Full and Sketched Micro-Foundations

Similar documents
MAIN THEORETICAL PERSPECTIVES IN CONTEMPORARY SOCIOLOGY

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

Modern Sociological Theory 7,5 ECTS credits

Modern Sociological Theory 7,5 ECTS credits

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Macrosociology-Microsociology

Historical Pathways. The problem of history and historical knowledge

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

On Recanati s Mental Files

In Search of Mechanisms, by Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden, 2013, The University of Chicago Press.

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Discourse analysis is an umbrella term for a range of methodological approaches that

Situated actions. Plans are represetitntiom of nction. Plans are representations of action

Sidestepping the holes of holism

BDD-A Universitatea din București Provided by Diacronia.ro for IP ( :46:58 UTC)

Université Libre de Bruxelles

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

The Debate on Research in the Arts

French theories in IS research : An exploratory study on ICIS, AMCIS and MISQ

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

The book Opportunities and Deprivation in the Urban South by Eduardo Cesar

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

Master of Arts in Psychology Program The Faculty of Social and Behavioral Sciences offers the Master of Arts degree in Psychology.

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

Paradigm paradoxes and the processes of educational research: Using the theory of logical types to aid clarity.

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions

i n t r o d u c t i o n

Arnold I. Davidson, Frédéric Gros (eds.), Foucault, Wittgenstein: de possibles rencontres (Éditions Kimé, 2011), ISBN:

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Methods, Topics, and Trends in Recent Business History Scholarship

REFERENCES. 2004), that much of the recent literature in institutional theory adopts a realist position, pos-

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

Part IV Social Science and Network Theory

Anyon, Jean (2009). Theory and Educational Research: Toward Critical Social Explanation. New York and London: Routledge.

Thai Architecture in Anthropological Perspective

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

Georg Simmel and Formal Sociology

Image and Imagination

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Attila Bruni Sarah Pink, Doing Sensory Ethnography. London, Thousand Oaks, New Delhi, Singapore: Sage, 2009, 184 pp. (doi: 10.

Introduction: Mills today

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

FORUM: QUALITATIVE SOCIAL RESEARCH SOZIALFORSCHUNG

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Critical Discourse Analysis. 10 th Semester April 2014 Prepared by: Dr. Alfadil Altahir 1

Capstone Design Project Sample

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

GABRIEL TARDE AND THE END OF SOCIAL By Bruno Latour

Mixing Metaphors. Mark G. Lee and John A. Barnden

Methodology in a Pluralist Environment. Sheila C Dow. Published in Journal of Economic Methodology, 8(1): 33-40, Abstract

Natural Genetic Engineering and Natural Genome Editing, Salzburg, July

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

PHIL/HPS Philosophy of Science Fall 2014

Triune Continuum Paradigm and Problems of UML Semantics

Philosophical foundations for a zigzag theory structure


Is Situational Analysis Merely Rational Choice Theory?

Narrative Case Study Research

In basic science the percentage of authoritative references decreases as bibliographies become shorter

Tippkeskuse metodoloogiline seminar 1: KULTUUR. 29.september 2009

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique of Pure Reason for Describing Epistemological Trends in IS

Twentieth Excursus: Reference Magnets and the Grounds of Intentionality

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Qualitative Design and Measurement Objectives 1. Describe five approaches to questions posed in qualitative research 2. Describe the relationship betw

Culture in Social Theory

Policies and Procedures

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

ABOUT ASCE JOURNALS ASCE LIBRARY

Holism, Concept Individuation, and Conceptual Change

Stenberg, Shari J. Composition Studies Through a Feminist Lens. Anderson: Parlor Press, Print. 120 pages.

