Non-literal Language Use and Coordination in Dialogue

Similar documents
Metonymy Research in Cognitive Linguistics. LUO Rui-feng

Meaning Machines CS 672 Deictic Representations (3) Matthew Stone THE VILLAGE

Etna Builder - Interactively Building Advanced Graphical Tree Representations of Music

AN INSIGHT INTO CONTEMPORARY THEORY OF METAPHOR

istarml: Principles and Implications

Mixing Metaphors. Mark G. Lee and John A. Barnden

Revitalising Old Thoughts: Class diagrams in light of the early Wittgenstein

Cover Page. The handle holds various files of this Leiden University dissertation.

Transition Networks. Chapter 5

SYNTAX AND MEANING Luis Radford Université Laurentienne, Ontario, Canada

Two-Dimensional Semantics the Basics

Introduction. 1 See e.g. Lakoff & Turner (1989); Gibbs (1994); Steen (1994); Freeman (1996);

Loughborough University Institutional Repository. This item was submitted to Loughborough University's Institutional Repository by the/an author.

Nissim Francez: Proof-theoretic Semantics College Publications, London, 2015, xx+415 pages

Comparison, Categorization, and Metaphor Comprehension

Lecture 7: Incongruent Counterparts

A Cognitive Account of the Lexical Polysemy of Chinese Kai Flora Yu-Fang Wang Graduate Institute of English, National Taiwan Normal University

Barbara Tversky. using space to represent space and meaning

The Object Oriented Paradigm

Understanding the Cognitive Mechanisms Responsible for Interpretation of Idioms in Hindi-Urdu

INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON ENGINEERING DESIGN ICED 05 MELBOURNE, AUGUST 15-18, 2005 GENERAL DESIGN THEORY AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY

The Study of Motion Event Model and Cognitive Mechanism of English Fictive Motion Expressions of Access Paths

STYLE-BRANDING, AESTHETIC DESIGN DNA

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Metonymy and Metaphor in Cross-media Semantic Interplay

Tamar Sovran Scientific work 1. The study of meaning My work focuses on the study of meaning and meaning relations. I am interested in the duality of

19 th INTERNATIONAL CONGRESS ON ACOUSTICS MADRID, 2-7 SEPTEMBER 2007

INTUITION IN SCIENCE AND MATHEMATICS

Reviewed by Charles Forceville. University of Amsterdam, Dept. of Media and Culture

On Recanati s Mental Files

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Reasoning About Mixed Metaphors Within an Implemented Artificial Intelligence System

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995.

A New "Duration-Adapted TR" Waveform Capture Method Eliminates Severe Limitations

into a Cognitive Architecture

Cognitive poetics as a literary theory for analyzing Khayyam's poetry

THE ECOLOGICAL MEANING OF EMBODIMENT

Sets, Symbols and Pictures: A Reflection on Euler Diagrams in Leonhard Euler s Tercentenary (2007)

Terminology. - Semantics: Relation between signs and the things to which they refer; their denotata, or meaning

Automatic Polyphonic Music Composition Using the EMILE and ABL Grammar Inductors *

Using Rules to support Case-Based Reasoning for harmonizing melodies

SEEING IS BELIEVING: THE CHALLENGE OF PRODUCT SEMANTICS IN THE CURRICULUM

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

ATSC Proposed Standard: A/341 Amendment SL-HDR1

The Cognitive Nature of Metonymy and Its Implications for English Vocabulary Teaching

Generating Polysemy: Metaphor and Metonymy

Metaphors: Concept-Family in Context

Re-appraising the role of alternations in construction grammar: the case of the conative construction

Lecture (04) CHALLENGING THE LITERAL

How to edit syntax trees on the surface

The experiential basis of meaning

METAPHOR Lecture Material Master Program in Literature Department of Linguistics, Faculty of Humanities University of Indonesia

Introduction: Metonymy across languages *

Bennett on Parts Twice Over

On the Subjectivity of Translator During Translation Process From the Viewpoint of Metaphor

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

The Observer Story: Heinz von Foerster s Heritage. Siegfried J. Schmidt 1. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2011

Artificial Intelligence and Sign Theory

Space is Body Centred. Interview with Sonia Cillari Annet Dekker

22/9/2013. Acknowledgement. Outline of the Lecture. What is an Agent? EH2750 Computer Applications in Power Systems, Advanced Course. output.

