The good, the bad and the relative, part two: Goodness and the criterion problem in qualitative research

Similar documents
TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Four Characteristic Research Paradigms

RESEARCH AFTER POSTSTRUCTURALISM

Qualitative Design and Measurement Objectives 1. Describe five approaches to questions posed in qualitative research 2. Describe the relationship betw

FORUM: QUALITATIVE SOCIAL RESEARCH SOZIALFORSCHUNG

Introduction and Overview

CRITICAL THEORY BEYOND NEGATIVITY

By Maximus Monaheng Sefotho (PhD). 16 th June, 2015

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

FOUNDATIONS OF ACADEMIC WRITING. Graduate Research School Writing Seminar 5 th February Dr Michael Azariadis

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought

MODULE 4. Is Philosophy Research? Music Education Philosophy Journals and Symposia

Edinburgh Research Explorer

Goals and Rationales

Stenberg, Shari J. Composition Studies Through a Feminist Lens. Anderson: Parlor Press, Print. 120 pages.

These are some notes to give you some idea of the content of the lecture they are not exhaustive, nor always accurate! So read the referenced work.

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Competing Paradigms In Qualitative Research

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

The Critical Turn in Education: From Marxist Critique to Poststructuralist Feminism to Critical Theories of Race

Media as practice. a brief exchange. Nick Couldry and Mark Hobart. Published as Chapter 3. Theorising Media and Practice

Paradigm paradoxes and the processes of educational research: Using the theory of logical types to aid clarity.

HISTORIOGRAPHY IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY: FROM SCIENTIFIC OBJECTIVITY TO THE POSTMODERN CHALLENGE. Introduction

Inter-subjective Judgment

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

Quality in Qualitative Research

Any attempt to revitalize the relationship between rhetoric and ethics is challenged

What is Postmodernism? What is Postmodernism?

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

Ralph K. Hawkins Bethel College Mishawaka, Indiana

The pleasure of the bottomless: postmodernism, chaos and paradigm shifts

Back to Basics: Appreciating Appreciative Inquiry as Not Normal Science

Dialogical encounter argument as a source of rigour in the practice based PhD

African Fractals Ron Eglash

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Grant Jarvie and Joseph Maguire, Sport and Leisure in Social Thought. Routledge, London, Index, pp

Holliday Postmodernism

The phenomenological tradition conceptualizes

PROGRAMME SPECIFICATION FOR M.ST. IN FILM AESTHETICS. 1. Awarding institution/body University of Oxford. 2. Teaching institution University of Oxford

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Society for the Study of Symbolic Interaction SSSI/ASA 2002 Conference, Chicago

Reflexive Methodology

Post-positivism. Nick J Fox

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

Big Questions in Philosophy. What Is Relativism? Paul O Grady 22 nd Jan 2019

Humanities Learning Outcomes

Copyright is owned by the Author of the thesis. Permission is given for a copy to be downloaded by an individual for the purpose of research and

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology


Special Issue Introduction: Coming to Terms in the Muddy Waters of Qualitative Inquiry in Communication Studies

12th Grade Language Arts Pacing Guide SLEs in red are the 2007 ELA Framework Revisions.

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

Emerging Questions: Fernando F. Segovia and the Challenges of Cultural Interpretation

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

Normative and Positive Economics

The Historicity of Understanding and the Problem of Relativism in Gadamer's Philosophical Hermeneutics

Texas Southern University. From the SelectedWorks of Anthony M Rodriguez Ph.D. Michael A Rodriguez, Ph.D., Texas Southern University

Introduction Theorising is used in this book to indicate the activity of trying to reach adequate conceptual terms for understanding media structures

Reflection on Communication Theory as a Field

TEST BANK. Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues

Critical interpretive synthesis: what it is and why it is needed. Mary Dixon-Woods Department of Health Sciences University of Leicester

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

International Seminar. Creation, Publishing and Criticism: Galician and Irish Women Poets. Women, Poetry and Criticism: The Role of the Critic Today

Objectivity and Diversity: Another Logic of Scientific Research Sandra Harding University of Chicago Press, pp.

