Self-reference. Sereny's presentation in "Godel, Tarski, Church, and the Liar,"' although the main idea is

Similar documents
Disquotation, Conditionals, and the Liar 1

CS/MA 109 Quantitative Reasoning. Wayne Snyder Computer Science Department Boston University

Scientific Philosophy

Introduction: A Musico-Logical Offering

On Meaning. language to establish several definitions. We then examine the theories of meaning

Background to Gottlob Frege

Haskell Brooks Curry was born on 12 September 1900 at Millis, Massachusetts and died on 1 September 1982 at

Nissim Francez: Proof-theoretic Semantics College Publications, London, 2015, xx+415 pages

cse371/mat371 LOGIC Professor Anita Wasilewska

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Cambridge Introductions to Philosophy new textbooks from cambridge

Glossary alliteration allusion analogy anaphora anecdote annotation antecedent antimetabole antithesis aphorism appositive archaic diction argument

Paradoxes: Part 2 of 2. Of Art and Mathematics. feature. Punya Mishra & Gaurav Bhatnagar. Self - Reference and Russell s Paradox

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

Dan Nesher, Department of Philosophy University of Haifa, Israel

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press,

Vagueness & Pragmatics

2 nd Int. Conf. CiiT, Molika, Dec CHAITIN ARTICLES

Elements of Style. Anders O.F. Hendrickson

6.034 Notes: Section 4.1

Frege: Two Kinds of Meaning

138 Great Problems in Philosophy and Physics - Solved? Chapter 11. Meaning. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/knowledge/meaning

Prospectus Final Draft

Philosophy Historical and Philosophical Foundations of Set Theory Syllabus: Autumn:2005

Peirce's Remarkable Rules of Inference

COMP Intro to Logic for Computer Scientists. Lecture 2

A Notion of Logical Concept based on Plural Reference

AP LANGUAGE & COMPOSITION SUMMER ASSIGNMENT

MATH 195: Gödel, Escher, and Bach (Spring 2001) Notes and Study Questions for Tuesday, March 20

Tools for Thinking. Chapter Introduction. 2.2 Formal Systems. Always Be Prepared. Boy Scout Motto

1/ 19 2/17 3/23 4/23 5/18 Total/100. Please do not write in the spaces above.

Tarski on Logical Notions

Non-Classical Logics. Viorica Sofronie-Stokkermans Winter Semester 2012/2013

THE PROBLEM OF INTERPRETING MODAL LOGIC w. V. QUINE

What is formal logic? Jean-Yves Béziau Federal University of Ceara CNPq/DCR - FUNCAP Brazil

Formalising arguments

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

Appendix B. Elements of Style for Proofs

COMMON FORMATIVE ASSESSMENT PLANNING TEMPLATE Greenfield/Rosedale RCD Project

Charles Ball, "the Georgian Slave"

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Mathematical Principles of Fuzzy Logic

English III Honors 2018 Summer Assignment

THE CREATIVE CIRCLE: SKETCHES ON THE NATURAL HISTORY OF CIRCULARITY

Logical Foundations of Mathematics and Computational Complexity a gentle introduction

Guide for Author s Manuscript Submission

AP English Language and Composition Summer Assignment 2017

Scholarly Paper Publication

Symbolization and Truth-Functional Connectives in SL

BROUWER'S CONTRIBUTIONS TO THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS*

SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE AND RELIGIOUS RELATION TO REALITY

Replies to the Critics

Formalizing Irony with Doxastic Logic

Basic English. Robert Taggart

PARADOX AND ARGUMENTATION

House Style for Physical Geography at Keele. Updated 25 th September 2012, Peter G Knight

The Cognitive Nature of Metonymy and Its Implications for English Vocabulary Teaching

Introduction Section 1: Logic. The basic purpose is to learn some elementary logic.

What is formal logic? Jean-Yves Béziau

Alfred Tarski in Poland: New Translations and Background

INTERPRETING FORMAL LOGIC *

COMMON GRAMMAR ERRORS. By: Dr. Elham Alzoubi

QUANTIFICATION IN AFRICAN LOGIC. Jonathan M. O. Chimakonam Ph.D Department of Philosophy University of Calabar, Nigeria

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

Quine s Two Dogmas of Empiricism. By Spencer Livingstone

A Functional Representation of Fuzzy Preferences

Advanced Placement English Language and Composition Mrs. Ellie Kenworthy 2016 Summer Reading Assignment

Computability and Logic, Fifth Edition

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

Corcoran, J George Boole. Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2nd edition. Detroit: Macmillan Reference USA, 2006

4. Rhetorical Analysis

QUESTIONS AND LOGICAL ANALYSIS OF NATURAL LANGUAGE: THE CASE OF TRANSPARENT INTENSIONAL LOGIC MICHAL PELIŠ

RUSSELL AND FREGE ON THE LOGIC OF FUNCTIONS

POST STRUCTURAL READINGS OF A LOGICO-MATHEMATICAL TEXT. 1. The project

Introduction p. 1 The Elements of an Argument p. 1 Deduction and Induction p. 5 Deductive Argument Forms p. 7 Truth and Validity p. 8 Soundness p.