The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Proposed Standard Revision of ATSC Digital Television Standard Part 5 AC-3 Audio System Characteristics (A/53, Part 5:2007)

John R. Edlund THE FIVE KEY TERMS OF KENNETH BURKE S DRAMATISM: IMPORTANT CONCEPTS FROM A GRAMMAR OF MOTIVES*

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

Introduction It is now widely recognised that metonymy plays a crucial role in language, and may even be more fundamental to human speech and cognitio

Usage of any items from the University of Cumbria s institutional repository Insight must conform to the following fair usage guidelines.

Permutations of the Octagon: An Aesthetic-Mathematical Dialectic

Social Semiotic Techniques of Sense Making using Activity Theory

Is composition a mode of performing? Questioning musical meaning

Browsing News and Talk Video on a Consumer Electronics Platform Using Face Detection

How Semantics is Embodied through Visual Representation: Image Schemas in the Art of Chinese Calligraphy *

BOOK REVIEW. William W. Davis

Mass Communication Theory

Wilson, Tony: Understanding Media Users: From Theory to Practice. Wiley-Blackwell (2009). ISBN , pp. 219

Cognitive analysis applied to the literary genre: the concepts of body and nature in the Shakespearean tragedy of King Lear

Logic and Abduction. Cognitive Externalizations in Demonstrative Environments. Lorenzo Magnani

Thomas Kuhn s Concept of Incommensurability and the Stegmüller/Sneed Program as a Formal Approach to that Concept

Metagraf2: Creativity, Beauty towards the Gestalt...

Music Performance Panel: NICI / MMM Position Statement

Gestalt, Perception and Literature

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Journal of Nonlocality Round Table Series Colloquium #4

Exploiting Cross-Document Relations for Multi-document Evolving Summarization

The Role of Metaphor in Interaction Design

ITU-T Y Functional framework and capabilities of the Internet of things

Academic Writing. Formal Requirements. for. Term Papers

The poetry of space Creating quality space Poetic buildings are all based on a set of basic principles and design tools. Foremost among these are:

EddyCation - the All-Digital Eddy Current Tool for Education and Innovation

Thinking of or Thinking Through Diagrams? The Case of Conceptual Graphs.

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

Spatial Formations. Installation Art between Image and Stage.

[a] whether or not such cultural concepts exist in addition to, or in. contradistinction to, the grammatico-semantic and grammatico-pragmatic

Experiments on musical instrument separation using multiplecause

Reflections on Kant s concept (and intuition) of space

1. PSEUDO-IMPERATIVES IN ENGLISH Characterization.

Adisa Imamović University of Tuzla

Lecture (0) Introduction

Transcription:

Non-literal Language Use and Coordination in Dialogue Josef Meyer-Fujara and Hannes Rieser Fachhochschule Stralsund, Zur Schwedenschanze 15, 18435 Stralsund e-mail: josef.meyer-fujara@fh-stralsund.de Universität Bielefeld, Fakultät LiLi, Postfach 10 01 31, 33501 Bielefeld e-mail: rieser@lili.uni-bielefeld.de Abstract. Metonymies are known as ways of conceptualizing entities and situations of various sorts. For example, users of PCs usually call the icon depicting a waste paper basket 'basket'. They thus use the name of the depicted object for referring to the depicting object. We use a model airplane ("Baufix" airplane) as the paradigm case for investigating the semiotics of depictional metonymies and the role they are put to in construction dialogue. The airplane's structure is described in a GPSG format and given a model-theoretic semantics. We also describe how aggregates of the toy model are given depictional interpretations in the course of the construction dialogue. The coordinating role of metonymic language use is illustrated. It is also shown how cognition can be integrated into the model developed. 1 Motivation In everyday talk as well as in scientific discussion people frequently use nonliteral language (tropes). Tropes are taken as a manifestation of productive or creative language use. This is one of the reasons why the cognitive sciences, including AI, are interested in theories of non-literal language (cf. (Indurkhya 1992), (Way, 1991)), especially in theories of metaphor and metonymy. Before we describe the field we are interested in, i.e. metonymies based on depiction, we provide some examples of metonymies in general (the metonymic expression is underlined): (a) I m parking out back. (b) The DRT-box is empty. (c) The airplane is built. Metonymies are based on certain relations which they exploit. E.g., (a) uses a relation between the driver and the vehicle to refer to the vehicle with the first person pronoun I, in (b) the object called box is really a rectangle, hence one uses a relation between boxes surfaces and rectangles to refer to a particular DRTrepresentation, and (c) is said of a toy-airplane, where a construction in ways yet to be explained licenses the use of the word airplane. Many types of metonymies exist and there does not seem to be one single theory which can capture them all (cf. (Nunberg, 1995)). Example (c) is outstanding, 256

since it exploits a relation between the toy in question and the class of airplanes. The example meets another current interest of the cognitive sciences, namely the interest in depiction (cf. (Sloman, 1971), (Glasgow et al., 1995), (Eschenbach & Kulik, 1997) and (Habel, 1998)). In order to refer to drawings, maps, pictures, models etc., we may use the names of the objects they are about. Certain types of metonymies, we observe, are based on a relation of depiction, of being about another object. These metonymies have an obvious application interest: Computer icons, e.g., are called folders, waste-paper baskets etc. or with CASE tools plants, objects and modules. In our article we explain how the depiction relation for metonymies can be reconstructed and properly interpreted. Our investigation is based on a corpus of transcripts, speech recordings, video-films and eye-tracker data gathered in the context of the following experimental setting: An instructor has a toy airplane (called "Baufix" airplane) shown in fig. 1 in front of him. He instructs a constructor to build an airplane of the same type using another set of parts lying in front of him. Both agents are separated by a screen. We use the example of the toy-airplane as a paradigm case for investigating depictional metonymies and their role in construction dialogue. 2 Semiotics of Depicting Aggregates Depicting aggregates such as the toy airplane refer to real-world objects, and this reference depends on their compositional structure. Such aggregates must hence be seen as structured semiotic objects. Consequently, we have to specify their syntax, semantics and pragmatics. 2.1 Syntax Our leading hypotheses for the syntax of depicting aggregates are: 1) Aggregates ultimately consist of elementary parts ( atoms ). 2) Aggregates are composed of atoms and of aggregates of lower complexity. 3) Aggregates are subject to well-formedness conditions concerning the connections of atoms and partial aggregates to each other. Of the many syntax formats possible, we chose GPSG for flexibility. We will illustrate the syntax describing the structure of the tail of the "Baufix" airplane: The atoms available for its construction are three-holes bars 3ll i, five-holes bars 5ll i, a red holes cube lwr 1, a red round bolt ssr 1, and hexagonal bolts skr i. The aggregate resulting from putting skr 1 through an end hole of 3ll 1 will be denoted by [ X1 f 1, 3ll 1, skr 1 ]. Here, f 1 is a syncategorematic terminal symbol describing the special arrangement. The corresponding general grammar rule reads R 1 : X 1 f 1, 3LL, SKR, where 3LL denotes the category of three-holes bars, SKR indicates the category of hexagonal bolts and X 1 names an aggregate of instantiations of these. Further 257

