Aristotle s Concept of Nature: Traditional Interpretation and Results of Recent Studies

Similar documents
An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

Aristotle. By Sarah, Lina, & Sufana

Z.13: Substances and Universals

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Aristotle. Aristotle. Aristotle and Plato. Background. Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle and Plato

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

THE LOGICAL FORM OF BIOLOGICAL OBJECTS

Teleology, First Principles, and Scientific Method in Aristotle s Biology by Allan Gotthelf


In Parts of Animals I 1 (and elsewhere) Aristotle makes it clear that his goal in the study of nature is a

Darwinian populations and natural selection, by Peter Godfrey-Smith, New York, Oxford University Press, Pp. viii+207.

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala

THE END OF EVOLUTION

Aristotle (summary of main points from Guthrie)

The Contemporary Relevance of Aristotle s Thought

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

Ed. Carroll Moulton. Vol. 1. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, p COPYRIGHT 1998 Charles Scribner's Sons, COPYRIGHT 2007 Gale

Definition and the Epistemology of Natural Kinds in Aristotle

On Aristotelian Universals and Individuals: The Vink that is in Body and May Be In Me

Martin, Gottfried: Plato s doctrine of ideas [Platons Ideenlehre]. Berlin: Verlag Walter de Gruyter, 1973

SOCI 421: Social Anthropology

Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring Russell Marcus Hamilton College

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

R. G. COLLINGWOOD S CRITIQUE OF SPENGLER S THEORY OF HISTORICAL CYCLE

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

* For referencing this article please use the Blackwell (2009) version.

DOWNLOAD OR READ : VESTIGES OF THE NATURAL HISTORY OF CREATION PDF EBOOK EPUB MOBI

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

EVOLUTIONARY BIOLOGY

ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. Parmenides on Change The Puzzle Parmenides s Dilemma For Change

AL-MUKHATABAT ISSN ISSUE 06/2013

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

MODERN BIOLOGICAL NEO-TELEOLOGISM VS. ARISTOTLE S GENUINE TELOS

Aristotle on the Mechanism of Inheritance

WRITING A PRÈCIS. What is a précis? The definition

Aristotle s Categories and Physics

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

ON ARISTOTELIAN UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS: THE VINK THAT IS IN BODY AND MAY BE IN ME. Irena Cronin

CHALLENGES AND FALLACIES IN COMPUTER APPLICATIONS OF THE EVOLUTIONARY ANALOGY IN DESIGN METHODOLOGY

A Basic Aristotle Glossary

Owen Barfield. Romanticism Comes of Age and Speaker s Meaning. The Barfield Press, 2007.

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Sean Coughlin. PERSONAL DATA Born 27 May 1982 in Hamilton (Canada) Citizen of Canada, the United States of America, and the United Kingdom

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995.

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

RESEMBLANCE IN DAVID HUME S TREATISE Ezio Di Nucci

PHILOSOPHY PLATO ( BC) VVR CHAPTER: 1 PLATO ( BC) PHILOSOPHY by Dr. Ambuj Srivastava / (1)

The History of Philosophy. and Course Themes

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

An introduction to biological essentialism. John Wilkins Biohumanities Project University of Queensland

CONTENTS II. THE PURE OBJECT AND ITS INDIFFERENCE TO BEING

FLF5246 History of Ancient Philosophy (Aristotle s Psychology: Perception) 1 st semester, 2019 Prof. Evan Keeling 08 Créditos Duração: 12 semanas

Riccardo Chiaradonna, Gabriele Galluzzo (eds.), Universals in Ancient Philosophy, Edizioni della Normale, 2013, pp. 546, 29.75, ISBN

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Julie K. Ward. Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) Mathesis Publications

The Philosophy of Human Evolution

The Origin of Aristotle's Metaphysical Aporiae

It is from this perspective that Aristotelian science studies the distinctive aspects of the various inhabitants of the observable,

Morse Peckham manuscript for variorum text of The Origin of Species by Charles Darwin

Course Syllabus. Ancient Greek Philosophy (direct to Philosophy) (toll-free; ask for the UM-Flint Philosophy Department)

7AAN2026 Greek Philosophy I: Plato Syllabus Academic year 2015/16

The Milesian School. Philosopher Profile. Pre-Socratic Philosophy A brief introduction of the Milesian School of philosophical thought.

