EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PRAGMATISM AND AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY

Similar documents
Pragmatism, Semiotic mind and Cognitivism

Kant, Peirce, Dewey: on the Supremacy of Practice over Theory

Peirce and Semiotic an Introduction

Anne Freadman, The Machinery of Talk: Charles Peirce and the Sign Hypothesis (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2004), pp. xxxviii, 310.

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Current Issues in Pictorial Semiotics

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

Terminology. - Semantics: Relation between signs and the things to which they refer; their denotata, or meaning

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

44 Iconicity in Peircean situated cognitive Semiotics

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

THE PROBLEM OF NOVELTY IN C.S. PEIRCE'S AND A.N. WHITEHEAD'S THOUGHT

Community of Inquiry and Inquiry- based learning

Foundations in Data Semantics. Chapter 4

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

INTERVIEW: ONTOFORMAT Classical Paradigms and Theoretical Foundations in Contemporary Research in Formal and Material Ontology.

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Humanities Learning Outcomes

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Domains of Inquiry (An Instrumental Model) and the Theory of Evolution. American Scientific Affiliation, 21 July, 2012

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

Narrative Thinking in Architectural Education

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Phenomenology Glossary

EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PRAGMATISM AND AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY. The History of Reception of Charles S. Peirce in Greece 1

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

Habit, Semeiotic Naturalism, and Unity among the Sciences Aaron Wilson

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Mass Communication Theory

Mitchell ABOULAFIA, Transcendence. On selfdetermination

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

WILLIAM JAMES STUDIES VOLUME 14 NUMBER 1 SPRING 2018 PP

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

Introduction: Umberto Eco s interpretative semiotics: Interpretation, encyclopedia, translation

Peterborough, ON, Canada: Broadview Press, Pp ISBN: / CDN$19.95

COPYRIGHT 2009 ASSOCIAZIONE PRAGMA

Intersemiotic translation: The Peircean basis

138 Great Problems in Philosophy and Physics - Solved? Chapter 11. Meaning. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/knowledge/meaning

Meaning and Modernity Social Theory in the Pragmatic Attitude

Lecture (0) Introduction

The Teaching Method of Creative Education

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995.

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Undercutting the Realism-Irrealism Debate: John Dewey and the Neo-Pragmatists

Review of "The Unexplained Intellect: Complexity, Time, and the Metaphysics of Embodied Thought"

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

COPYRIGHT 2009 ASSOCIAZIONE PRAGMA

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

1/9. The B-Deduction

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document

SYNTAX AND MEANING Luis Radford Université Laurentienne, Ontario, Canada

Logic, Truth and Inquiry (Book Review)

Three Pragmatist Legacies in the Thought of Umberto Eco

FORUM: QUALITATIVE SOCIAL RESEARCH SOZIALFORSCHUNG

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

MODULE 4. Is Philosophy Research? Music Education Philosophy Journals and Symposia

TRAGIC THOUGHTS AT THE END OF PHILOSOPHY


(as methodology) are not always distinguished by Steward: he says,

The Debate on Research in the Arts

Problems of Information Semiotics

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Qualitative Design and Measurement Objectives 1. Describe five approaches to questions posed in qualitative research 2. Describe the relationship betw

A guide to the PhD and MRes thesis in Creative Writing candidates and supervisors

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

Vinod Lakshmipathy Phil 591- Hermeneutics Prof. Theodore Kisiel

The Observer Story: Heinz von Foerster s Heritage. Siegfried J. Schmidt 1. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2011

Cultural Studies Prof. Dr. Liza Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

Semiotics of Terminology: A Semiotic Knowledge Profile

Keywords: semiotic; pragmatism; space; embodiment; habit, social practice.

Art, Vision, and the Necessity of a Post-Analytic Phenomenology

MEDIA AND TRANSLATION. AN INTERDISCIPLINARY APPROACH

CHAPTER - II. Pragmatism of Charles Sanders Peirce

Foucault's Technologies of the Self: A Kantian Project?

Nature's Perspectives

Scientific Philosophy

Confines of Democracy

Phenomenology and Structuralism PHIL 607 Fall 2011

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Kant s Critique of Judgment

What is the Object of Thinking Differently?

Gestalt, Perception and Literature

RESPONDING TO ART: History and Culture

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy

The Pragmatic Turn, by Richard J. Bernstein. Cambridge: Polity, 2010,, The Pragmatic Turn, Polity, Cambridge Malden 2010, xi pp.

7. This composition is an infinite configuration, which, in our own contemporary artistic context, is a generic totality.