rules are R 2 : X 2 f 2, X 1, LWR; R 3 :X 3 f 3, 5LL, SSR; R 4 : S f 4, X 2, X 3. R 2 describes bolting a red holes cube onto an X 1 -structure; R 3 describes forming an aggregate of a five-holes bar and a round bolt put through its middle hole. Bolting the round bolt of X 3 into the suitable hole of the cube in X 2 is described by R 4. This yields category S corresponding to the tail of the toy airplane. Further rules such as 5LL 5ll 1 describe instantiation of categories. Fig. 1: "Baufix" airplane 2.2 Semantics Here, our leading hypotheses are: 1) Semantics follows syntax (compositionality). 2) "Baufix" atoms denote themselves (autosemantics). 3) "Baufix" aggregates denote themselves or (parts of) real airplanes. Hypotheses 2 and 3 reflect that dialogue agents do not conceive of isolated "Baufix" atoms as depicting entities. Only more complex aggregates such as given by S in 2.1 are seen as depicting. Following these hypotheses, the domain of our models is sorted into "Baufix" atoms, "Baufix" aggregates and (parts of) real airplanes. The interpretation function is a pair of two functions, mapping every object x to <V Bf, V ap >(x), where V Bf is the identity function and where the co-domain of V ap is the set of (parts of) real airplanes. An object x is in the domain of V ap if and only if it depicts (some part of) a real airplane. We denote the meaning of an object x relative to a model M = (U, <V Bf, V ap >) by [ x ] M. The meaning of, e.g. f 1 is [ f 1 ] M = {<x,y> x is put into an end hole of y}. For "Baufix" atoms x, the meaning is the atom x itself, for elementary category symbols such as 5LL, it is the set of instances of the category. Furthermore, [ [ X1 f 1, 3LL, SKR] ] M = [ X 1 ] M is the set of all "Baufix" aggregates consisting of a hexagonal bolt put into the end hole of a three-holes bar. Finally, the meaning of S is a pair <V, W>, where W consists of all tails of real airplanes. Intuitively, V contains all pairs <x,y> of the following sort: The first element x is an aggregate consisting of a three-holes bar and a red holes cube 258

fixed to the bar by a hexagonal bolt put through the bar s end hole. The second element y is made up of a five-holes bar and a red round bolt put into its central hole. The relation f 4 captures the specific linkage between x and y. Our approach accounts for the facts that only certain aggregates are named metonymically and that metonymic and nonmetonymic expressions can alternate. 2.3 How to Generalize the Approach There are lots of toy models, all depicting planes. Even though models exhibit their relation to airplanes in different ways, they ultimately may be bound to the same extension. In this sense, the Baufix airplane and the so-called Japanese airplane in fig. 2 depict the same class of airplanes in contrast to the Lego plane in the same figure depicting biplanes. Why is it that models depict in the same way? The intuition accounting for that is that some of their parts fulfil a comparable role as regards depiction. This of course has to be captured by our syntactic description. Fig. 2: Japanese plane and "Lego plane We can achieve this target in at least two ways: The first is to let the different models be generated by different grammars, more generally, to set up a set of admissible grammars and to constrain these grammars by a suitable filter. The second is to provide one single parameterized grammar. Details are given in (Rieser & Meyer-Fujara, 1999). Both techniques will provide the same extension for the Baufix airplane and the Japanese one and weed out the Lego plane. 2.4 Pragmatics: Introduction of Metonymies in Construction Dialogue Based on the generalized approach to depictive metonymy in 2.3, we can map speakers onto their grammars. Hence, in order to explain why in a normal situation speakers can fairly homogeneously and successfully use "airplane" for different models, we must postulate that speakers use different grammars employing extensionally equivalent relations of metonymy. 259