The Philosopher George Berkeley and Trinity College Dublin

Aristotle's Psychology First published Tue Jan 11, 2000; substantive revision Mon Aug 23, 2010; Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (edited version)

Linnet. Extent of postjuvenile moult. II III IV V VI VII VIII IX X XI XII Linnet. Summer. Adult. Female (11-VI)

Claim: refers to an arguable proposition or a conclusion whose merit must be established.

An Aristotelian Understanding of Object-Oriented Programming

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

Lecture 12 Aristotle on Knowledge of Principles

Corcoran, J George Boole. Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2nd edition. Detroit: Macmillan Reference USA, 2006

3 DA III.8, 432a102 4 Balme 1987b: Balme 1987a: Freudenthal 1995: 31. Vital heat, according to Freudenthal, is heat carrying informing

A Plea for Human Nature

Relational Logic in a Nutshell Planting the Seed for Panosophy The Theory of Everything

What Makes Us Essentially Different?

206 Metaphysics. Chapter 21. Universals

African Fractals Ron Eglash

But, if I understood well, Michael Ruse doesn t agree with you. Why?

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

Keywords: Teleology; Teaching of Evolution; Evolutionary thinking

164 BOOK REVIEWS [March

Chapter 2 The Main Issues

CURRICULUM VITAE MEHMET M. ERGINEL

Aristotle s Phenomenology of Form: The Shape of Beings that Become

Fatma Karaismail * REVIEWS

Reviewed by Philip Beeley, Universitiit Hamburg Depending on one's point of view, Leibniz's early philosophy can either be

Information for authors

Alfred Russel Wallace

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

HISTORY 104A History of Ancient Science

1. Introduction. Kathrin Koslicki Department of Philosophy, University of Alberta

ARISTOTLE S METAPHYSICS. February 5, 2016

Essay Review: What Made Ernst Unique? *

Aristotle on the matter of corpses in Metaphysics H5

Pierre Hadot on Philosophy as a Way of Life. Pierre Hadot ( ) was a French philosopher and historian of ancient philosophy,

T h e G r e e k P h i l o s o p h e r s

Causes and Kinds in Aristotle s Embryology. Jessica Louise Gelber. A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the

Humanities 116: Philosophical Perspectives on the Humanities

Unity in Aristotle s Metaphysics H 6

Chapter 1. The Power of Names NAMING IS NOT LIKE COUNTING

Transcription:

Evolving Concepts of Nature Pontifical Academy of Sciences, Acta 23, Vatican City 2016 www.pas.va/content/dam/accademia/pdf/acta23/acta23-berti.pdf Aristotle s Concept of Nature: Traditional Interpretation and Results of Recent Studies Enrico Berti Aristotle s concept of nature dominated Western culture including the Islamic world from late antiquity to the Middle Ages, and was then permanently displaced by the concept of modern science introduced by Galilei and Descartes in the seventeenth century. However, despite its long rule, the true meaning of Aristotle s concept was not always understood. In particular, its application to living beings was interpreted as an essentialist and fixist model, as opposed to the evolutionistic model introduced by Darwin. In this paper I would like to explain briefly why this interpretation, which has become the traditional one, is largely the result of a misunderstanding due to a Platonic or Neoplatonic reading of Aristotle s concept of nature as form or essence. In the famous chapter on the meanings of the term nature (phusis), contained in Book V of the Metaphysics, which is considered Aristotle s dictionary of philosophical terms, he distinguishes among the various meanings of this term, present in common parlance or in the theories of the philosophers preceding him: generation (genesis), growth (phusis with a long u), matter (hule) from where things come from, and the form (eidos) or essence (ousia) of natural entities, that is, the things that have in themselves and as such the source of their own movement. While the first two meanings belong to common parlance, the third belongs to the philosophies of the Presocratics and the last one is the correct meaning which, according to Aristotle, must be given to the term nature, allowing us to make a distinction between natural entities, which have nature as their source, and artificial entities, which have art (techne), that is, man, as their source. At the end of the above-mentioned chapter, Aristotle declares: From what has been said, then, it is plain that nature in the primary and strict sense is the substance of things which have in themselves, as such, a source of movement; for the matter is called nature because it is qualified to receive this, and processes of becoming and growing are called nature because they are movements proceeding