The Concept of Nature

Pragmatism as transition. Historicity and Hope in James, Dewey, and Rorty, Columbia University Press, New York, 2009

Transcription:

* EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PRAGMATISM AND AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY COPYRIGHT 2009 ASSOCIAZIONE PRAGMA Bonfantini, Fabbrichesi, Zingale (a cura di), Su Peirce. Interpretazioni, ricerche, prospettive, Milano, Bompiani, 2015, 316 pp. Charles Sanders Peirce (1839-1914) is known today as the first American philosopher, and as the founder of pragmatism. Indeed, Peirce was both and much more. In a partial list of roles he played during his life, Peirce graduated as a chemist, published as an astronomer, worked in geodesy, wrote as a philosopher, and defined himself as a logician. While he gained only a partial, late recognition in his time, today the broadness of his interests is reflected by the diversity of the people that refer to him, either for scholarly study or for inspiration. The 21 essays constituting Su Peirce provide an overview of Italy s scholarship on Peirce s philosophical, semiotic and historical thought. The essays were originally presented in a series of meetings organized by the Psòmega Club for the centennial of Peirce s death at the University of Milan and the Polytechnic University of Milan. They are organized into four sections: an introductory one ( On the meaning of Peirce: Three Introductions ) and three thematic ones ( Understanding Peirce: Perspectives and Problems, Peirce and Others: Philosophy and Semiotics, and Peirce beyond Peirce. Inquiries and Problems ). Contributions range from close analysis to traditionally philosophical topics in Peirce such as the idea of externality (Calcaterra), reality (Brioschi), Kantianism (Maddalena), logic and phenomenology (Stango, Paolucci), language (Fadda) to dialogical engagement with different thinkers as with Vailati (Facchi), Lady Welby (Petrilli), Husserl (Silvestri), Saussure (Martone), Hjelmslev (Caputo), Bachtin (Ponzio), Lacan (Cimatti) and to multidisciplinary discussions in the direction of applied philosophy. In this last section, the authors tackle the problems of historical testimony (Pisanty), the social situatedness of creativity (Goldoni), experience in the working practice (Proni), and abduction and projects in design theory (Zingale). Bonfantini closes the volume with a reflection on contemporary issues in light of a pragmatic historical materialism. Despite the diversity of the fields of engagement, I detect a strong philosophical unity beneath the 21 essays in this volume, namely in the quest for a Peircean anthropology. The obvious reference here is to Kant. Anthropology, for Kant, is the study that aims at answering the question on what man is ( Was ist der Mensch? Logik Jäsche, 1800; AA IX) through the careful observation of man s actions. The role of actions becomes even more pivotal in Peirce s philosophy. Dispositions towards action and expectation of outcomes describe not only the attitude of the inquirer ( The Fixation of Belief, 1877), but also the purposive self-control of the moral man ( What Pragmatism Is, 1905). In the following, I will offer a brief account of the many essays that constitute the volume, focusing on how the idea of a pragmatist anthropology emerges from their different perspectives. Bonfantini, Eco, and Fabbrichesi open the volume with three introductory essays. While Eco and Bonfantini provide a connection with the history of Peirce s reception in Italy, Fabbrichesi programmatically opens the debate towards the future and uses * University College London [claudia.cristalli.15@ucl.ac.uk] 374

