WHY STUDY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY? 1

Similar documents
observation and conceptual interpretation

Postmodernism. thus one must review the central tenants of Enlightenment philosophy

Aristotle on the Human Good

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

Unified Reality Theory in a Nutshell

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

1) Three summaries (2-3 pages; pick three out of the following four): due: 9/9 5% due: 9/16 5% due: 9/23 5% due: 9/30 5%

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

The Art of Time Travel: A Bigger Picture

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Questions from sample assessment materials with student responses and commentaries 2 and 5 mark items

PDF hosted at the Radboud Repository of the Radboud University Nijmegen

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Lisa Randall, a professor of physics at Harvard, is the author of "Warped Passages: Unraveling the Mysteries of the Universe's Hidden Dimensions.

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

Emotions from the Perspective of Analytic Aesthetics

Pleasure, Pain, and Calm: A Puzzling Argument at Republic 583e1-8

The Influence of Chinese and Western Culture on English-Chinese Translation

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS GENERAL YEAR 12

2 Unified Reality Theory

Contradictions, Dialectics, and Paradoxes as Discursive Approaches to Organizational Analysis

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates Republic Symposium Republic Phaedrus Phaedrus), Theaetetus

LeBar s Flaccidity: Is there Cause for Concern?

Emerging Questions: Fernando F. Segovia and the Challenges of Cultural Interpretation

AP LATIN: VERGIL 2012 SCORING GUIDELINES

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

The Three Eyes and Modern Art

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

Mind, Thinking and Creativity

Care of the self: An Interview with Alexander Nehamas

Martin, Gottfried: Plato s doctrine of ideas [Platons Ideenlehre]. Berlin: Verlag Walter de Gruyter, 1973

3. The knower s perspective is essential in the pursuit of knowledge. To what extent do you agree?

Image and Imagination

A Meta-Theoretical Basis for Design Theory. Dr. Terence Love We-B Centre School of Management Information Systems Edith Cowan University

Challenging the View That Science is Value Free

Presented as part of the Colloquium Sponsored by the Lonergan Project at Marquette University on Lonergan s Philosophy and Theology

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

[T]here is a social definition of culture, in which culture is a description of a particular way of life. (Williams, The analysis of culture )

Current Issues in Pictorial Semiotics

TEST BANK. Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

Choosing your modules (Joint Honours Philosophy) Information for students coming to UEA in 2015, for a Joint Honours Philosophy Programme.

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

Conceptual Change, Relativism, and Rationality

Kuhn. History and Philosophy of STEM. Lecture 6

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Steven E. Kaufman * Key Words: existential mechanics, reality, experience, relation of existence, structure of reality. Overview

P O S T S T R U C T U R A L I S M

Song Wei, Qin Mingli. Dalian University of Technology

Architecture is epistemologically

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

Categories and Schemata

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Arakawa and Gins: The Organism-Person-Environment Process

Idealism and Pragmatism: "Transcendent" Validity Claims in Habermas's Democratic Theory

An essay on Alasdair MacIntyre s Relativism. Power and Philosophy

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

AESTHETICS. Key Terms

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE

The Power of Ideas: Milton Friedman s Empirical Methodology

ARISTOTLE S METAPHYSICS. February 5, 2016

A Condensed View esthetic Attributes in rts for Change Aesthetics Perspectives Companions

The phenomenological tradition conceptualizes

Incommensurability and the Bonfire of the Meta-Theories: Response to Mizrahi Lydia Patton, Virginia Tech

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Science: A Greatest Integer Function A Punctuated, Cumulative Approach to the Inquisitive Nature of Science

MATTHEWS GARETH B. Aristotelian Explanation. on "the role of existential presuppositions in syllogistic premisses"

Kant, Peirce, Dewey: on the Supremacy of Practice over Theory

LAKATOS IN DISGUISE. John Kadvany, Imre Lakatos and the Guises of Reason. Durham: Duke University Press. Pp. xx US$23.95 PB, US$69.95 HB.

Intention and Interpretation

The Psychology of Justice

Thomas Kuhn's "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions"

A New Approach to the Paradox of Fiction Pete Faulconbridge

A Brief Guide to Writing SOCIAL THEORY

Chudnoff on the Awareness of Abstract Objects 1

What is Postmodernism? What is Postmodernism?

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography

COPYRIGHT 2009 ASSOCIAZIONE PRAGMA

Pierre Hadot on Philosophy as a Way of Life. Pierre Hadot ( ) was a French philosopher and historian of ancient philosophy,

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

Words or Worlds: The Metaphysics within Kuhn s Picture of. Science. Justin Price

M E M O. When the book is published, the University of Guelph will be acknowledged for their support (in the acknowledgements section of the book).