ENRICO BERTI from this. And nature in this sense is the source of the movement of natural objects, being present in them somehow, either potentially or actually. 1 In Book II of the Physics, which is the treatise that Aristotle officially devotes to the concept of nature, he reiterates that nature is not in matter, but in form, specifically in the form of entities that have in themselves the source of change and are thus capable of generating themselves. In support of this argument he mentions the difference between a man and a bed, which lies in the fact that man is generated by man, whereas a bed is not generated by a bed. 2 To understand this explanation it is necessary to recall that Aristotle viewed the generation of living beings as essentially the work of form, which he calls soul, intended not in the Christian sense of spiritual principle, but in the sense of vital principle, which is also in common with plants and non-human animals. All interpreters agree on the need to consider the term substance in the sense of essence or form, for example in the passage of Metaph. V and other similar ones, like Aristotle himself says at the end of Book VII of the Metaphysics, which is devoted to clarifying what is substance. But this view of nature as essence is what has led modern philosophers to attribute to Aristotle a kind of essentialism, that is, a concept of nature as characterized by the admission of universal and unchanging essences, which apparently guide natural events, in particular the reproduction processes of living beings, in an absolutely fixed and regular way, excluding any possibility of evolution: the so-called fixism. An exemplary expression of this interpretation is W.K.C. Guthrie s book on Aristotle in his monumental History of Greek Philosophy, where, in commenting on Aristotle s treatise on substance in Book VII of the Metaphysics, he states: Doubtless this is not a satisfactory explanation of reality. For it makes Darwinian evolution impossibile. 3 According to the traditional interpretation, the form mentioned by Aristotle is precisely a universal, immutable form, like the Ideas accepted by Plato. This is due to the fact that Aristotle calls form eidos, which is the same term Plato uses to refer to Ideas. In Greek this term also means what we call species, that is, not an individual, but a class of individuals, a kind. 1 Aristot. Metaph. V 4, 1015 a 13-19 (The Complete Works of Aristotle, The Revised Oxford Translation, Edited by J. Barnes, Princeton 1985). 2 Aristot. Phys. II 1, 193 b 6-12. 3 W.K.C. Guthrie, A History of Greek Philosophy, VI, Aristotle: An Encounter, Cambridge 1981, p. 222. 2 Evolving Concepts of Nature

ARISTOTLE S CONCEPT OF NATURE: TRADITIONAL INTERPRETATION AND RESULTS OF RECENT STUDIES According to the traditional interpretation, the only difference between the Idea accepted by Plato and the form accepted by Aristotle is the fact that the Idea is a transcendent entity, one that exists in another world, different from the sensitive one, the so-called intelligible world, whereas the form is an entity immanent in matter, that is, existing in the sensitive world. According to this interpretation, Aristotle did nothing but transfer Plato s Ideas from the intelligible world to the sensitive world, that is, to nature. This interpretation, however, has been refuted for several decades now, first of all by a specialist in Aristotle s biological works, David Mowbray Balme (1912-1989). In a famous article entitled Aristotle s biology was not essentialist, he points out that, according to Aristotle, form is the moving cause of animal reproduction, because it produces, through the pneuma contained in the male seed, the movements that give form to the material provided by the female parent, thus constituting the embryo and guiding its development until the complete formation of the individual (a process that William Harvey called epigenesis). 4 As Balme shows, this form has nothing to do with species, which is a mere universal obtained by generalization, resulting from the similarity between parents and offspring produced by the form. The form that causes reproduction is what Aristotle calls soul (psyche), which, as we have said, means something different in part from the way in which we speak of soul in Christianity. According to Aristotle, the soul of the male parent, through the movements that it imparts to the material, generates the embryo s soul, which is evidently of the same species as its parent s, but is an individual soul, distinct from the latter. This form always acts on matter, impressing the characteristics proper of the species, but may in turn be subject to the action of matter, which may bring about a few differences between individuals of the same species. 5 Balme observes, for example, that Aristotle in his Metaphysics explains that individuals of the same species such as males and females in animals, or blacks and whites in humans, are different, respectively, because of sex and skin color. 6 Balme also recalls that in his Historia animalium Aristotle notes that there are differences between animals of the same species, for example cicadas: 4 D. M. Balme, Aristotle s biology was not essentialist, «Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie», 62, 1980, pp. 1-12, reprinted with Appendixes in A. Gotthelf & J. G. Lennox (eds.), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle s Biology, Cambridge 1987, pp. 291-312. 5 Aristot. De gen. an. IV 3, 768 b 15-25. 6 Aristot. Metaph. X 9, 1058 a 29-b 10. Evolving Concepts of Nature 3