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Four Characteristic Research Paradigms

Sociology. Kuipers, Giselinde (2014). In Attardo, Salvatore (ed.), Encyclopedia of Humor Studies,

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

istarml: Principles and Implications

Lecture 24 Sociology 621 December 12, 2005 MYSTIFICATION

Logic and Artificial Intelligence Lecture 0

0 6 /2014. Listening to the material life in discursive practices. Cristina Reis

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History

The Application of Stylistics in British and American Literature Teaching. XU Li-mei, QU Lin-lin. Changchun University, Changchun, China

The social and cultural significance of Paleolithic art

Special Issue Introduction: Coming to Terms in the Muddy Waters of Qualitative Inquiry in Communication Studies

Goals and Rationales

Autoethnography. IIQM Webinar Series Dr. Sarah Wall July 24, 2014

Research Projects on Rudolf Steiner'sWorldview

MYKOLAS ROMERIS UNIVERSITY FACULTY OF SOCIAL TECHNOLOGIES INSTITUTE OF PSYCHOLOGY

Society for the Study of Symbolic Interaction SSSI/ASA 2002 Conference, Chicago

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Transcription:

Symposium / On Analytical Sociology: Critique, Advocacy, and Prospects Full and Sketched Micro-Foundations The Odd Resurgence of a Dubious Distinction by Gianluca Manzo doi: 10.2383/36900 Little s Analytical Sociology and the Rest of Sociology is a thoughtful reflection upon analytical sociology (hereafter AS) and its limitations. Differently from previous critics [Opp 2007; Abbott 2007; Gorski 2009, 176-181; Gross 2009], Little more overtly expresses a positive appreciation of AS, which he sees as an important contribution to our thinking about social research and an illuminating approach to social explanation. Similarly to those critics, however, Little considers that AS s scope is diminished by the following weaknesses: 1) AS is committed to a reductionist version of methodological individualism; 2) AS s theory of action is simply a variant of rational-choice theory; 3) AS underestimates the historical roots of social phenomena. Overall, Little s paper devotes much more energy to discussing the first of these limitations. It argues that the reductionist strategy on which AS is built implies an excessively strong micro-foundation requirement. According to Little, this ultimately induces AS to regard large sectors of sociology which do not fulfill this requirement as less than fully scientific, even though, Little argues, they are rigorous and explanatory. In this short rejoinder to Little, I defend three arguments: 1) Little caricatures the ambitions of AS; 2) Little s conception of social ontology and explanation is in fact virtually the same as that of AS; 3) Little s distinction between a strong and a Sociologica, 1/2012 - Copyright 2012 by Società editrice il Mulino, Bologna. 1

Manzo, Full and Sketched Micro-Foundations weak form of micro-foundation is not a robust basis on which to attack AS because this distinction is internally contradictory. 1 Let me start with the supposedly imperialistic attitude of AS. Little builds on Demeulenaere s [2011, 1] statement according to which AS should [ ] be seen [ ] as an effort to clarify ( analytically ) theoretical and epistemological principles which underlie any satisfactory way of doing sociology (and, in fact, any social science). In my opinion, this is a bad starting point. Demeulenaere s statement which implies that AS is more a branch of the philosophy of social sciences than an approach of relevance for theoretically-minded empirically-oriented social scientists should not be regarded as an accurate description of how analytical sociologists conceive themselves. Whilst it is undeniable that AS contains a normative dimension, careful inspection of AS programmatic writings suggests that AS adopts a far less peremptory posture. Let us first recall that Hesdtröm and Swedberg [1998, 25] overtly stressed that the essence of the mechanisms approach is to be found in a special style of theorizing. Special does not mean general, nor that the approach is the only legitimate sociological perspective. On the contrary, the normative perimeter of the approach is clearly defined from the outset. AS s original intent was, on the one hand, to make sociological theory conceptually more precise and with clearer empirical explananda, and, on the other hand, to complement statistically-oriented research with more systematic and creative theoretical thinking [Hesdtröm and Swedberg 1998, 1, 15-21; Hedström 2005, 3-4, 12-13]. Recent statements like the overarching purpose of the book is to move sociology in a more analytical direction or our hope is that the analytical-sociological framework will emerge as the central template for a renewed sociology for the Twenty-first century [Hedström and Bearman 2009, 4, 21] should thus be understood within the current state of our discipline, in which much published work still falls within what Abell and Reyniers [2000, 748] called fugitive frameworks, i.e. analyses that build on (a mix of) opaque linguistic expressions, loose concepts, a distorted use of otherwise rigorous methods, and mere descriptivism note that serious social scientists outside AS have also tried to establish boundaries of this kind [Goldthorpe 2000, 1-11]. What about, more specifically, the rest of sociology considered by Little? Despite the general expression adopted, his research examples come from two research traditions, namely (comparative) historical sociology and qualitative-oriented micro-sociology. Several elements suggest that AS does not disregard these perspecx 1 Here I do not address Little s reading of AS s action theory because I have elsewhere discussed this point at length in response to Gross s identical interpretation [Manzo 2010]. 2