Peirce as a tool Towards the possibility of a New Pragmatic Anthropology. In this, her essay fits very nicely within Bonfantini s presentation of Peirce s philosophy as an open system of knowledge ( A Guess at the Riddle, c.1889, CP 1.1): Peirce s declared hope is that his philosophical work may be general enough that any particular sciences could fit in (13). 1 Indeed, Fabbrichesi draws on biology (Gilber, Sapp, & Tauber 2012) as well as from Peirce s philosophy for her discussion of man as a socially rather than individually defined being. Her article also relates to Calcaterra s contribution, in that Fabbrichesi discusses a social and external perspective on the self from later writings of Peirce ( What Pragmatism Is, 1905, EP2, and a paragraph from MS R 403, c.1893, quoted in De Tienne 2005), while Calcaterra focuses on the early papers New List of Categories, 1867, and Questions Concerning Certain Faculties Claimed for Man, 1868. Bonfantini s introduction is quite helpful in presenting chronologically Peirce s most famous philosophical and semiotic writings. The early New List (1867) is the point of departure and the leading aim of philosophical inquiry: to find concepts general enough that they may be used by any other philosopher as well as by any person in the ordinary operations of reasoning. Those general concepts are thus termed categories, elucidated in the anti-cartesian essays of 1868, the Illustrations of the logic of Science of 1877-8, the reflections on continuity and mind of 1892 and evolutionary love (Peirce 1893: 15-9). Bonfantini s final recap of the scope of the New List and its integration with phenomenology and phaneroscopy highlights the novelty of those later reflections (20) but misses the opportunity to draw the reader s attention to MS R 403 (c.1893) an explicit rewriting of the 1867 early List (EP1: 1). Indeed, as far as I know, the implications of this for the evolution of Peirce s thought remain to be explored. Eco s contribution is a reworking of his thesis of primary iconism, first exposited in his 1997 Kant and the Platypus. Eco s effort in the 1997 book aimed at demonstrating the reality content of the semiotic experience: My thesis was that, if one defends a theory of interpretation, and precisely because of that, then one must also concede that there is something that can be interpreted (23). With this, Eco openly declared his positive intentions: his aim was that of supplementing Peirce s theory with a possible answer to the problem of finding a ground for reality. Peirce s explicit refusal of a first start of our knowledge of reality a key-aspect of his philosophy, as pointed out by Paolucci (28) was rejected by Eco, who feared the nihilism involved in an infinite and groundless process of mediation (28). The theory of primary iconism was therefore first elaborated to fulfill the need of a ground of reality. While keeping to the label of primary iconism, Eco now explains this concept in a quite different way, namely as what cannot be avoided when a subject an interpretant subject enters the semiotic process (32). What cannot be avoided is something that pertains equally to the subject s cognitive system and to the external world at a given instant t. Eco concludes: even if primary iconism does not exist cosmologically, it still exists for the subject (33). To use a Peircean phrase, reality pertains more to the outward clash than to the outward itself. 1. References to the essay s pages are to the Italian text; however, all quotations have been translated into English. If not further specified, all translations are mine. 375

A different strategy to approach Peirce s concept of reality (and truth) is to be found in the anthropological shift towards practice and agency that the pragmatic perspective encourages us to assume. This is precisely the attitude that is explored in the rest of the volume. Among the introductory essays, Fabbrichesi applies her anthropological commitment to an account of the self as derivate: the self is not the ground but rather the product of its own actions and choices. Therefore, it becomes possible to distinguish two aspects of being a person, namely personality and individuality. While personality is the series of actions sewed into habits and, as it were, embroidered into the larger fabric of the world, individuality is the still unrelated thing, similar to the thread that may be hanging from the unfinished embroidery. Calcaterra s contribution ( Epistemology of the Self ) further elaborates on the notion of the agent subject from the perspective of the subject s external construction. Accordingly, the great innovation of Peirce is his complete dismissal of the dualism between an internal and an external self, which had permeated the philosophical discourse since Descartes (59). The dualism is eliminated by denying any originality or foundational role to the internal side, which becomes an inferential product of the active agent. The construction of the self is achieved through the experience of error (there must be someone who is wrong I am wrong; 61) and the testimony of the others ( Questions Concerning Certain Faculties Claimed for Man, 1868, EP 1). In Brioschi s essay The Notion of Reality in Peirce: Between Expectation and Surprise the real as Calcaterra s self is a derived notion, that may be discovered through its opposite: namely, illusion (82). However, unlike the self which can indeed be built out of false testimony, the real seems to advance a stronger claim towards truth (in the long run): first, by resisting our attempts at thinking arbitrarily of it; and, secondly, by being the object toward which any inquiry, if pursued fairly and long enough, will ultimately converge. However, Brioschi notices, there may be a problem in defending those two theses at the same time (88). Intuitively, in order to resist us, something must at least be present to us; however, the truth and the real are to be discovered at the end of the process of inquiry that is, in the future. Brioschi shows that the two theses can be reconciled, provided that reality is defined through the anthropological analysis of the structure of expectation and surprise. Expectation and surprise are not simply feelings but rather logical attitudes; following Maddalena (2003), Brioschi relates them to the metaphysical categories of Thirdness and Secondness respectively. While Thirdness, showing the regularity of natural laws, grounds expectation, Secondness, that is the subject s clash with its object, is the metaphysical name for surprise. Maddalena s discussion of the anti-kantianism of Peirce ( Peirce, anti-kantianism, and the synthetic meaning of pragmatism ) has several facets, which are probably best illustrated in his recent The Philosophy of Gesture (2015). I survey the one more closely related to the anthropological leaning of the book. According to Maddalena, experience as continuity (71) is the common element to all pragmatism. Experience and common sense are opposed to intellectualism, as shown in the Peircean critique of Cartesianism. Indeed, Maddalena argues, since Kantianism is a form of intellectualism, and since the anti-intellectual attitude is constitutive of both Peirce s 376

