Crosslinguistic Notions of (In)definiteness *

Similar documents
February 16, 2007 Menéndez-Benito. Challenges/ Problems for Carlson 1977

(The) most in Dutch: Definiteness and Specificity. Koen Roelandt CRISSP, KU Leuven HUBrussel

MONOTONE AMAZEMENT RICK NOUWEN

Depiction Verbs and the Definiteness Effect DRAFT 1. This paper is part of a longer project on the semantics of depiction verbs and

Linking semantic and pragmatic factors in the Japanese Internally Headed Relative Clause

Comparatives, Indices, and Scope

Re-appraising the role of alternations in construction grammar: the case of the conative construction

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

On Recanati s Mental Files

Lecture 7. Scope and Anaphora. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 1

Partial and Paraconsistent Approaches to Future Contingents in Tense Logic

In the sentence above we find the article "a". It shows us that the speaker does not need a specific chair. He can have any chair.

Quantifier domain restriction

Imperatives are existential modals; Deriving the must-reading as an Implicature. Despina Oikonomou (MIT)

Introduction to English Linguistics (I) Professor Seongha Rhee

Time and again: the intriguing life of a temporal adverb

Nissim Francez: Proof-theoretic Semantics College Publications, London, 2015, xx+415 pages

Introduction. Fiora Salis University of Lisbon

On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth

Deriving the Interpretation of Rhetorical Questions

!"#$%&'()**#%*#+,*,-./#!"##)*0#1.*02#%3#3.-2'45,-2%*4%-.,*',0#/%*',*'"#

Diagnosing covert pied-piping *

Discourse as action Politeness theory

Plurals Jean Mark Gawron San Diego State University

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

LOCALITY DOMAINS IN THE SPANISH DETERMINER PHRASE

The Syntax and Semantics of Traces Danny Fox, MIT. How are traces interpreted given the copy theory of movement?

Sonority as a Primitive: Evidence from Phonological Inventories Ivy Hauser University of North Carolina

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Conceptions and Context as a Fundament for the Representation of Knowledge Artifacts

Replies to the Critics

Generating Polysemy: Metaphor and Metonymy

Introduction HIROYUKI ETO

Semantic Research Methodology

Robert Pirsig offers a critique of academic writing.

17. Semantics in L1A

Intensional Relative Clauses and the Semantics of Variable Objects

CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION. communication with others. In doing communication, people used language to say

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press,

Choose the correct word or words to complete each sentence.

1 Pair-list readings and single pair readings

THE APOSTROPHE II. Using the apostrophe to show possession (In words that do not already end in s )

CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION. language such as in a play or a film. Meanwhile the written dialogue is a dialogue

Symbolization and Truth-Functional Connectives in SL

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions

The Cognitive Nature of Metonymy and Its Implications for English Vocabulary Teaching

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Towards Culturally-Situated Agent Which Can Detect Cultural Differences

SNP Best-set Typesetter Ltd. Article No.: 583 Delivery Date: 31 October 2005 Page Extent: 4 pp

Respective Answers to Coordinated Questions

SIGNS, SYMBOLS, AND MEANING DANIEL K. STEWMT*

Neural evidence for a single lexicogrammatical processing system. Jennifer Hughes

Interactions between Semiotic Modes in Multimodal Texts. Martin Siefkes, University of Bremen

Review of Epistemic Modality

A critical pragmatic approach to irony

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Poznań, July Magdalena Zabielska

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Conversational Implicature: The Basics of the Gricean Theory 1

Works Cited at the end of the essay. Adequate development in a paragraph

Exploring nominal reference in the field: Diagnostics plus results from Bulu

Intro to Pragmatics (Fox/Menéndez-Benito) 10/12/06. Questions 1

Language Documentation and Linguistic Theory STYLE SHEET Department of Linguistics, SOAS

positive forms: use the verb without an ending: I work in a nice office. My colleagues usually help me with my presentations.