Sociologica, 1/2012 tives a priori. First, Hedström and Swedberg [1998, 23] overtly acknowledged that Goffman s analyses are full of situational mechanisms, i.e. linkages between actors behaviour and the specific social situation to which they are exposed. Second, AS has recently engaged in explicit dialogue with ethnography with a view to their mutual enrichment [Vaughan 2009]. Third, ethnographic observation was a methodological pillar for some of the scholars who contributed to launching AS [Gambetta 1993; Gambetta 2009; Gambetta and Hamill 2005]. Finally, explicit conceptual bridges between AS and historical sociology are under construction, with the analysis of social networks providing possible theoretical and methodological leverage [Barkey 2009]. Thus, contrary to what Little claims, AS has clearly identified intellectual adversaries ; it does not consider itself the whole of sociology or a uniquely best research strategy for sociology ; it discusses with a large spectrum of sociological approaches; and it fully acknowledges the importance of combining abstraction with thick descriptions of historically, socially situated interacting actors. Let me now move to Little s point that AS is based on a reductionist strategy according to which a good explanation [ ] should not make reference to meso or macro level factors. To see that this objection is simply factually wrong, consider the two following excerpts: Verbally, we can say that phenomenon M is a function of actions m, which are dependent on situation S of the actor, which situation is itself affected by macro-social actions M [Boudon 1986, 30]. Thus structure at one time (macro-level) generates the conditions which together with existing interests shape the actions of actors (micro-level) that jointly produce outcomes which modify the structure of a later time (macro-level) which generates conditions that again (through constraints and incentives) shape actions (microlevel) that jointly produce outcomes (macro-level) and so on [Coleman 1993, 63]. Boudon s and Coleman s statements provide us with a simple description of the static and the dynamic version of the so-called structural individualism originally proposed within Dutch sociology in an overly anti-reductionist spirit [Wippler 1978, 143]. While they did not use the term, Hedström and Swedberg [1998 11-13] explicitly follow a weak version of methodological individualism which takes certain macro-level states as given and incorporates them into the explanation. The reference to the concept of structural individualism comes with Hedström [2005, 5, 70-74] and with Hedström and Bearman [2009, 4, 8, 10-11]. These programmatic AS works conceptualize macro-states as supervening on micro-level properties and assume that they exert a relatively autonomous causal power. The qualification relatively refers to the fact that at least one individual component must be at work for the macro-level state to produce some changes in the social world. To highlight 3

Manzo, Full and Sketched Micro-Foundations the circular relation between structure and action at issue here, I have elsewhere proposed the notion of complex methodological individualism [Manzo 2007]. Let us now consider the following quotation from Little s Level of the Social [2006, 353]: All of these social factors are constituted by the set of agents who populate them at a given time. Agents act within the context of these structures; and their actions both reproduce and modify the structure. At any given time, agents are acting in ways that affect future states of the system while being prompted or constrained by existing structures and mentalities in ways that influence their future actions. What is the real difference between this position, which Little labels methodological localism, and the structural individualism contained in Boudon s and Coleman s above statements, and today advocated by AS? The similarity is also striking with respect to the epistemological implication that Little draws from his ontological position [ibidem, 360]: There are no causal mechanisms that do not supervene upon the structured choices and behavior of individuals. The mechanisms through which social causation is mediated turn on the structured circumstances of choice of intentional agents, and nothing else. In footnote 24, associated with this passage, Little explicitly acknowledges that Hedström and Swedberg [1998, 24] endorse his position that there exist no such things as macro-level mechanisms [Little 1998, 161] also explicitly writes: There is no such thing as pure social causation from macro-state to macro-state. So why does Little now attack AS for positing that the mechanisms are supposed to occur solely at the level of the actors not at meso or macro levels? Whilst it may seem that Little is criticizing himself, Analytical Sociology and the Rest of Sociology contains a nuance that helps to explain this apparent contradiction. Little maintains that the microfoundation requirement can be interpreted either as a full specification of the microfoundations in every case or as a sketch of the way that a given social-level process might readily be embodied. He explicitly admits that he is inclined to interpret the requirement in the second way while AS tends to give priority to the first. Here, therefore, Little seems to rehabilitate a distinction that sometimes appeared in his early writings [Little 1991, 196, 200; Little 1998, 6, 8] but that is absent from his more recent work [Little 2006; Little 2009; Little 2010; Little 2011] note, however, that even in Little [1998] the distinction is absent from chapter 10, which provides the very systematic treatment of causal explanations. The implication that he draws from this distinction seems stronger than before, however. Little concludes, in fact, that we can make careful statements about 4

