Spectrum inversion as a challenge to intentionalism

Similar documents
Types of perceptual content

6 Bodily Sensations as an Obstacle for Representationism

1/10. Berkeley on Abstraction

Perceptions and Hallucinations

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

Book Reviews Department of Philosophy and Religion Appalachian State University 401 Academy Street Boone, NC USA

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Objective Interpretation and the Metaphysics of Meaning

Perception and Mind-Dependence Lecture 3

Faculty of Philosophy, University of Cambridge Part IB: Metaphysics & Epistemology

On Recanati s Mental Files

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

Conceptualism and Phenomenal Character

The red apple I am eating is sweet and juicy. LOCKE S EMPIRICAL THEORY OF COGNITION: THE THEORY OF IDEAS. Locke s way of ideas

In The Mind and the World Order, C.I. Lewis made a famous distinction between the

McDowell, Demonstrative Concepts, and Nonconceptual Representational Content Wayne Wright

24.500/Phil253 topics in philosophy of mind/perceptual experience

Naturalizing Phenomenology? Dretske on Qualia*

Diachronic and synchronic unity

THE SENSATION OF COLOUR

The Two-Dimensional Content of Consciousness

Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science

Twentieth Excursus: Reference Magnets and the Grounds of Intentionality

A New Approach to the Paradox of Fiction Pete Faulconbridge

Image and Imagination

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

A Higher-order, Dispositional Theory of Qualia. John O Dea. Abstract

Affect, perceptual experience, and disclosure

LeBar s Flaccidity: Is there Cause for Concern?

IS THE SENSE-DATA THEORY A REPRESENTATIONALIST THEORY? Fiona Macpherson

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

Truest Blue. Alex Byrne and David R. Hilbert. 1. The puzzle

206 Metaphysics. Chapter 21. Universals

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

A Confusion of the term Subjectivity in the philosophy of Mind *

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

This essay provides an overview of the debate concerning the admissible. contents of experience, together with an introduction to the papers in this

Individualism and the Aesthetic

M. Chirimuuta s Adverbialism About Color. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. I. Color Adverbialism

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

Berkeley s idealism. Jeff Speaks phil October 30, 2018

Thomas Szanto: Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Comments on Bence Nanay, Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery

SNP Best-set Typesetter Ltd. Article No.: 583 Delivery Date: 31 October 2005 Page Extent: 4 pp

The central and defining characteristic of thoughts is that they have objects. The object

The Embedding Problem for Non-Cognitivism; Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Abstract of Graff: Taking Cover in Coverage. Graff, Gerald. "Taking Cover in Coverage." The Norton Anthology of Theory and

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Thesis-Defense Paper Project Phi 335 Epistemology Jared Bates, Winter 2014

Scents and Sensibilia Clare Batty University of Kentucky

Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008

We know of the efforts of such philosophers as Frege and Husserl to undo the

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

Ridgeview Publishing Company

Indexical Concepts and Compositionality

PARAGRAPHS ON DECEPTUAL ART by Joe Scanlan

Seeing Cherries Typically:

Investigating subjectivity

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Philosophy of sound, Ch. 1 (English translation)

Volume 59 Number 236 July 2009

An autonomist view on the ethical criticism of architecture

THE ECOLOGICAL MEANING OF EMBODIMENT

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Chudnoff on the Awareness of Abstract Objects 1

Katalin Farkas Central European University, Budapest

A Succession of Feelings, in and of Itself, is Not a Feeling of Succession

THE PROPOSITIONAL CHALLENGE TO AESTHETICS

The Sensory Basis of Historical Analysis: A Reply to Post-Structuralism ERIC KAUFMANN

The erratically fine-grained metaphysics of functional kinds in technology and biology

Uskali Mäki Putnam s Realisms: A View from the Social Sciences

Four Theories of Amodal Perception

FUNCTIONALISM AND THE QUALIA WARS. Ekai Txapartegi

Exploring touch: A review of Matthew Fulkerson s The First Sense

Owen Barfield. Romanticism Comes of Age and Speaker s Meaning. The Barfield Press, 2007.