Possible Ramifications for Superiority

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1

Journal for contemporary philosophy

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

THE PARADOX OF ANALYSIS

Part A Instructions and examples

Resources for Further Study

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver

1. Introduction. Paper s Questions

Dynamic Semantics! (Part 1: Not Actually Dynamic Semantics) Brian Morris, William Rose

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

Categories and Schemata

Comparison, Categorization, and Metaphor Comprehension

Or what? Or what?: Challenging the speaker. NELS 46, Concordia. Or what questions are strategies for re-asking a big question.

Note: Please use the actual date you accessed this material in your citation.

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

JRN 2201 final exam notes 7/20/14

The Style Sheet for Gengo Kenkyu, Journal of the Linguistic Society of Japan

A New Paradigm for Constructing Children-Oriented Web-sites of Art Museums

1. PSEUDO-IMPERATIVES IN ENGLISH Characterization.

Idioms. Idiom quiz. 1. Improve after going through something A. As plain as day

Scientific Philosophy

Ambiguity/Language/Learning Ron Burnett President, Emily Carr Institute of Art + Design

The indefinite articles 1. We use the article a / an when we are talking about something for the first time or not specific things.

Polysemy in the meaning of come: Two senses with a common conceptual core

Manuel García-Carpintero & Genoveva Martí (eds.): Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2014, 368 pages

Understanding English Grammar: A Linguistic Introduction

1 Objects and Logic. 1. Abstract objects

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Phonology. Submission of papers

Lesson 18: Sending/Receiving Information - Phone (20-25 minutes)

Metonymy Research in Cognitive Linguistics. LUO Rui-feng

CONTEXT CLUES 3. EXAMPLES

Face-threatening Acts: A Dynamic Perspective

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Bibliometric analysis of the field of folksonomy research

Transcription:

Crosslinguistic Notions of (In)definiteness * ISHIKAWA, Kiyoshi Hosei University kiyoshi@fujimi.hosei.ac.jp Abstract We argue that both Russellian and Heimian definites exist in natural languages. Our account captures both the commonality and difference between the two. Further, we suggest that the Russellian/Heimian distinction extends to indefinites too. 1 Introduction One morning, Alice tells (1) to her husband, John, who doesn't read newspapers. Her use of the president is dependent on the uniqueness of president in the fixed domain she is talking about (i.e. the U.S. politics situation). Let's call it a Russellian domain (R-domain) and such a use of definite description Russellian definiteness (R-definiteness). (1) Hey John, the president resigned!! In the evening John describes a scene he saw in the afternoon with (2). Clearly, the described scene contains at least two dogs, thus the uniqueness of dogs on which his use of the dog is dependent is not w.r.t. the scene as a whole, but rather w.r.t. a domain dynamically constructed by his first sentence. Let's call such a domain a Heimian domain (H-domain) and such a use of definite description Heimian definiteness (H-definiteness). (2) I found a dog on the lawn. The dog was biting another dog An R-domain r is something out there, not necessarily within our comprehension in its totality. An H-domain h is the part of such an r which is known, or already familiar, to the conversation participants, which grows as the conversation proceeds. Then, assuming the lattice-theoretic ontology of [1], we say the denotation of a definite description is max(d, p), where max is a function that maps an R- or H-domain d and a property p to the maximal individual which has p in d; the uniqueness, then, follows from the singular morphology of the NP. The Russellian/Heimian distinction (hereafter, the R/H distinction) is a result of the choice of the domain (cf. [2]). Regarding such domains as 85