ENRICO BERTI one, small in size, the first to come and the last to disappear; the other, large, that comes last and first disappears. 7 Similarly there are differences in the Egyptian ibis species, white and black: the white ones are found all over in Egypt, excepting in Pelusium; the black ones are found in Pelusium, and nowhere else in Egypt. 8 More in general, Balme remarks that Aristotle states that animals of the same species differ according to their location, for example: variety in animal life may be produced by variety of locality: thus in one place an animal will not be found at all, in another it twill be small, or short-lived, or will not thrive, 9 or animals of the same species have different characteristics and behaviour according to the season, for example: a considerable number of birds change according to season the colour of their plumage and their note; as, for instance, the owzel becomes yellow instead of black, and its note gets altered, for in summer it has a musical note and in winter a discordant chatter. The thrush also changes in colour; about the throat it is marked in winter with speckles, in summer spotted. 10 In short, Aristotle considered that many differences between animals of the same species depended on external circumstances, such as place and time, or even environment and lifestyle. Thus Balme can state that: The extraordinary later misinterpretations of Aristotle, the magical entelechies and real specific forms, must be largely due to these imported concepts Species, Essentia, Substantia which presided like three witches over his rebirth in the Middle Ages, but should be banished to haunt the neoplatonism from which they came. 11 We could add that for Aristotle those that we call natural laws, for example the law by which animals of a certain species generate animals of the same species (Aristotle repeats countless times that man generates man ), are not always, i.e. out of necessity, valid, like the laws of mathematics, but are only valid for the most part, that is, in most cases. Thus, certain exceptions are admitted and according to Aristotle they are an accident, that is, a product of chance, and this accident or chance depends on matter, which is capable of being otherwise than as it for the most part is. 12 7 Aristot. Hist. An. V 30, 556 a 14-15. 8 Ibid. IX 27, 617 b 28-29. 9 Ibid. VIII 28, 605 b 22-25. 10 Ibid. IX 49, 632 b 14-20. 11 Balme, art. cit., p. 306. 12 Aristot. Metaph. VI 2, 1027 a 5-20. 4 Evolving Concepts of Nature