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

dialectica The Place of Subjects in the Metaphysics of Material Objects

By Tetsushi Hirano. PHENOMENOLOGY at the University College of Dublin on June 21 st 2013)

Goldie s Puzzling Two Feelings: Bodily Feeling and Feeling Toward

Could Hume Save His Account of Personal Identity? On the Role of Contiguity in the Constitution of Our Idea of Personal Identity 1

Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates Republic Symposium Republic Phaedrus Phaedrus), Theaetetus

The Invalidity of the Argument from Illusion

Existential Cause & Individual Experience

On The Search for a Perfect Language

The Art of Time Travel: A Bigger Picture

ALIGNING WITH THE GOOD

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN:

The Revealed Yet Still Hidden Relation between Form & the Formless

The Ancient Philosophers: What is philosophy?

Level 2 Award. Thinking and Reasoning Skills. Mark Scheme for January OCR Level 2 Award Unit 1 B901: Thinking and Reasoning Skills

Formal Properties as the Basis for Value in Music

Kent Academic Repository

N E W S L E T T E R 4 1 JUL 15. July 2015 How would we feel if Aliens took over our Lives? Page 1 Your Step to Reconciliation Roseline Deleu Page 5

Transcription:

Spectrum inversion as a challenge to intentionalism phil 93515 Jeff Speaks April 18, 2007 1 Traditional cases of spectrum inversion Remember that minimal intentionalism is the claim that any two experiences of a given sense modality which have the same content will also have the same phenomenal character: i.e., if two such experiences have the same content, then what it s like to have the one experience will be the same as what it s like to have the other. Let s take the interpersonal version of this thesis, i.e. x y (x & y are experiences of the same sense modality with the same content x & y have the same phenomenology) The first thing to see is how certain kinds of inverted spectrum examples can be used to challenge minimal intentionalism. Any counterexample to minimal intentionalism will be a pair of possible experiences which satisfy the following description: e 1 and e 2 are experiences of the same sense modality, and have the same content (represent the world as being the same way). But e 1 and e 2 have different phenomenal character: what it s like to have e 1 is different from what it s like to have e 2. To see how the inverted spectrum can seem to provide an example of this sort, consider the passage by which Locke introduced the inverted spectrum scenario into the philosophical literature: Neither would it carry any Imputation of Falsehood to our simple Ideas, if by the different Structure of our Organs, it were so ordered, That the same Object should produce in several Men s Minds different Ideas at the same time; v.g. if the Idea, that a Violet produced in one Man s Mind by his Eyes, were the same that a Marigold produces in another Man s, and vice versa. For since this could never be known: because one Man s Mind could not pass into another Man s Body, to perceive, what Appearances were produced by those Organs; neither the Ideas hereby, nor the Names, would be at all confounded, or any Falsehood be in either. For all Things, that had the Texture of a Violet,