California Content Standards that can be enhanced with storytelling Kindergarten Grade One Grade Two Grade Three Grade Four

The Observer Story: Heinz von Foerster s Heritage. Siegfried J. Schmidt 1. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2011

CHAPTER SEVEN CONCLUSION

CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK

CST/CAHSEE GRADE 9 ENGLISH-LANGUAGE ARTS (Blueprints adopted by the State Board of Education 10/02)

THEORY, ETIDCS AND POLIDCS: INTERPRETIVE RESEARCH IN SCIENCE EDUCATION. Catherine Milne and Peter Taylor Curtin University of Technology.

Part IV Social Science and Network Theory

Owen Barfield. Romanticism Comes of Age and Speaker s Meaning. The Barfield Press, 2007.

(as methodology) are not always distinguished by Steward: he says,

Faceted classification as the basis of all information retrieval. A view from the twenty-first century

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Post Structuralism, Deconstruction and Post Modernism

M E M O. When the book is published, the University of Guelph will be acknowledged for their support (in the acknowledgements section of the book).

Program General Structure

Capstone Design Project Sample

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

PARADOX AS PARADIGM Examining Henri J. M. Nouwen s Paradigmatic Method. For DMN 911 Assignment #2 Bill Versteeg

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

8/28/2008. An instance of great change or alteration in affairs or in some particular thing. (1450)

Why is there the need for explanation? objects and their realities Dr Kristina Niedderer Falmouth College of Arts, England

3. The knower s perspective is essential in the pursuit of knowledge. To what extent do you agree?

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

Eleventh Grade Language Arts Curriculum Pacing Guide

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

If Leadership Were a Purely Rational Act We Would be Teaching Computers. Chester J. Bowling, Ph.D. Ohio State University Extension

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology

General Educational Development (GED ) Objectives 8 10

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

CHAPTER TWO EPISTEMOLOGY AND THEORY. Introduction. the dissertation, which are postmodern, social constructionist and ecosystemic in nature.

GV958: Theory and Explanation in Political Science, Part I: Philosophy of Science (Han Dorussen)

Welcome to Sociology A Level

THE ARTS IN THE CURRICULUM: AN AREA OF LEARNING OR POLITICAL

Transcription:

International Journal of Nursing Practice 1999; 5: 2 7 SCHOLARLY PAPER The good, the bad and the relative, part two: Goodness and the criterion problem in qualitative research Carolyn Emden RN, PhD Scholar in Residence, School of Nursing,The Flinders University of South Australia, Adelaide, Australia Margarete Sandelowski RN, PhD Professor, Department of Women s and Children s Health, School of Nursing, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill, United States of America Accepted for publication May 1998 Emden C., Sandelowski M. International Journal of Nursing Practice 1999; 5: 2 7 The good, the bad, and the relative, part two: Goodness and the criterion problem in qualitative research This (part two) paper finds the problem of the criterion at the heart of disputes about what constitutes goodness in qualitative research, an ancient philosophic conundrum as to how best represent reality. Ways around the problem are considered, including conceiving criteria as open-ended lists, and enabling conditions. Discussion principally concerns the impact of postmodernist thinking on the topic, and how qualitative researchers might usefully juxtapose the rationality of a modern world (in which notions such as reliability and validity are prized) with a mounting postmodern sensibility that acknowledges irrationality, fragmentation, and uncertainty. Part one of the paper traced efforts to define goodness in qualitative research within various fields, including nursing. Disputes were found to centre on how the traditional concepts of reliability and validity related to qualitative research. In reviewing various sets of criteria of goodness, these concepts were consequently conceived as being championed, translated, exiled, redeemed, and surpassed. Key words: criteria, goodness, postmodernism, qualitative research. ANCESTRY OF THE CRITERION Chisholm is quoted by Smith as stating that the problem of the criterion is one of the most important and difficult problems of philosophy. 1 Smith further suggests that one has not seriously thought about the nature of inquiry until one has confronted the criteria issue. 1 Positivism is home to the belief that reality exists out there and that the job of science is to discover this reality. Classically, in Correspondence: Dr Carolyn Emden, PO Box 187, Lobethal, SA 5241, Australia. Fax: +61 88201 3410; Email: <Carolyn.Emden@flinders.edu.au> order to control and predict reality (the natural world) great precision is necessary on the part of the scientist to verify conclusions reached. To distinguish whether things are really as they appear, that is, whether science is doing its job, is largely a matter of applying a correct method. 2 While positivism has long been overtaken by less purist assumptions (for example, reality exists but can never be fully apprehended... objectivity can only be approximated the problem of the criterion persists.that is, what counts as evidence of good science? Or, what counts as true? Criteria connotate efforts to develop and test