and the pragmatic movement, then by adopting pragmatism one should dispose of Kant and of Descartes at once. This reading of Kant s philosophy and of its relation with Peirce s is not without critics, especially because Peirce claims to have derived the very term pragmatism from Kant ( What pragmatism is, 1905; EP2: 333) and to value Kant for his practical philosophy more than for his epistemology. The most serious critic to Maddalena s views is probably Gava (2014). Although Maddalena acknowledges Gava s criticism of his anti-kantian reading of Peirce, he does not engage directly with Gava s argument here. It would be productive for the Peirce community if Maddalena and Gava could give more visibility to their respective positions in a published form. The two contributions by Stango ( The Logic of Ontological Recognition ) and Paolucci ( Logic of Relatives, Semiotics, and Phenomenology ) provide some suggestions on how the connection between logical thought and the world can be established and cultivated. Stango s logic of ontological recognition has the notion of object (or of it ) at its core, namely the problem of how the object is recognised as what it is by the knowing subject. Paolucci s contribution is also focused on the role of objects in Peirce s logic: the passage from the logic of relatives to semiotics is based on the idea that the logic is a logic of relations between objects, as exemplified by chemical models. The logic of relatives thus breaks with the traditional form of propositional logic, proposing a diagrammatic (instead of a sequential) style of reasoning. Those two contributions can be seen also as a critical reaction to Eco s theory of primary iconism. Fadda s essay, Peirce and Languages, is concerned with the role that natural, historic languages play in Peircean semiotics, that is the overlap of cultural and of biological dispositions for language in the human animal (127). Fadda proceeds from here outlining the project to apply Peirce s categories of semiotics, which certainly have a broader concern than language-use, back to linguistics and towards a broader, mostly communicative and visual understanding of language (131), as opposed to the logocentrism of Saussure. From the dialogical section, only Facchi ( From Peirce to Vailati ) and Petrilli ( Peirce and Welby ) develop this dialogue from a historical perspective. Martone advances a possible point of contact with Saussure on the notion of the metaphor, and Caputo pushes the linguistic engagement of Peirce s thought towards Hjelmselv. A contiguity is found in their mathematical fathers (194), as well as in the role of experience in the semantic content (197). Overall, those contributions fall outside of the discussion of a pragmatist anthropology and engage in a philosophical dialogue with other thinkers and traditions of thought. The last section of the book contains instances of application of Peirce s theories to contemporary subjects or problems. The essays I shall focus on are those of Goldoni, Proni, and Zingale. Goldoni ( Inhabiting the Improvisation ) connects the musical tradition of jazz improvisation with the ability to improvise in life gained by experience and built into a sharable, social language (245). Proni ( From Peirce to Sennet: Pragmatism and the Project [of living] argues that both Peirce and Sennet advance a new concept of 377

human experience. Being experienced goes hand in hand with being aware of one s own actions, and this awareness brings skill and dexterity (255) to the agent, who thus becomes craftsman of her own actions. This craftsmanship is recognised as a value to be preserved in the alienated contemporary world. Despite the fact that a personal skill is usually not easily transferable to a community, Proni maintains that craftsmanship s skills are suitable to be developed socially. This new kind of shared craftsmanship unites individual and social planning, interpersonal relations and logic of scientific discovery, as well as a still to be formulated guidelines for the [optimal] project (255). This vision, albeit seeming more Utopian than applied Peirce, remains open for further development. Finally, Zingale ( This is my design: the Space of Abduction in Planning ) connects design as a cultural and historical form [ ] of planned action (258) with the abductive inference stimulated by the irritation of doubt. As Brioschi s reality was suspended between expectation and surprise, here abduction stems from a particular uneasiness or cause of concern with what is given. Moreover, the planning imagination, which is set into motion by concern, is what allows one to conceive an object, i.e. an artifact, only together with its possible effects (263). Indeed this conception is open, and future planning may lead to further effects and therefore to different objects. This pragmatic perspective allows Zingale to introduce a very situated, and semiotically grounded concept of design. Zingale s awareness of the relation that an object has with its environment as well as with the cultural and historical contingency of its users shows a scenario of truly applied pragmatic concepts in the light of a pragmatic anthropology. To conclude, Su Peirce is a very ambitious volume, which captures a relevant part of Peirce s scholarship in Italy, plus an estimate of how appealing Peirce s thought can be for contemporary reflections on society and on community, as well as for other academic disciplines. As Fabbrichesi writes (55), Peirce has not met the destiny of the other classical pragmatists. William James (1842-1910), John Dewey (1859-1952) and George Herbert Mead (1863-1931) have today been appropriated by different fields (psychology, education theory, and sociology respectively), while Peirce remains an author for everyone and nobody, whose work continually awakes the attention of scholars from the most different backgrounds. Su Peirce will therefore appeal to a wide range of scholars, and may set the agenda for further studies in Peirce s scholarship and its ramifications in other cultural domains. 378