producing constantly the Idea, which he called Blue, and those which had the Texture of a Marigold, producing constantly the Idea, which he as constantly called Yellow, whatever those Appearances were in his Mind; he would be able as regularly to distinguish Things for his Use by those Appearances, and understand, and signify those distinctions, marked by the Names Blue and Yellow, as if the Appearances, or Ideas in his Mind, received from those two Flowers, were exactly the same, with the Ideas in other Men s Minds. (Essay on Human Understanding, II.xxxii.15) Here we are asked to imagine two different subjects whose blue and yellow experiences are inverted. That is, when A looks at a violet, his experiences seems to him exactly how B s experiences when looking at marigolds seem to him. But, Locke says, this description does not carry any imputation of Falsehood about the experiences of either. He argues for this claim when he says each would be able as regularly to distinguish Things for his Use by those Appearances as the other. Let s suppose that Locke is right about this, and that two perceivers could have their experiences as of blue and yellow things inverted with respect to each other without either misperceiving the world at all. This thought can be turned into an argument against minimal intentionalism as follows (using, as has become standard, Invert for the name of the perceiver whose experiences are inverted with respect to ours, and Nonvert for the name of the perceiver whose experiences are not inverted with respect to ours): 1. When Invert and Nonvert look at a violet, their experiences have different phenomenal characters. (Premise) 2. When Invert and Nonvert look at a violet, neither misperceives the color of the violet. (Premise) 3. The violet is only one color. (Premise) 4. Invert and Nonvert represent the violet as having the same color. (2,3) 5. There is no other difference in the contents of the experiences of Invert and Nonvert. (Premise) 6. The experiences of Invert and Nonvert have the same content. (4,5) C. The experiences of Invert and Nonvert have the same content, but different phenomenal characters. (1,6) (1) and (2) are the assumptions built into the scenario that Locke imagines; but once we have these assumptions in hand, we need only the plausible further assumptions (3) and (5) to yield (C), which is inconsistent with minimal intentionalism. This is why the possibility of spectrum inversion without misrepresentation is often thought to show that minimal intentionalism must be false. We will consider in turn three responses on behalf of the intentionalist: 1. If Invert and Nonvert are appropriately similar, then (1) is not metaphysically possible. 2. Premise (5) is false, since there is a difference in the contents of the experiences of Invert and Nonvert other than their representation of the color of the violet. 2

3. Premise (2) is false, and one of Invert and Nonvert have the color of the violet wrong. 2 Intrapersonal inverted spectrum cases It is worth mentioning first one sort of response you might have to the inverted spectrum example above: you might think that this sort of example shows that interpersonal versions of intentionalism are false, but that an intrapersonal version is still true. One way to bring out the problems with this move is via Block s discussion of the possibility of intrapersonal spectrum inversion: First, we have a functionally normal person. Second inverting lenses are placed in his eyes and he says grass looks red and blood looks green. Third, after a period of confused use of color terms, he finally adapts to the point where he uses color language normally. That is, he naturally and immediately describes blood as red and grass as green. At the third stage, he is functionally normal except in one important respect: he recalls the period before the insertion of the lenses as a period in which grass looked to me the way blood now looks. Fourth, he has amnesia about the period before the lenses were inserted and is functionally totally normal just as in the first period. It is plausible that if you have the intuition that there is no misrepresentation in Locke s case, you should also have the intuition that there is no misrepresentation here. So spectrum inversion is a problem for intrapersonal versions of intentionalism as much as for interpersonal versions. 3 Inverted earth This is also a good time to consider the challenge to intentionalism posed by the example of Inverted earth. Here is Block s description of the example: lnverted Earth differs from Earth in two respects. Firstly, everything has the com- plementary color of the color on Earth. The sky is yellow, grass is red, fire hydrants are green, etc. I mean everything really has these oddball colors. If you visited Inverted Earth along with a team of scientists from your university, you would all agree that on this planet, the sky is yellow, grass is red, etc. Secondly, the vocabulary of the residents of Inverted Earth is also inverted: If you ask what color the (yellow) sky is, they (truthfully) say Blue!. If you ask what color the (red) grass is, they say Green. If you brought a speaker of the Inverted Earth dialect to a neutral place (with unknown sky color, unfamiliar vegetation, and the like) and employed a team of linguists using any reasonable methods to plumb his language, you would have to come to the conclusion that he uses red to mean what we mean by green, blue to mean what we mean by yellow, etc. You would have to come 3