CRITICAL STUDIES/BOOK REVIEWS

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

James SCOTT JOHNSTON, John Dewey s Earlier Logical Theory

Kant Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics, Preface, excerpts 1 Critique of Pure Reason, excerpts 2 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 9/19/13 12:13 PM

Is Hegel s Logic Logical?

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS ATAR YEAR 11

COURSE: PHILOSOPHY GRADE(S): NATIONAL STANDARDS: UNIT OBJECTIVES: Students will be able to: STATE STANDARDS:

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Transcription:

WHY STUDY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY? 1 Why Study the History of Philosophy? David Rosenthal CUNY Graduate Center CUNY Graduate Center May 19, 2010 Philosophy and Cognitive Science http://davidrosenthal1.googlepages.com/ OVERVIEW I. Two Concepts of Philosophy II. Why Study Its History: Some Standard Reasons CUNY Graduate Center 5/19/10 2

WHY STUDY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY? 2 I. Two Concepts of Philosophy I d like to begin with a question: When did you last notice two people now working in philosophy who understood each another s views and arguments? Answer: Very likely when you last noticed two who agreed about the relevant views and arguments use to support them. So how about two who don t thus agree: When did you see two such people who nonetheless understood each other well? I. Two Concepts of Philosophy 3 This isn t because philosophy is abstract and often technical and complicated; such epidemic mutual misunderstanding is strikingly rare in mathematics and physics. How about in the (other) humanities? Mutual misunderstanding di isn t all that t rare in literature, music, and the arts. Professors and critics often just stick to their own views which which often seem all but incommensurable with those of others and mainly fight for those views rather than foster mutual comprehension. Such observations may tempt us to accept librarians and deans placing philosophy among the humanities, rather than as a distinctively theoretical discipline. I. Two Concepts of Philosophy 4

WHY STUDY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY? 3 The resemblance to the humanities figures also in the significant place historical work has in our field. That s characteristic of the humanities, not at all of the sciences. Postmodernism capitalizes on this, arguing that t philosophical l work is best seen as deconstruction or an ongoing conversation, and as not, despite its pretensions, seeking to get at the truth about things. That picture does no justice to philosophy, which plainly does aim at solving problems. But there s yet another resemblance to the humanities: Past philosophers built big systems, which may suggest perspectives and ways of looking at reality perhaps not unlike the way great works of art often do. I. Two Concepts of Philosophy 5 So the history of such systems may seem like a history of ways of looking at things again on analogy with the humanities. It offers alternate routes to understanding and insight about the nature of reality. But t the system builders themselves plainly l aimed at getting things right getting getting at the truth so one could read just their books and not bother with any alternatives. Aristotle, Hume, Kant, and Hegel all argued that their predecessors were just wrong. Past work in science is incorporated (if true) or discarded (if not).. So why is there any distinctively philosophical role for systems that do not capture the truth apart from their being part of our cultural heritage? I. Two Concepts of Philosophy 6

WHY STUDY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY? 4 Perhaps the current view of philosophy as one of the humanities and its history as significant distorts its nature, seeing it just as providing insight and understanding in contrast with the (real) sciences, which do get at the truth about things. The sciences theorize about the nature of things. Science is truth seeking, the arts interpretative. Where does philosophy fit? Philosophy is truth seeking, but finds its history significant and and not a mere adjunct. What role does that history play? And how to reconcile philosophy s problem-solving nature with the emphasis on its history? I ll mainly discuss the first question, saying a bit about the second at the very end. I. Two Concepts of Philosophy 7 II. Why Study History? The standard reasons are unconvincing. Historical work is occasionally suggestive perhaps nowhere more than Aristotle on ethics, but also Brentano for Chisholm and Spinoza for Hampshire. But that s rare. Past work may be seen as a cautionary list of mistakes not to make; but past mistakes are seldom relevant to contemporary work. Past philosophers often argued for their own view by showing how it undermined those of their predecessors. But now that s mainly done with our contemporaries who after all can talk back! II. Why Study History? 8