The Liar Paradox in Plato

Designing a Deductive Foundation System

The indefinite articles 1. We use the article a / an when we are talking about something for the first time or not specific things.


Intensional Relative Clauses and the Semantics of Variable Objects

Paradigm paradoxes and the processes of educational research: Using the theory of logical types to aid clarity.

mcs 2015/5/18 1:43 page 15 #23

Who's Kicking Who? RICHARD LANHAM

INTRODUCTION TO AXIOMATIC SET THEORY

Essential Aspects of Academic Practice (EAAP)

THE PARADOX OF ANALYSIS

Solution to Digital Logic )What is the magnitude comparator? Design a logic circuit for 4 bit magnitude comparator and explain it,

THE SUBSTITUTIONAL ANALYSIS OF LOGICAL CONSEQUENCE

Taylor & Francis Standard Reference Style: Chicago author-date

The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall 2015

08/2018 Franz Steiner Verlag

LEVEL PRE-A1 LAAS LANGUAGE ATTAINMENT ASSESSMENT SYSTEM. English English Language Language Examinations Examinations. December 2005 May 2016

Support materials. Elementary Podcast Series 02 Episode 05

Candidate Surname. Candidate Number

Frege on the Psychological. John F. Horty. Philosophy Department and. University of Maryland. College Park, MD (

THE SUBSTITUTIONAL ANALYSIS OF LOGICAL CONSEQUENCE

2176 Book Reviews as free open-source software, will serve as a lasting contribution of the translation project even beyond the translation itself. Vo

Transcription:

Self-reference The following result is a cornerstone of modern logic: Self-reference Lemma. For any formula q(x), there is a sentence 4 such - that (4 $([re])) is a consequence of Q. Proof: The proof breaks down into two parts. The hard part is to see what sentence 4 to use, and the easy part is to verifl that it works. In approaching the hard part, I'll be following Gyorgy Sereny's presentation in "Godel, Tarski, Church, and the Liar,"' although the main idea is already there in Godel's original paper.2 The key idea goes back to the 6th century BCE, when the Cretan Epimenides said that Cretans always lie. Assuming for argument that the other statements made by Cretans are all blatent falsehoods, we find ourselves inexorably driven to the unhappy conclusion that, if what Epimenides says is true, it is false, whereas if what he says is false, it is true. It is doubtful that Epimenides realized the paradoxical nature of what he said, but someone who was fully aware of the cognitive disturbance was Eubulides of Miletas, a contemporary of Aristotle, who asked us to assess what is said by someone who declares, "What I am now saying is false." Eubulides is credited with other notorious paradoxes, notably the sorites (The observation that taking a single straw fiom a heap of straw still leaves you with a heap of straw leads, by multiple applications, 1. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 9 (2003): 3-25. 2. "aer formal unentscheidbare Satze der Principia mathematica und venvandter Systeme I." Monatsheftefir Mathematik und Physik 38 (1931): 173-198. English translations in Jean van Heijenoort, ed., From Frege to Godel (Cambridge, Mass., and London: Harvard University Press, 1967), pp. 596-616, and in Martin Davis, ed., The Undecidable (Hewlett, N.Y.: Raven Press, 1965), pp. 4-38.

Self-reference Theorem, p. 2 to the conclusion that there is a heap of straw that contains no straw at all) and the hooded man (You do not know who the hooded man is, but you do know who your father is, even though, unknown to you, the hooded man is your father; this contradicts the logical principle that names that denote the same thing can be exchanged). Eubulides' formulation is in one way sharper than Epimenides', since it doesn't depend on the mendacity of all one's neighbors. However, it introduces a new level of complexity, since it contains the indexicals "now" and "I." You can avoid these complexities by looking at page 65 of the June 1969 issue of ScientiJc Ameri~an,~ where you will find the sentence, "The sentence printed in red on page 65 of the June 1969 issue of ScientiJc American is false," printed in red. This still isn't what we need for present purposes. For present purposes, we would like to reproduce a version of the liar paradox (with is place of "is false") within the language of arithmetic, and contingent facts about who said what when and where aren't expressible within the language of arithmetic. What is expressible within the language of arithmetic is syntax, which we can express by means of the Godel coding. So we would like to examine a version of the lair paradox that identifies the offending sentence in purely syntactic terms. A purely syntactic version of the liar paradox is given by Q~ine:~ "Yields a falsehood when appended to its own quotation" yields a falsehood when appended to its own quotation. 3. This is Tarski's article, "Truth and Proof." 4. "The Ways of Paradox" from The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays, revised ed. (Cambrdige, Mass., and London: Harvard University Press), 1976.