Sociologica, 1/2012 macro-macro and macro-meso causal relations without proceeding according to the logic of Coleman s boat up and down the struts. I regard Little s flexible interpretation of the microfoundation requirement as highly problematic. First of all, what distinguishes a full individual-level narrative from a sketched one? Little does not provide any analytical criterion with which to separate the two kinds of micro-level accounts. Second, when should we stop at a sketch and when should we not? On this point, Little s advice is: We need to be confident there are microfoundations, and the meso properties need to be causally robust. But if this is satisfied, we do not need to extend the explanation down to the actors. But how could one be confident there are microfoundations if one does not detail several possible individual-level narratives and assess the empirical relevance of each of them? Once this operation has been performed, however, the sketch is no longer needed because (at least) one detailed (potential) microfoundation has been provided. The idea of microfoundation sketches is thus circular and self-defeating. Besides its conceptual vagueness and logical inconsistency, Little s distinction between strong and weak microfoundation requirements is unconvincing on empirical grounds. Little fails to provide any compelling example of a mechanism that leads from a given meso-level factor A to a given meso-level factor B without proceeding according to the logic of Coleman s boat up and down the struts, to take his own words (an objection that may be extended to Jepperson and Meyer [2011], whom Little takes as inspiring source). The opposite is true. When in the last section of the paper Little discusses five pathways through which meso-level structures have causal powers (in particular he focuses on organizations), all of them amount to a detailed description of how micro-level properties like individuals beliefs, values, desires, incentives, or identity are shaped by the specific organizational and institutional settings at hand. This negative result is perfectly in line with the strong microfoundationist Little who claims, for instance, that if we are interested in analysis of the casual properties of states and governments, we need to arrive at an analysis of the institutions and constrained patterns of individual behaviour through which the state s characteristics are affected [Little 2009, 165]. This result is also fully compatible with AS s research program, which Little oddly considers reductionist. By contrast, this result is strikingly in contradiction with the main argument that the weak microfoundationist Little now seeks to defend: that explanations of one set of factors in terms of another set of factors at the same level (what he calls lateral strategies ) are fully legitimate and deep explanations. 5

Manzo, Full and Sketched Micro-Foundations References Abbott, A. 2007 Mechanisms and Relations. Sociologica 2. doi:10.2383/24750 Abell, P., and Reyniers, D. 2000 On the Failure of Social Theory. 51: 739-750. Barkey, K. 2009 Historical Sociology. Pp. 712-734 in The Oxford Handbook of Analytical Sociology, edited by P. Bearman and P. Hedström. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Boudon, R. 1986 Theories of Social Change. Cambridge: Polity Press. Coleman, J.S. 1993 Reply to Blau, Tuomela, Diekman, and Baurmann. Analyse und Kritik 15: 62-69. Demeulenaere, P. (ed.) 2011 Analytical Sociology and Social Mechanisms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Gambetta, D. 1993 The Sicilian Mafia. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. 2009 Princeton: Princeton University Press. Gambetta, D., and Hamill, H. 2005 Streetwise. How Taxi Drivers Establish Customers Trustworthiness. New York: Russell Sage Foundation. Goldthorpe, J.H. 2000 On Sociology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Gorski, P.S. 2009 Social Mechanisms and Comparative-Historical Sociology: A Critical Realist Proposal. Pp. 147-194 in Frontiers of Sociology, edited by P. Hedström and B. Wittrock. Leiden: Brill. Gross, N. 2009 A Pragmatist Theory of Social Mechanisms. American Sociological Review 74:358-379. Hedström, P. 2005 Dissecting the Social: On the Principles of Analytical Sociology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hedström, P., and Bearman, P. 2009 What is Analytical Sociology all about? Pp. 3-24 in The Oxford Handbook of Analytical Sociology, edited by P. Bearman and P. Hedström. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hedström, P., and Swedberg, R. (eds.) 1998 Social Mechanisms: An Introductory Essay. Pp. 1-31 in Social Mechanisms. An Analytical Approach to Social Theory, edited by P. Hedström and R. Swedberg. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 6