Goodness in qualitative research 3 propositions in a language from which all perspective, bias, and so forth have been removed 3 and are closely aligned with the notion of a rigor whose ancestry can similarly be traced to positivism and its problems.a properly done study possesses rigor. This search for scientific certitude persists, even within the very different ontological, epistemological, and methodological positions of qualitative research. This is apparent in the deeply pervasive use of the terms rigor and criteria within qualitative research literature, whether in debate about the topic per se, or within research reports and theses, or within discussions and decisions of review panels and funding boards. Importantly for this paper, once one has grasped the philosophic significance of the criterion problem, use of the term goodness (or substitute terms such as rigor, quality, standards, guidelines, or principles) is not an escape from the problem. At most, it suggests an attempt to grapple more reflectively with the problem. Usage of the various terms is not consistent in the literature, as will be shown; nevertheless some associations can be made, and we return to these in conclusion.the key point at this juncture is that all the terms, whatever their usage, are directed (wittingly or unwittingly) towards solving the criterion problem. CONTEMPLATING THE DEMISE OF CRITERIA Moving beyond criteriology 4 in terms of reliability and validity severs qualitative research from the tenets of positivism, a pleasing option for many, as shown in Part one of this paper. To move away from criteria per se is a vastly more complex enterprise. It could be argued that the prospect of a world (whether of research or other human endeavour) without reference points is analogous to being becalmed under leaden skies without a compass. Without an external guide of one form or another, how can we know what direction to take or, for that matter, what is good (or poor) qualitative research? Conversely, as Heshusius plainly puts it: If something is good, you know it. It is a mark of naivete to be dependent on a list of criteria to arrive at something you can trust. Such dependence is a regression into security seeking, a reverse kind of positivism. It is finding refuge once more in method. 5 To further confound the debate is the realisation that no criterion can ever be independent of our own construction of it. 5 Thus, the problem of the criterion is central to this discussion. Criteria as open-ended lists Smith describes one way around the criteria problem: conceiving criteria not as definite rules but as everevolving and open-ended lists. 1 Such a conception allows for items (criteria) to be added or subtracted, according to the use of the list. Criteria are thus constantly modified through practice and become dialogical in nature. The most common criticism of this approach, according to Smith, is that its adherents are not really talking about criteria or even research, they... have pushed nonfoundationalism so far that they are enmeshed in a completely unacceptable relativism, one that reduces knowledge to the level of merely belief, opinion, and/or taste. 1 Criteria as enabling conditions In a paper provocatively titled Farewell to criteriology, Schwandt makes a case for social science inquiry to be more accurately termed practical reasoning or practical philosophy. 3 As such, the focus is away from theorycentered, value neutral, atomistic, disengaged reason, towards democracy, at the heart of which lie five enabling conditions to do with dialogue, a community of interpreters, rhetoric, conversation, and imagination. 3 Schwandt also calls for a new vocabulary in which terms such as certainty are not used; rather, the word adoption suggests efforts to make something fit. Similarly, understanding is advocated instead of knowledge because of its greater versatility. Schwandt believes the biggest threat to his ideas is not relativism but cynicism, a disbelief in shared values.the title of this paper is only sustainable on the basis of its author s strict definition of criteriology: the quest for permanent or stable criteria of rationality. 3 More critically, Schwandt s ideas could be construed as the criterion problem in disguise. Inapplicability of criteria of goodness across qualitative traditions A further dimension to the criterion problem is an assumption that qualitative inquiry comprises a homogenous set of traditions that can be considered as one, for the purpose of determining quality. Atkinson argues against classification of various research approaches as qualitative: there is no single set of theoretical or methodological presuppositions to underpin a qualitative paradigm, nor is there an uncontested collection of methods and research exemplars. 6 While acknowledging there is some benefit in classification and simplification for teaching purposes, Atkinson maintains it is dangerously mis-