Self-reference Theorem, p. 3 Quine's construction generalizes nicely. Given a property P, consider the following sentence: "Yields a sentence with property P when appended to its own quotation" yields a sentence with property P when appended to its own quotation. The sentence is true if and only if it has property P. This still isn't quite what we want, however, because it relies on a syntactic feature that English doesn't share with the formal language, namely, that you can form a sentence by concatenating a (possibly complex) noun phrase with a (possibly complex) verb phrase. An alternative formulation that does generalize uses the operation of substituting a noun phrase for a ~ariable.~ Grelling 's paradox6 asks us to partition open sentences into those that satisfy themselves and those that do not. "x contains fewer than ten words" contains fewer than ten words, and so it satisfies itself, unlike "x contains fewer than five words." "x is an open sentence of Eng1ish"is an open sentence of English, so it satisfies itself. "x is an open sentence of Portuguese" is not an open sentence of Portuguese, so it does not satisfy itself. Also, "x is a horse" is not a horse, and thus it does not satisfy itself. Now consider "x does not satisfy itself." It would appear that it satisfies itself if and only if it does not. To generalize the Grelling paradox, note that an expression of English satisfies an open sentence just in case the sentence obtained by substituting the quotation name of the expression for the variable in the open sentence is true. Thus "x contains fewer than ten words is true" 5. Explicit variables are part of the dialect of English employed in math and science. Everyday speech employs pronouns for the much the same purpose. 6. Grelling, Kurt, and Leonard Nelson. "Bemerkungen zu den Paradoxien von Russell und Burali-Forti." Abhandlungen der Fries 'schen Schule neue Folge 2 (1908): 301-334.

Self-reference Theorem, p. 4 satisfies itself because '"x has fewer than ten words' has fewer than ten words" is true. If an expression doesn't satisfy an open sentence, then the result of substituting the quotation name of the expression for the variable in the open sentence is false. Thus "x is a horse" doesn't satisfy itself, and so "'x is a horse' is a horse" is false. An open sentence S does not satisfy itself if and only if the sentence obtained by substituting the quotation name of S for its variable is false. Thus Grelling's paradox consists in asking whether a false sentence is obtained from "A false sentence is obtained from the open sentence x when its quotation name is substituted for its variable" when its quotation name is substituted for its variable. This gives us a version of Eubulides' paradox in which the paradoxical sentence is identified entirely by its syntactic features. The sentence "This sentence is false" is a sentence that asserts its own falsity, but it does so by making use of the demonstrative "this," and demonstratives aren't available in the formal language of arithmetic. "A false sentence is obtained from 'A false sentence is obtained from the open sentence x when its quotation name is substituted for its variable' when its quotation name is substituted for its variable" likewise asserts its own falsity, and it does so without relying on demonstratives. Right at the moment, our focus isn't on the liar paradox. We'll come back to talk about the paradox later on, although what we'll have to say won't be even remotely satisfying. Right now, however, our interest in self-reference, and we're in luck, for the same construction works generally. Specifically, given a property P, the sentence "A sentence with property P is obtained from the open sentence 'A sentence with property P is obtained from the open sentence x when its quotation name is substituted for its variable' when its quotation name is substituted for its variable" is true if and only if it has property P.

Self-reference Theorem, p. 5 Transferring this construction from English to the formal language, we use Godel numbers in place of quotation names. Specifically, we define a function Z taking a number to the Godel number for the numeral for that number, thus: Z(0) = Q' = 4 Z(n+l) = r[n=l] 1 = Pair(4,Z(n)) The usual technique for converting recursive definitions to explicit definitions shows that Z is A. The partial function that takes the code number of a formula and the code number of a term to the code of the formula obtained by substituting the term for free occurrences of the variable "x"in the formula is A.7 We explicitly wrote out the formula for substituting a term into a term, and the formula for substituting a term into a term is completely analogous. I won't write it out, but I could if I wanted to. We just noted that the formula Z taking a number n to [n] is A. Composing the two, we see that the function g given by: g(n) = the code of the sentence obtained from the formula coded by n by substituting [n] for free occurrenes of "x," if n is the code of a formula whose only free variable is "x"; = 0, otherwise; is A, so there is a formula y(x,y) that functionally represents it. Continuing with our formalization of the generalized version of Grelling paradox, with "$(x)" taking the place of "property P," let e(x) be the formula 7. "x" isn't really a variable of the formal language; the official variables are "x,," "x,," "x,," and so on, but I'll pretend "x" is a variable, because too many subscripts are annoying.

Self-reference Theorem, p. 6 (3y)(y is a sentence A y(x,y) A $(y)). Let k be the Godel number of k, and let 4 be the sentence (3Y)(Y is a sentence A (y([ki,y) A $(Y)). Then r@ = g(k), and so Also, Q ~(~Y)(Y([~I,Y) - Y = [ r@l). Q 1 [r@] is a sentence. Consequently, Q t((3~)([ r@l is a sentence A ~([kl,~) A $(Y)) - $Ur@l), that is, Q t (4 - $([ r@).m Generalized Self-Referential Lemma. For any formula $(x,z,,z2,...,q), there is a formula 4(z,,z,,..., 4 such that: Q t(vzl)(vz2)...(v4(4(~1,~2,---, 4 - $( '@,z1,z2,...,43). Proof: In the proof of the Self-Referential Lemma, the extra variables quietly go along for the ride. H