resource situations in the situation semantic sense, we argue for the significance of the R/H distinction for English and other languages. 2 Inclusiveness H-definiteness is named after [3], which reduces definiteness to familiarity. We formulate familiarity in terms of domains (situations), while [3] formulates it in terms of individuals (file cards). Here, [4]'s inclusiveness analysis is formulated as the maximality function max. For example, in (3), the boys refers to the three boys the speaker met. (3) I met two boys at 10:00. I met another at 11:00. The boys were This is only natural, since the H-domain contains three boys when the boys is uttered.' 3 Accommodation Cases like (1) could offer a problem for reduction of definiteness to familiarity, since the president wasn't introduced explicitly in the discourse beforehand; hence [3]'s appeal to accommodation. However, we want to have some characterization of when accommodation is or isn't possible. In our view, "accommodated" definites are simply R-definites. (1) is a case in point; John knows that there is only one president in the U.S., so he only has to identify the R-domain (the U.S. politics situation). In contrast, in (2), it isn't part of Alice's knowledge that the H-domain (the witnessed scene), or some other R-domain, contains a unique dog, hence the oddity of starting with (2'). (2') I found the dog The two kinds of definiteness can interact (associative use). In (4), the first sentence constructs an H-domain, which contains a car x. It is part of common knowledge that a car has a unique fence, so it is known that x has a unique fence in its car situation, which is an R-domain (cf. [5]). This is why its fence is felicitous. In contrast, if x wasn't initially introduced in the Heimian way, we wouldn't have no clue as to which car's car situation is used as resource; hence, starting the conversation with the second sentence of (4) is infelicitous. (4) I saw a car. Its fence was 4 Crosslinguistic ranges of definiteness While that president can't replace the president in (1), that dog can replace the dog in (2). Here we follow [6], [7] and [8] in treating both the P and that P (and proper names etc.) as definite descriptions. This means that, in explaining the replacement fact, we can't appeal to something like

the description/direct-reference distinction; rather, we have to explain it as commonalities and differences between two kinds of descriptions. My proposal here is that that P requires an H-domain while the P is compatible either with an H- or R-domain. The replacement fact about (1)-(2) follows from this proposal; the and that partially overlap in meaning (see also [9]). Seen from this perspective, some languages appear to mark the R/H distinction overtly. For example, in Japanese, inu can appear either with or without an article, depending on the context (inu roughly means dog). The article sono can attach to inu only when it is used as an H-definite. Thus, sono can't attach to the translation of the president in (1), while the dog in (2) can be translated into sono inu. Thus, sono corresponds to both that and the Heimian the.2 Further, I suggest that Japanese is not the only such language. For example, consider the examples (5)-(8) of Bavarian ([10], p. 69; originally from a paper by Hannes Scheutz) of Bavarian; da is Russellian and dea is Heimian (we assume that names are R-definites).3 (5) Dai*Dea Kare is kema. `Karl has arrived.' (6) Da/*Dea Kini is gschtoabm. `The King has died.' (7) Da/*Dea Schnaps is daia. `Schnaps is expensive.' (8) I hab a Bia un Schnaps bschdait. Dea/*Da Schnaps war daia. `I have ordered a beer and a schnaps. The schnaps was expensive.' 5 Extension to indefinite descriptions If indefinite descriptions are to be analyzed in terms of existential claims on a given domain (i.e. resource situation), then we will expect the R/H distinction is applicable to indefinites too. When an R-domain is chosen, a boy is to refer to an arbitrary boy. In contrast, if an H-domain is chosen, it is to refer to one of the boys already introduced in the discourse.4 The distinction overtly marked in Turkish noted in [12] can be viewed as such a case. [12] attempts to capture this distinction by stipulating two kinds of discourse referents. In contrast, with the R/H distinction, we need no such new stipulation.5 6 Conclusion In our analysis, H-definiteness is regarded as familiarity of H-domains, instead of familiarity of individuals; the latter is derivative from the former (also note that R-definites are also "familiar" in a sense; it is only that 87