ARISTOTLE S CONCEPT OF NATURE: TRADITIONAL INTERPRETATION AND RESULTS OF RECENT STUDIES It is clear that those mutations are possible in the margin of indetermination left vacant by the laws of nature and this is what makes evolution possible, according to modern genetics. When a modern geneticist like Jacques Monod explains evolution in terms of chance and necessity, he unknowingly repeats the association between these two concepts already employed by Aristotle to explain natural phenomena. 13 This does not mean, of course, that Aristotle was an evolutionist, but one cannot even say that he was fixist, like Linnaeus and Cuvier, or, if he was, he certainly did not know it. It simply means that Aristotle s biology was not incompatible with the theory of evolution, as an Irish philosopher, Fran O Rourke,14 recently explained thanks to extensive documentation. With regard to this subject, it is important to remember that, after reading the English version of Aristotle s De partibus animalium, Charles Darwin wrote a letter to the translator of the work, William Ogle, saying: Linnaeus and Cuvier have been my two gods, though in very different ways, but they were mere schoolboys to old Aristotle. 15 Besides, the interpretation of form, or essence, as an individual reality, and thus not coincident with the species, which Balme had arrived at through the analysis of Aristotle s biological works, was also confirmed by the analysis of the Aristotelian metaphysics made by two German scholars who are considered among the greatest contemporary scholars of Aristotle, Michael Frede and Günther Patzig. Indeed, in a famous commentary on Book VII of the Metaphysics, they showed not only that, for Aristotle, substance coincides with form, but that Aristotle does not consider substantial form as universal, like the species, but as individual, like the soul. 16 Indeed, this is the only way to explain otherwise incomprehensible passages such as the following: the causes of things in the same species are different, not in species, but in the sense that the causes of different individuals are different, your matter and form (eidos) and moving cause being different from 13 J. Monod, Le hasard et la nécessité: essai sur la philosophie naturelle de la biologie moderne, Paris 1970. 14 F. O Rourke, Aristotle and the Metaphysics of Evolution, «The Review of Metaphysics», 43, 2004, pp. 3-59. 15 Cfr. A. Gotthelf, Darwin on Aristotle, «Journal of the History of Biology», 32, 1999, pp. 3-30. 16 M. Frede G. Patzig, Aristoteles Metaphysik Z, Text, Übersetzung und Kommentar, 2 Bände, München 1988. Balme too simultaneously reached the same result in the first Appendix added to his above mentioned article: Note on the aporia in Metaphysics Z. Evolving Concepts of Nature 5

ENRICO BERTI mine, while in their universal formula they are the same. 17 Besides, a decade earlier than Balme s article, the great biologist Max Delbrück, 1969 Nobel Prize for Medicine, wrote that, if it were possible to give a Nobel prize posthumously, we ought to give it to Aristotle for having discovered the implicit principle in DNA, i.e. in the acid contained in the nucleus of the cells of every living being. This principle, following Delbrück, is just the form, which acts as a «programme», or a «plan of development», guiding the embryo from its conception up to the complete development of the mature individual, plant or animal.18 Following Delbrück s studies, and probably also taking Balme s article into account, another great biologist and historian of biology, Ernst Mayr, stated that he had changed his mind about the concept of form in Aristotle. These are his words: No other ancient philosopher has been as badly misunderstood and mishandled by posterity as Aristotle [...]. Delbrück is entirely right when insisting that it is quite legitimate to employ modern terms like genetic program for eidos where this helps sto elucidate Aristotle s thoughts. One of the reasons why Aristotle has been so consistently misunderstood is that he uses the term eidos for his form living principle, and every body took it for granted that he had something in mind similar to Plato s concept of eidos. Yet, the context of Aristotle s discussions makes it abundantly clear that his eidos is something totally different from Plato s eidos (I myself did not understand this until recently). 19 Similar considerations can be made about Aristotle s famous teleology with regard to nature, which is also subject to numerous misunderstandings. The abundant literature dispelling these, however, is unfortunately known almost exclusively to specialists of Aristotelian philosophy, and for the most part is unknown to scientists and biologists. Even in this case, a significant exception is Ernst Mayr who, in a paragraph of his above-mentioned book, explains The Multiple Meaning of Teleological, exonerating Aristotle from much of the naiveté attributed to him. But this is another matter that would require a more thorough examination. 17 Aristot. Metaph. XII 5, 1071 a 27-29 (emphasis of mine). 18 M. Delbrück, Aristotle-totle-totle, in J. Monod amd E. Borek (eds.), Of Microbes and Life, New York 1971, pp. 50-55. 19 E. Mayr, Toward a New Philosophy of Biology. Observations o fan Evolutionist, Cambridge, Mass. 1988, pp. 56-57. 6 Evolving Concepts of Nature