However, in our experimental setting only the instructor has a stable grammar for the object on his side throughout the construction dialogue, whereas the constructor, screened off from him, will develop such a grammar in (ideally monotonic) successive steps by the instructor s help. Finally, as shown in fig. 3, he will have acquired a grammar depicting airplanes. At the end of the construction dialogue, we arrive at a situation where there exist two grammars, G I and G C,m, generating the Baufix airplanes at the instructor s and the constructor s side, respectively. All along the construction dialogue, the instructor s grammar has been a necessary condition for the constructor s building of his version of the airplane. Ideally, the two Baufix airplanes will cover one common extension, i.e., depict in the same way. beginning of dialogue time end of dialogue constructor G C,0 G C,1 G C,2 G C,3 G C,m objects in the world extension: tail extension: airplane extension: tail + fuselage extension: tail + fuselage + wings instructor G I = G I = G I = G I = = G I Description: G C,j : different stages of constructor s grammar, G I : invariant instructor s grammar, : interpretation Fig. 3: Constructor acquiring a grammar for depicting objects 3 Outlook In our aproach we use extensional models for the definition of the meaning of depicting aggregates. Objects in the model domain are things in the world, namely real airplanes and their parts. We nevertheless aim at a cognitive interpretation of our theories. We see two ways of integrating cognitive aspects: As for the first way, agents consider depicting objects as being segmentable into parts even if the objects are not put together from individual elements as "Baufix" toy planes are. There are natural segmentations corresponding to principles of object recognition as described, e.g., by Marr and Nishihara (1978). A cognitively motivated syntax may start out from such segmentations, e.g., from 260

segmentations into geons in the sense of Biederman (1987). As for the second way, one may use concepts instead of things as objects of the model. Since concepts are not directly accessible, agglomerations of geometric figures may be used in their place (cf. arguments given in (Biederman, 1987)). Thus a relation is established between syntactic structure and concepts. A further field of research is the examination of parameters of metonymy use in order to get at pragmatic constraints, dealing with questions such as: When are metonymic expressions introduced in dialogue? What is the profit gained from their use? One of the main profits we found out is the possibility of intrinsic orientation liberating from negotiating the meaning of 'up', 'in front', 'left', etc.. Further research in representation metonymy seems worth-while because of its widespread use in WIMP user interfaces. Intelligent agents supporting users of CASE or CAD/CIM systems will inevitably have to cope with depiction as well as with the step-wise construction of meaning in dialogue. References Biederman, I. (1987). Recognition-by-Components: A Theory of Human Image Understanding. Psychological Review, 94(2),115-147. Eschenbach, C. & Kulik, L. (1997). An axiomatic approach to the spatial relations underlying left right and in front of behind. In: G. Brewka, C. Habel & B. Nebel (eds.), KI-97 Glasgow, J, Narayanan, H. & Chandrasekaran, B. (eds.) (1995). Diagrammatic Reasoning: Cognitive and Computational Perspectives. Cambridge, Ma: MIT Press. Habel, Ch. (1998). Piktorielle Repräsentationen als unterbestimmte räumliche Modelle. Kognitionswissenschaft 7, 58-67 Indurkhya, B. (1992). Metaphor and cognition: an interactionist approach. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Johnson-Laird, Ph.N. & Miller, G.A. (1979). Language and Perception. Cambridge: Univ. Press Jung, B. (1997). Wissensverarbeitung für Montageaufgaben in virtuellen und realen Umgebungen. St. Augustin: infix. Marr, D. & Nishihara, H.K. (1978). Representation and Recognition of Three-Dimensional Shapes. Proc. Royal Society of London, Series B, 200, 269-294. Meyer-Fujara, J. & Rieser, H. (1997). Zur Semantik von Repräsentationsrelationen. Fallstudie eins zum SFB-"Flugzeug". Technical Report 97/7. SFB 360 "Situierte Künstliche Kommunikatoren". Bielefeld: Bielefeld Univ. Nunberg, G. (1995). Transfers of meaning. Journal of Semantics 12, 109-133. Rieser, H. & Meyer-Fujara, J. (1999). Zur Semantik von Repräsentationsrelationen. Fallstudie zwei zum SFB- Flugzeug. Technical Report 99/1. SFB 360 "Situierte Künstliche Kommunikatoren". Bielefeld: Bielefeld Univ. Sloman, A. (1971). Interactions Between Philosophy and Artificial Intelligence: The Role of Intuition and Non-Logical Reasoning in Intelligence. Artificial Intelligence 2, 209-225. Wachsmuth, I. & Jung, B. (1996). Dynamic Conceptualization in a Mechanical-Object Assembly Environment. Artificial Intelligence Review 10, (3-4), 345-368. Way, C.E. (1991). Knowledge representation and metaphor. Oxford: Intellect Books. 261