Heimian familiarity, but not Russellian familiarity, is sensitive to discourse dynamics). Our move from individuals to domains is in line with [14]'s situation semantic arguments for the notion of resource situation (although not necessarily with his generalized-quantifier analysis of (in)definites). From the considerations in the previous sections, we conclude that the Russellian/Heimian distinction is something too significant to miss.' Notes *I would like to thank Shuichi Yatabe for discussion. I would also like to thank Tomoko Inagawa, Masayo Iida, Motoko Katayama, Mika Kizu, Atsushi Shimojima and some students at Kokushikan University for native judgments on Japanese. Of course, all remaining errors are mine. 1 1n principle, a single conversation can involve two or more H-domains; each H-domain is part of some or other R-domain. However, the hearer can't finely distinguish them without a good clue, in which case she only assumes one big H-domain subsuming all these small H-domains, as in (3). 'Here we are only saying that H-definites are explicitly so marked in the grammar by sono; we don't intend here to analyze bare nominals in Japanese, which can mean not only R-definites but also indefinites and generics, and further, for some speakers, H-definites in addition. In a more extensive study we will have to say that this in English and kono and ano in Japanese are also overt markers of H-definiteness (in fact, some Heimian uses of the translate to kono rather than sono). 3 [10] cites a paper by Karen Ebert and says that Frisian also follows this pattern (p. 69). On the other hand, [11]'s data, also cited in [10], of Indonesian could also be interpreted as exhibiting a similar contrast (bare nominals vs. those with itu or -nya, the former of which is a demonstrative corresponding to that according to [11]). Both [10] and [11] view the distinctions in terms of genericity. I can't examine their positions in this paper (cf. n. 2). Tut in [7]'5 terms, the R/H distinction for an indefinite then resides in whether its role should be assumed in an R-domain or an H-domain. 5 [13] observes that similar contrasts are overtly marked in German and Dutch etc. in terms of linear order. I have nothing interesting to say about this here. 6Due to lack of space I can't discuss [15] or the technical details of the present analysis (quantification over situations, novelty of indefinites, etc.). References [1] G. Link. "The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms." In R. Bauerle, C. Schwarze and A. von Stechow (eds.) Meaning, Use, and Interpretation of Language, 302-323, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1983. 88

[2] J. Hintikka and J. Kulas. "Different Uses of the Definite Article." In J. Hintikka and F. Vandamme (eds.) Logic of Discovery and Logic of Discourse, 71-82, New York and London: Plenum, 1985. [3] I. Heim. The Semantics of Definite and Indefintie Noun Phrases. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Massachusetts, Amherst, 1982. [4] J. A. Hawkins. Definiteness and Indefiniteness. London: Croom Helm, 1978. [5] K. Ishikawa. "Situated Groups." In A. Ishikawa and Y. Nitta (eds.) The Proceedings of the 1994 Kyoto Conference: A Festschrift for Professor Akira Ikeya, 21-30, Tokyo: The Logico-Linguistic Society of Japan, 1995. [6] K. Bach. Thought and Reference. Oxford: Clarendon, 1987. [7] K. Ishikawa. A Network Theory of Reference. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Tokyo, 1995. [8] K. Ishikawa. "Individuation and Reasoning." To appear in E. Engdahl, J. Etchemendy, J. Seligman, H. Sirai and D. Westersthl (eds.) Language, Logic and Computation: The 1994 Moraga Proceedings, Stanford: CSLI, In press. [9] J. P. Thorne. "On the Notion Tefinite'." Foundations of Language 8: 562-568,1972. [10] M. Krifka, F. J. Pelletier, G. N. Carlson, A. ter Meulen, G. Chierchia, and G. Link. "Genericity: An Introduction." In G. N. Carlson and F. J. Pelletier (eds.) The Generic Book, 1-124, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995. [111 L. Portersfield and V. Srivastay. "(In)definiteness in the Absence of Articles: Evidence from Hindi and Indonesian." In H. Borer (ed.) Proceedings of the Seventh West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, 265-276, Stanford: Stanford Linguistics Association, 1988. [12] M. Enc. "The Semantics of Specificity." Linguistic Inquiry 22: 1-25, 1991. [13] M. Diesing. Indefinites. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992. [14] R. Cooper. "Generalized Quantifiers and Resource Situations." In P. Aczel, D. Israel, Y. Katagiri and S. Peters (eds.) Situation Theory and its Applications, vol.3, 191-211, Stanford: CSLI, 1993. [15] N. Kadmon. "Uniqueness." Linguistics and Philosophy 13: 273-324, 1990. 89

90