4 C. Emden and M. Sandelowski leading to treat qualitative methods in all their variety as paradigmatic. At best, any comprehensive listing of qualitative studies will reveal a collection of assumptions, methods, and kinds of data that share some broad family resemblances. As he points out, the processes of classification and simplification frequently go hand in hand. 6 Engel and Kuzel similarly argue that there are conflicting discourses within the qualitative research tradition, and attempt to apply in principle arguments to cover all cases that become too abstract to be useful. 7 They state that criteria for judging the quality of work in various traditions needed to be particular to the approach and might be markedly different across approaches. 7 Beck 8 goes further, claiming simplification within the same tradition can be misleading, taking as an example three proponents of phenomenology (Giorgi, Colaizzi and VanKaam), and showing how one cannot assume that similar criteria of rigor are applicable to each.these ideas are borne out by Lincoln who states that specific criteria might apply to specific kinds or classes of research and (intriguingly) that it might be best to permit criteria to grow indigenously as a natural consequence of the inquiry effort. 4 The demise of criteria per se seems a long way off, despite efforts by some authors to recast the problem as a non-issue. Philosophical problems tend not to go away in a hurry, as Lincoln, in possibly her most philosophical paper on this topic, concludes: We are not ready either to close down the conversation or to say farewell to criteria quite yet. 4 Confounding the problem is the mounting realisation that it may not be possible to keep a qualitative tradition alive as a coherent whole. It seems our topic of goodness in qualitative research may be fragmenting as we write, posing a considerable pragmatic challenge for those required to make speedy judgements about the quality of qualitative work, such as members of human research ethics committees, funding bodies, and editorial review boards, as well as consumers and the designers of the research in the first place. POSTMODERNIST THINKING AND DEBATES ABOUT GOODNESS Trends in thinking discussed above parallel shifts in philosophical ideas about knowledge. Like it or not, as Giroux says:... we have entered a new age, one that is marked by a crisis of power, patriarchy, authority, identity, and ethics. This new age has been described, for better or worse, by many theorists in a variety of disciplines as the age of postmodernism. It is a period torn between the ravages and benefits of modernism... we live in a time when a strong challenge is being waged against a modernist discourse in which knowledge is legitimized almost exclusively from a European model of culture and civilization. 9 The discourse to which LeCompte and Goetz 10 ascribed in 1982 was decidedly modernist, as was that of their criterion-oriented followers. It was a discourse of the Enlightenment, of science and certainty, truth and objectivity. The appeal to grand narratives was widespread, as indeed it still is today; that is, that there is some fixed point of reference (such as a set of criteria) to which one can turn for deciding courses of action, importance, and worth. The onset of a postmodern sensibility within many fields and disciplines is well captured by Bernstein when he speaks of a headiness or prevailing mood which is difficult to pin down, and confusing, a sense that something is happening that radically calls into question entrenched ways of thinking, acting and feeling. 11 Although postmodernism has multiple meanings (and indeed would be better termed postmodernisms on this account) philosophically speaking, it holds that the dualisms which continue to dominate Western thought are inadequate for understanding a world of multiple cause and effects interacting in complex and non-linear ways. 12 The growing discomfort of some authors with the criteria approach to determining goodness in qualitative research can be construed as directly related to these changing philosophical orientations. Take as an example Lincoln s views about positionality. 4 Others, disillusioned with the principles of modernity, have feelings of frustration and futility about what, if anything, might take their place in the face of postmodernism being widely viewed as pessimistic and nihilistic. As Cobb says: Deconstruction as carried forward by the leading French thinkers, Derrida and Foucault, problematizes everything that the modern world has taken for granted. It undercuts every quest for certainty. It does not seek to replace what it has torn down with a new edifice, showing instead the problematic character of the aim to construct any edifices at all. 13 Resistance to this pessimism of postmodernism is evident in the writings of authors such as Richardson who