Sociologica, 1/2012 Jepperson, R., and Meyer, J.H. 2011 Multiple Levels of Analysis and the Limitations of Methodological Individualisms. Sociological Theory 29: 54-73. Little, D. 1991 Varieties of Social Explanations. Boulder: Westview Press. 1998 Microfoundations, Methods, and Causation: Essays in the Philosophy of Social Sciences. New Brunswick and London: Transaction Publishers. 2006 Levels of the Social. Pp. 343-372 in Handbook for Philosophy of Anthropology and Sociology, edited by S. Turner and M. M. Risjord. Amsterdam: New York, Elsevier. 2009 The Heterogenous Social: New Thinking About the Foundations of the Social Sciences. Pp. 154-178 in Philosophy of the Social Sciences: Philosophical Theory and Scientific Practice, edited by C. Mantzavinos. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 2010 Methodological Individualism. In Encyclopedia of Political Theory, edited by M. Bevier. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. 2011 Causal Mechanisms in the Social Real. Pp. 273-295 in Causality in the Sciences, edited by P. M. Illari, F. Russo, and J. Williamson. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Manzo, G. 2007 Comment on Andrew Abbott/2. Sociologica 2. doi:10.2383/24752 2010 Analytical Sociology and Its Critics. European Journal of Sociology 51: 129-170. Opp, K.D. 2007 Review of: P. Hedström Dissecting the Social. European Sociological Review 23: 115-122. Vaughan, D. 2009 Analytic Etnography. Pp. 688-711 in The Oxford Handbook of Analytical Sociology, edited by P. Bearman and P. Hedström. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Wippler, R. 1978 The Structural-Individualistic Approach in Dutch Sociology. The Netherlands Journal of Sociology 14: 135-155. 7

Manzo, Full and Sketched Micro-Foundations Full and Sketched Micro-Foundations The Odd Resurgence of a Dubious Distinction Abstract: In this short rejoinder to Daniel Little s paper on Alaytical sociology, the author defends three arguments: 1) Little caricatures the ambitions of AS; 2) Little s conception of social ontology and explanation is in fact virtually the same as that of AS; 3) Little s distinction between a strong and a weak form of micro-foundation is not a robust basis on which to attack AS because this distinction is internally contradictory. Keywords: Analytical sociology, structural individualism, complex methodological individualism, micro-foundation, supervenience. Gianluca Manzo earned a Ph.D. in Social Sciences (2006) jointly from the University of Paris-Sorbonne and the University of Trento. He currently is a permanent research fellow at the Centre Nationale de la Recherche Scientifique (CNRS, France) as a member of the Groupe d Etude des Méthodes de l Analyse Sociologique de la Sorbonne (GEMASS, Paris) as well as a non-permanent lecturer at the University of Paris-Sorbonne. His research focuses on reason- and network-based explanations of social inequalities and on how testing these explanations by means of agent-based computational models. On these topics, he published a book, The spiral of inequalities (Paris, Presses de l Université Paris-Sorbonne, 2009), several articles published in European Sociological Review, European Journal of Sociology, Quality and Quantity, and Revue Française de Sociologie, as well as chapters in volumes edited by Cambridge University Press. 8