept that is applicable even in the absence of explicit probabilistic laws. But instances of probabilistic laws

permit inference to chances in particular circumstances. The more universal and insuperable the limits on accessible information, the more objective are the chances that help transcend them. A modified Lewisian chance (relative to a spacetime point or region) may be located at one end of a spectrum of objectivity that is visible only to physically situated agents like us. It does not supervene on the Humean mosaic, but nor does it help generate it. Though fundamental in current science, quantum chance has no more metaphysical significance then a ticket s chance of winning the next drawing of the Pennsylvania lottery. Jenann Ismael University of Arizona Title: On Chance (or, Why I am only a half-humean) The main divide in the philosophical discussion of chances, is between Humean and anti- Humean views. Humeans think that statements about chance can be reduced to statements about patterns in the manifold of actual fact (the Humean Mosaic ). Non-humeans deny that reduction is possible. If one goes back and looks at Lewis early papers on chance, there are actually two separable threads in the discussion: one that treats chances as recommended credences and one that identifies chances with patterns in the manifold of categorical fact. I will defend a half humean view that retains the first thread and rejects the second. My suggestion is that what the Humean view can be thought of as presenting the patterns in the Humean mosaic as the basis for inductive judgments built into the content of probabilistic belief. This will be offered as a template for accounts of laws, capacities, dispositions, and causes i.e., all of the modal outputs of Best System style theorizing. In each case, the suggestion will be, these are derivative quantities that encode inductive judgments based on patterns in the manifold of fact. They extract projectible regularities from the pattern of fact and give us belief-forming and decision-making policies that have a general, pragmatic justification. Kerry McKenzie University of California, San Diego Title: In search of a pragmatic metaphysics: lessons from structuralism Central to pragmatist philosophy is its acknowledgement of human liability to error, and its corollary that perfection in science as in life is something far off and still in the process of achievement. But this idea that we are apt to be wrong about the world and may yet also hope to make progress in future is shared as the central vision of structuralist philosophy of science. Introduced by John Worrall in 1989 in response to the litany of errors outlined in Laudan s pessimistic induction, epistemic structuralism aims to model scientific knowledge in such a way as to accommodate human limitations with regard to the unobservable, while also making future

scientific commitments viewable as perfections or improvements of contemporary commitments as opposed to their outright supplantations. Given the close connections that evidently exist between pragmatist and structuralist philosophies, one might then wonder whether it is to structuralist metaphysics that we should look to in order to develop a more pragmatically oriented metaphysics of science. I will argue that at least as things stand the opposite is in fact the case. Structuralist metaphysics in its contemporary incarnation presents itself as a naturalistic metaphysics of the fundamental, with ontic structuralists drawing on our best current physics to argue for the existence of ontological priority relations between metaphysical categories. I will argue that this is in fact a project of analytic metaphysics that cannot hope to make true claims in advance of a final physics theory. More significantly, I will argue that there is also no sense to the idea that such claims, while false, can represent progress towards the true metaphysics to be revealed at the end of enquiry. At the root of this latter problem is that fact that the categories of analytic metaphysics have what James would call a one-drop character something that makes them in principle resistant to any concept of approximation or improvement. However, with our errors now in hindsight, we are in a better position to imagine what a metaphysics of science should look like if it is to be consistent with the shared motivations of both structuralism and pragmatism. Laura Ruetsche University of Michigan Title: Pragmatism, Perennialism, and the Physics of Ignorance Abstract: Investigations of the foundations of quantum field theories have suggested (at least to me) the thesis that theory specification has a pragmatic dimension: strategies for equipping physical theories with content, if sensibly pursued, eventuate in contents indexed not only (or not just) to the way the world is but also to our aims in using our theories and the circumstances we use them in. Realists and representationalists resist the move to pragmatize theoretical content. They say the move rests on artifacts of the present incomplete state of physics. Fundamental physics, they contend, can only be properly understood if it s understood as representing the way the world is. Anyone who thinks otherwise, they suggest, has paid too much attention to incomplete and unfundamental sciences. Since none of the physics at hand is genuinely fundamental, this representationalist maneuver seems to land us in a dialectical impasse. To assess the move to pragmatize theoretical content, we need to know things of which we re ignorant---the future of science, the nature of fundamental physics. In my talk, I ll try to negotiate this impasse by developing two reasons to predict that future scientific theories, including theories of fundamental physics, will continue to be best understood as possessing pragmatized content. C. Kenneth Waters University of Calgary

Title: Ask Not What is an Individual? Abstract: Philosophers of biology typically pose questions about individuation by asking What is an individual? For example, we ask, what is an individual species, an individual organism, or an individual gene? I will use my analysis of conceptual practice in genetics to motivate a more pragmatic approach. I will contend that instead of asking What is a gene?, we should ask: How do biologists individuate genes? For what purposes do biologists individuate genes? Do their practices of individuating serve these purposes? I will then apply this approach to the debate about whether holiobionts (assemblages of a host with microbial symbionts) are individuals. I will argue that biologists and philosophers have framed this debate with the wrong question. Instead of asking whether holiobionts are individuals, we should ask why biologists individuate holiobionts and whether their individuating practices serve important purposes.