WHY STUDY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY? 5 It s often said that we can understand today s issues only by seeing their origin. But issues must be framed ahistorically. And if issues do figure only in a historical context, why take them seriously? In that t spirit, it historical i work is often used as a ramp to get students into the issues. But that s typically done with snippets and simplifications that often distort the texts; it s mainly strawmen, not history. A A variation: We understand current issues only if we see them as problematic, which requires historical context. But something seems puzzling if we lack a solution not not because of how it arose. And past issues rarely commensurate with current versions. II. Why Study History? 9 Historical work offers views and arguments we might otherwise not consider. But older views seldom commensurate with our own. Historical work provides touchstones not just shortcuts, but ostensibly neutral points of common currency, e.g., Hume on causation. But these are seldom neutral and rarely require any historical study. Perhaps as 19 th -century science came to occupy turf formerly ruled by philosophy, philosophy retreated from Kant s secure path of a science (Bvii) to the safety of the humanities, encouraged by an Hegelian historicism. But that sacrifices philosophy s truth-seeking, problem-solving character to explain the role of its history. II. Why Study History? 10

WHY STUDY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY? 6 The standard reasons not only are pretty unconvincing; they all have an air of ad hoc rationalization. And that suggests something deeper is going on, not revealed by these appeals to superficial usefulness. What might that be? The epidemic failure in philosophy of mutual understanding di suggests an answer. How do we understand what anybody says? We have nothing to go on but that person s words, which we must construe in the best possible way. But how? 11 Sometimes the best we can do results in words that don t apply to things we understand, sentences we see as untrue, and questionable inferences. Then we just don t understand the other person s words. Understanding d t di requires casting others words so that they referentially match our own, result in sentences we see as true often enough to frame our understanding of other, puzzling sentences, and result in inferences that seem compelling to us. These forms of charity are unavoidable. But charity has all three forms which may pull in incompatible directions. So we must strike a balance, and there needn t be one that s best a unique best interpretation. 12

WHY STUDY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY? 7 But things are even worse. Words used in philosophy don t have fixed applications. And there s divergence about background assumptions and about which inferences are compelling. So the three forms of charity rarely yield straightforward results. To figure out what words apply to, what background beliefs are true, and what inferences valid, we must settle relevant philosophical issues. We can t interpret others work without views, however provisional, on the relevant matters. So doing anything in history of philosophy requires working on philosophical issues it s just that the issues arise in the context of interpreting texts. 13 We can see the role of charity in current debate. Commentators often seem almost deliberately to misunderstand those they discuss. That s seldom bad faith so much as misconstruals due to differences about what words refer to, what s true, and what inferences are compelling. Still, it s often hard or impossible to get past that. Contemporary commentary often proceeds a few sentences at a time. Historical texts, by structure, require interpreting things in the context of complex systems. That makes things harder, since one must take into account the connections among issues that figure in interpreting the text. But there s a big compensatory payoff. 14

WHY STUDY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY? 8 For one thing, we must grapple with how issues raised in the text hang together. Far more important, because the texts are so systematic, the philosophical issues one needs to settle for charitable interpretation will themselves exhibit rich systematic ti interrelations. Construing here requires work on systematically connected issues. So serious historical work in philosophy calls for doing enough systematic work on interconnected philosophical issues to have relevant views about what s true and what inferences are compelling. Interpreting systematic historical texts requires systematic background thinking of one s own about philosophical issues. 15 In conclusion, a few global remarks. Dewey spoke of those astounding differences of philosophic belief that startle the beginner and that become the plaything of the expert. He diagnosed this as due to theoretical [c]hoice that is disguised or denied i.e., undisclosed, optional assumptions. Dewey urged that we see each choice as a theoretical experiment to be tried on its merits and tested by its results i.e., its theoretical payoff in explaining and describing things (All Exp. & Nat., 30). The history of philosophy does suggest this unsettling multiplicity of incommensurate systems that one can jump into at will. 16

WHY STUDY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY? 9 Dewey s seemingly irresoluble multiplicity of systems occur only in the history of philosophy. Current oppositions answer and yield to some extent to argument. But the historical multiplicity of systems can be useful. Systems often oppose one another due to hidden shared assumptions, which charitable interpreting can reveal. And that in turn can suggest ways to get past the doctrines those systems embody to arrive at stable positions on the issues. By noting the interplay among the systems themselves, which charitable interpretation makes salient, we can hope to work toward transcending the systems themselves. So studying them is useful. 17 Charitable interpreting is essential to work in the history of philosophy, as is attention to systematic connections among issues one must work on to do the relevant charitable interpreting. That t interpretative t ti aspect of the history of philosophy recalls the interpreting essential to all the standard humanities. Because its history is inextricably tied to work on substantive issues in philosophy itself, there is an aspect of philosophy p that genuinely resembles the humanities. But that fits comfortably within picture of philosophy as a truth-seeking discipline. As Plato noted, philosophy is not on a par with the arts. 18

WHY STUDY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY? 10 Thank you very much CUNY Graduate Center 5/19/10 19