to the conclusion that the Inverted Earth dialect differs from ours in inverted meanings of color words. If commerce develops between the two planets and painters on Inverted Earth order paint from one of our paint stores, we shall have to translate their order for green paint into an order to our stock-boy to get red paint. Inverted Earth differs from earth in switched words and switched stimuli. It seems undeniable that people in Inverted Earth believe, and say, that the sky is yellow and that they are correct in this even though they use the word blue to describe the color of the sky. As Block says, there is nothing here which seems any more puzzling than the idea that one word can have different meanings in two languages. But now consider the following example: A team of mad scientists knock you out. While you are out cold, they insert color inverting lenses in your eyes, and change your body pigments so you don t have a nasty shock when you wake up and look at your feet. They transport you to Inverted Earth, where you are substituted for a counterpart who has occupied a niche on Inverted Earth that corresponds exactly (except for colors of things) with your niche at home. You wake up, and since the inverting lenses cancel out the inverted colors, you notice no difference at all. What it s like for you to interact with the world and with other people does not change at all. For example, the yellow sky looks blue to you, and all the people around you describe yellow objects such as the sky as blue. As far as the qualitative aspect of your mental life is concerned, nothing is any different from the way it would have been had you stayed home. Further, we may suppose that your brain is exactly the same in its physiological properties as it would have been had you stayed at home. Since things seem just the same to you after you are transported to Inverted Earth, it is very plausible that the phenomenology of your gazing at the sky is unchanged. But, Block suggests, the contents of your experiences of looking at the sky will, eventually, change: I would say that on your first day on Inverted Earth, your intentional contents remain the same as they were-that is different from the natives. At first, when you look at the sky, thinking the thought that you would express as It is as blue as ever, you are expressing the same thought that you would have been expressing yesterday at home, only today you are wrong. Also, your thought is not the same as the one a native of Inverted Earth would express with the same words. Nonetheless, according to me, after enough time has passed on Inverted Earth, your embedding in the physical and linguistic environment of Inverted Earth would dominate, and so your intentional contents would shift so as to be the same as those of the natives. Consider an analogy (supplied by Martin Davies): if you had a Margaret Thatcher recognitional capacity before your journey to Inverted Earth, and on arriving misidentify twin MT as MT, you are mistaken. But eventually your That s MT judgements get to 4

be about twin MT, and so become right having started out wrong. If you were kidnapped at age 15, by the time 50 years have passed, you use red to mean green, just as the natives do. Once your intentional contents have inverted, so do your functional states. The state that is now normally caused by blue things is the same state that earlier was normally caused by yellow things. So once 50 years have passed, you and your earlier stage at home would exemplify what I want, namely a case of functional and intentional inversion together with the same qualitative contents-the converse of the inverted spectrum case. So it looks like we have a case in which two color experiences (of the same person at different times) have the same phenomenology, but very different content. A first pass at a reply by the intentionalist is to say that this is an objection to biconditional rather than minimal intentionalism. After all, minimal intentionalism does not rule out differences in content which are accompanied by no difference in phenomenology. However, this is clearly not enough, as is shown by recalling the example of content inversion we discussed above. Consider my experience of The moral is that even if the minimal intentionalist can allow differences in content which are not differences in phenomenology, he cannot allow large differences in phenomenologyaffecting contents which are not differences in phenomenology. So the example of inverted earth is a problem for the minimal as well as the biconditional intentionalist. Three replies open to the minimal intentionalist: Say that in this case the meanings of your words come apart from the contents of your beliefs and perceptions. Say that in this case the contents of your beliefs and words come apart from the contents of your perceptions. Deny that the phenomenology of your experiences stays the same while you live in Inverted Earth. Maybe by the time the meanings of your words change, the phenomenology of your experience of looking at the sky has also changed (from a blu-ish phenomenology to a yellow-ish one). Deny that the meanings of your words change while you are living in Inverted Earth. Maybe the meanings of names would change, but the meanings of color words would not. The final option seems in some ways to be the best, but it is not obvious how to spell it out in a way which would not entail that color blind people mean different things by color words than we do. (There s probably an analogous problem with the contents of the beliefs of the color blind with respect to the first option above.) The third option might seem plausible if we are willing to be externalists about phenomenology. But, as? points out, there is a difficulty here in seeing how the shift in phenomenology could take place. Would it be all at once? Then it would surely be noticeable. Would it be gradual? In that case it is hard to see what the intermediate 5

stages between blue-seeing and yellow-seeming phenomenology would be. Would one s experiences have a green-seeming phenomenology for a while? References Ned Block, 1990. Inverted Earth. Philosophical Perspectives 4:52 79. John Locke, 1689. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Michael Tye, 2000. Consciousness, Color, and Content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 6