Goodness in qualitative research 5 reflects upon the loss of grand theory in the field of sociology. 14 Richardson poses a thesis that seeks some positivity: How in the midst of this ferment and uncertainty do we prevent a paralysis of intellect and the will to work? Why do any intellectual work at all? But, conversely, why not? We can be caught in the infinite regress of deconstructionism, where nothing is better than anything else, but we can also be drawn to infinite expansion. 14 Richardson suggests we turn uncertainty to our advantage by being more sociologically imaginative in our thinking, apprehending, and writing of the social world. 14 Proponents of a search for goodness in qualitative research find it difficult to ignore the relevance to the criterion problem of these contemporary schools of thought. To abandon a search may be to sink into an infinite regress of meaninglessness; to continue a search may be to acknowledge the need for reference points as to what is good ; to engage a postmodern sensibility is to recognise the profound difficulty of all positions. CONCLUSION The good, the bad... Nursing imagination about goodness in qualitative research is still to find full expression. In searching for ways to make value judgements about qualitative knowledge, perhaps (as Richardson suggests 14 ) uncertainty can be turned to advantage, and novel avenues of thought forged, whereby both the impracticability of the grand narrative is recognised, as well as the richness and value of local contexts and meanings appreciated. Bringing such notions together creates a paradox, the irony of which is well highlighted by Parusnikova in her engaging paper Is a postmodern philosophy of science possible? 15 An invigorating development within nursing literature is the recognition of such ironies, together with a discussion of how they impact upon the developing tradition of qualitative research. For example, Parsons discusses at length the crisis of legitimation and representation in research methodology, brought about largely by postmodern debates. 16 While Parsons sees the postmodern era as bedevilled with insight, innovative and tentative methods and techniques, a reappraisal of epistemologies and ontologies, and contradiction, she also acknowledges that researchers must meanwhile get on with the activities of research that, for many, straddle modern and postmodern praxis. 16 Faced with meeting the positivist language demands and modernist research design expectations of funding agencies, Parsons finds she is nevertheless able to usefully integrate postmodern critiques of her modernist methods within research reports. She believes nurse researchers are especially well placed in this regard because of their diverse experience with people from all walks of life. Reed is another nursing author who proposes a framework for incorporating both modernist and postmodernist philosophies, referring to her framework as being beyond postmodernism or neomodernist. 17 Not all nursing authors share such optimism. Kermode 18 challenges the relevance of postmodernist ideas for contemporary nursing, and is critical, for example, of Watson s 1993 paper Postmodernism and knowledge development in nursing 19 for making extravagant claims about nursing and postmodernism. He believes nurses are caught in a postmodern hoax whereby they are prepared to forfeit control over their future in the face of capitalism and patriarchy, grand narratives which are not dead. One of the present paper s authors has also written in this vein, questioning whether nurses are wise to give up their humanist values to postmodernism, when in some respects they are still to experience their own enlightenment. 20 (Those interested in such debates may enjoy Wickham s paper, Theorising sociology in the face of postmodernism in which he reaches what he calls a tactically useful ambiguity towards postmodernism. 21 )... and the relative With the expression postmodernist qualitative research upon us, 18 we raise here the potential value of including among one s criteria for goodness a criterion of uncertainty ; that is, an open acknowledgement that claims about our research outcomes are at best tentative and that there may indeed be no way of showing otherwise. While such statements can be found in research reports, they usually appear as an apology for methodological weakness, not as a indication of the philosophic strength of the work. Our point is that to openly declare the uncertainty of one s work is to acknowledge the current state of play of knowledge development. Thorne is instructive on this same point when she speaks of reverence for probable truth, recognition that no set of standards can ensure confidence that research findings are indeed entirely valid. 22 In searching for ways to establish goodness in qualitative research, an array of ideas has been developed over the past few decades, informed by changing conceptions

6 C. Emden and M. Sandelowski of science and knowledge development. It strikes us that we are not faced with an either/or situation here: a notion of juxtapositioning (akin to Parson s 16 notion of straddling ) suggests that ideas can quite successfully jostle for legitimacy according to the particular situation. No one set of criteria can be expected to fit the bill for every research study.the diversity of approaches and traditions that is building within qualitative research alone works against such a possibility. Taken with this, a growing appreciation of postmodern debates about the fragility of knowledge leads to a celebration, rather than a decrying, of uncertainty and ambiguity. Such an approach arguably requires a thoughtful consideration of all possibilities for judging goodness within the particular situation, along with full and explicit documentation, like the decision trail described by Koch. 23 Important, is recognition that ultimately our decisions amount to a judgement call. As Marshall, in reviewing the historical evolution of assumptions affecting goodness criteria, puts it: We are merely making a judgment when deciding whether one study is more valid than another. We have to decide whose biases were more correct. All of the earlier assumptions really lead to this reality: evaluating the goodness and value of research requires a judgement call. 24 The common inclusion of quantitative elements within qualitative nursing research designs indicates that notions of reliability, validity and generalisability are of continuing importance. Indeed, reliability and validity in all their transformations are likely to persist within qualitative research. For example, Lincoln acknowledges that she still finds foundational criteria (reliability and validity) useful when working with doctoral students. 4 At the same time, nursing researchers shall continue to seek different means of demonstrating goodness within their qualitative projects, about which there is an increasingly useful body of literature upon which to draw. One suggestion, as mentioned, for determining goodness in qualitative research is to include evidence of a postmodern sensibility in such form as a criterion of uncertainty. To ignore the criterion problem within a postmodern context could be doing a disservice to the society we seek to better through our qualitative research, a point of ethics as much as goodness. Out of an increased appreciation of conceptions of goodness in qualitative research, potential exists for further clarification of terms and their meanings. As stated, although the usage of terms in the literature is not consistent, some associations can be made. For example, goodness is a generic, even philosophic, term that is used in a seeming attempt to identify quality in all dimensions of qualitative research; rigor, principles, standards, and evaluation hold quantitative connotations despite their usage within qualitative contexts; while critique, connoisseurship, artistry, and poetics hold particular and pointed qualitative connotations.yet, within all terms and usages, the criterion problem lurks. Meanwhile, postmodernist thinking decries all such searches for order and meaning, usefully reminding us that it is never too late to ask: Whose criteria? Criteria for what? and, Why criteria at all?. REFERENCES 1 Smith JK. Alternative research paradigms and the problem of criteria. In: Guba EG (ed.). The Paradigm Dialog. Newbury Park: Sage, 1990; 167 187. 2 Guba EG. The alternative paradigm dialog. In: Guba EG (ed.). The Paradigm Dialog. Newbury Park: Sage, 1990; 17 27. 3 Schwandt TA. Farewell to criteriology. Qualitative Inquiry 1996; 2: 58 72. 4 Lincoln Y. Emerging criteria for quality in qualitative and interpretive research. Qualitative Inquiry 1995; 1: 275 289. 5 Heshusius L. Discussion on criteria. In: Guba EG (ed.). The Paradigm Dialog. Newbury Park: Sage, 1990; 198 201. 6 Atkinson P. Some perils of paradigms. Qualitative Health Research 1995; 5: 117 124. 7 Engel JD, Kuzel AJ. On the idea of what constitutes good qualitative inquiry. Qualitative Health Research 1992; 2: 504 510. 8 Beck C. Reliability and validity issues in phenomenological research. Western Journal of Nursing Research 1994; 16: 254 267. 9 Giroux HA. Rethinking the boundaries of educational discourse: Modernism, postmodernism, and feminism. College Literature 1990; 17: 1 50. 10 LeCompte MD, Goetz JP. Problems of reliability and validity in ethnographic research. Review of Educational Research 1982; 52: 31 60. 11 Bernstein RJ. The New Constellation:The Ethical-political Horizons of Modernity/postmodernity. Oxford: Polity, 1992. 12 Lather P. Getting Smart: Feminist Research and Pedagogy with/in the Postmodern. New York: Routledge, 1991. 13 Cobb JB.Two types of postmodernism: Deconstruction and process. Theology Today 1990; 47: 149 158. 14 Richardson L.The collective story: Postmodernism and the writing of sociology. Sociological Focus 1988; 21: 199 208.

Goodness in qualitative research 7 15 Parusnikova Z. Is a postmodern philosophy of science possible? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 1992; 23: 21 37. 16 Parsons C. The impact of postmodernism on research methodology: Implications for nursing. Nursing Inquiry 1995; 2: 22 28. 17 Reed PG.A treatise on nursing knowledge development for the 21st century: Beyond postmodernism. Advances in Nursing Science 1995; 17: 70 84. 18 Kermode S.The postmodern hoax and its effects on nursing. International Journal of Nursing Studies 1996; 33: 375 384. 19 Watson J. Postmodernism and knowledge development in nursing. Nursing Science Quarterly 1995; 8: 60 64. 20 Emden C. A magnificent chaos: Feminist (nursing) comments on Western philosophy. Nursing Inquiry 1995; 2: 29 35. 21 Wickham G. Theorising sociology in the face of postmodernism. Australian and New Zealand Journal of Sociology 1991; 27: 351 368. 22 Thorne S. The art (and science) of critiquing qualitative research. In: Morse JM (ed.). Completing a Qualitative Project: Details and Dialogue. Thousand Oaks: Sage, 1997; 117 132. 23 Koch T. Establishing rigour in qualitative research:the decision trail. Journal of Advanced Nursing 1994; 19: 976 986. 24 Marshall C. Goodness criteria: Are they objective or judgement calls? In: Guba EG (ed.). The Paradigm Dialog. Newbury Park: Sage, 1990; 188 197.