What's in a Hole? A A inconsistent triad: By Steven A. Gross

Similar documents
Bennett on Parts Twice Over

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

On Recanati s Mental Files

Lecture 10 Popper s Propensity Theory; Hájek s Metatheory

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Sidestepping the holes of holism

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Moral Judgment and Emotions

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

observation and conceptual interpretation

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

McDowell, Demonstrative Concepts, and Nonconceptual Representational Content Wayne Wright

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Lecture 7: Incongruent Counterparts

BOOK REVIEW. William W. Davis

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

Ontology as a formal one. The language of ontology as the ontology itself: the zero-level language

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Logic, Truth and Inquiry (Book Review)

1/10. Berkeley on Abstraction

Why Pleasure Gains Fifth Rank: Against the Anti-Hedonist Interpretation of the Philebus 1

Steven E. Kaufman * Key Words: existential mechanics, reality, experience, relation of existence, structure of reality. Overview

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

6 Bodily Sensations as an Obstacle for Representationism

Working BO1 BUSINESS ONTOLOGY: OVERVIEW BUSINESS ONTOLOGY - SOME CORE CONCEPTS. B usiness Object R eference Ontology. Program. s i m p l i f y i n g

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

M. Chirimuuta s Adverbialism About Color. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. I. Color Adverbialism

Aristotle on the Human Good

Comments on Bence Nanay, Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery

Spectrum inversion as a challenge to intentionalism

Université Libre de Bruxelles

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

Perceptions and Hallucinations

The Constitution Theory of Intention-Dependent Objects and the Problem of Ontological Relativism

CARROLL ON THE MOVING IMAGE

On Defining Art Historically

From: R. Casati and A. C. Varzi, 50 Years of Events: An Annotated Bibliography 1947 to 1997, Bowling Green, OH: Philosophy Documentation Center, 1997,

Book Reviews Department of Philosophy and Religion Appalachian State University 401 Academy Street Boone, NC USA

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

206 Metaphysics. Chapter 21. Universals

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN:

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Formalizing Irony with Doxastic Logic

Semiotics of culture. Some general considerations

IN DEFENSE OF ESSENTIALISM 1. L. A. Paul University of Arizona Australian National University/RSSS

Rational Agency and Normative Concepts by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord UNC/Chapel Hill [for discussion at the Research Triangle Ethics Circle] Introduction

Scientific Philosophy

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan. by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

Internal Realism. Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

Humanities Learning Outcomes

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Review of Epistemic Modality

Partial and Paraconsistent Approaches to Future Contingents in Tense Logic

Objects and Things: Notes on Meta- pseudo- code (Lecture at SMU, Dec, 2012)

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong

WHAT IS WRONG WITH THE RELATIONAL THEORY OF CHANGE? Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra Hertford College, Oxford

SIGNS, SYMBOLS, AND MEANING DANIEL K. STEWMT*

Strategies for Writing about Literature (from A Short Guide to Writing about Literature, Barnett and Cain)

Watching Anna knit, it s clear that the scarf she s making and the yarn

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

(as methodology) are not always distinguished by Steward: he says,

Perception and Mind-Dependence Lecture 3

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

Uskali Mäki Putnam s Realisms: A View from the Social Sciences

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

LeBar s Flaccidity: Is there Cause for Concern?

The erratically fine-grained metaphysics of functional kinds in technology and biology

Replies to the Critics

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN

Contradictions, Dialectics, and Paradoxes as Discursive Approaches to Organizational Analysis

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

Abstract Several accounts of the nature of fiction have been proposed that draw on speech act

Berkeley s idealism. Jeff Speaks phil October 30, 2018

Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008

Aristotle s Metaphysics

SNP Best-set Typesetter Ltd. Article No.: 583 Delivery Date: 31 October 2005 Page Extent: 4 pp

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography

University of Bristol - Explore Bristol Research. Peer reviewed version License (if available): Unspecified

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

RESPONDING TO ART: History and Culture

Transcription:

What's in a Hole? By Steven A. Gross rgle and Bargle - the protagonists of David and Stephanie Lewis' philosophical dialogue "Holes"1 ("in many ways, the inspirationn2 for the book under review) - worry themselves over the following A A inconsistent triad: (I) There exist no immaterial, abstract objects; (11) Holes exist; and (111) Holes are immaterial objects (since they involve the absence of matter). "Measuring th[e] price"3 of retaining (I), they consider ways of rejecting (11) and (111). If holes don't exist, it would seem that our apparent reference to and quantification over holes requires reinterpretation.4 Perhaps, for instance, the underlying logical form of such statements as "There are three holes in that piece of cheese" is something like that of "That piece of cheese is trebly-perforated." Such attempts at reinterpretation, however, seem to founder rather quickly. Argle and Bargle get stuck on "There are as many holes in my cheese as crackers on my plate,"5 and so turn to (111). But if holes are material, what is their matter? Not, it would seem, the matter occupying the space where the hole is located, if vacuums are possible. Argle argues rather that the lining of a hole - itself a material object - is the hole, so that the hole's matter is just that of the lining. But the price of this view, given the many candidate linings (how thick should the lining be?), includes inter alia admitting that for all holes, there is an x and a y such that xis the same hole as y, but xis not identical to y. (Oh - but when one is speaking of holes, 'same,' it is suggested, means 'coperforated.')6 Casati and Varzi wish to resist such ways of rejecting (11) and (111), the former as not sufficiently realist about holes, the latter as counter-intuitive.7 They argue rather that holes are immaterial bodies, a claim they introduce in terms of the following analogy: holes are composed of - but not identical to regions of - space, as material bodies are composed of - but not identical to particular quantities of - matter.* Space is thus, Casati and Varzi

suggest, the matter of holes; although, whereas holes are composed of space only, material objects are composed both of space and "ordinary matter." I say that this is how Casati and Varzi introduce their claim, because within a page they suggest that there is but one matter - which can be bare or palified - out of which all bodies (whether "immaterial," like holes, or material) are composed. On this presumably distinct conception, bare matter would correspond to space on the first account, and qualified matter to ordinary matter. Whether we still have, on this second conception, a mere analogy is unclear to me. Nor is it clear to me which conception Casati and Varzi favor. Their initial discussion of space as bare, unqualified matter is somewhat circumspect ("common sense does not forbid us," "according to some theorists it would be reasonable," "If one accepts this piece of metaphysics"), but whatever qualms they have seem to vanish within a page: "Holes are spacious; they are made of space; they consist of 'bare,' unqualified matter."9 Since Casati and Varzi do not at all develop the key concepts involved, I shall leave to one side whatever may be at stake between these two conceptions. I remain confused about what work is done - on either conception "Perhaps for the purpose of buildin8 a - by the ;laim robot that can follow sach instrwtions that holes are composed of as 'Put this rod in that hole,' some forspace. As far as I can tell. the malism regimentin8 our ordinary con- - remainder of cepts might prove quite useful. " Casati and Varzi's claims are equally consistent with the thesis that holes, although located in space (and although, if you like, they are bodies, albeit immaterial), are not composed of anythmg at all.10 This talk of being composed of space, in addition to its unclarity, seems an idle wheel." And Casati and Varzi do have much more to say about holes, more indeed than can receive mention in this brief note. Prominent among their claims are the following. Holes are always in something; they are "ontologically dependent" upon material hosts.12 A hole is connected (in the topological sense) to a surface of a host, but only when the surface contains discontinuities and concavities. Holes are fillable. These claims - along with remarks concerning the identity conditions of holes, the ways holes are created and destroyed (including the ways various kinds of holes can be made from other kinds of holes), and the ways holes are perceived - are elaborated in some detail, so as to provide a sort of taxonomy and natural history of holes and their kinds. Hollows, cavities, and tunnels are distinguished, for instance, in terms of concepts drawn from mereology and topology. "Why this obsession with holes?" a female colleague slyly asked. The Lewises defended - or had Argle and Bargle defend - their seven-page dialogue by adverting, beyond the intrinsic interest of holes, to their illustrative

value: their consideration of holes provides a neat, self-contained display of the standard structure of many ontological disputes. Casati and Varzi defend their book-length study - again, in addition to pointing to the intrinsic interest of holes - by suggesting that it might contribute to an area of artificial intelligence research sometimes called "naive physics - the science of ordinary things, space, time and motions at the ordinary man's disposal in his everyday actions."13 However, their unrefreshing insouciance concerning matters methodological and criteria of adequacy, in particular, leaves the upshot of this seemingly scientific backing unclear. What one encounters is more or less standard conceptual analysis enlisted to motivate a formalism, with appeals to intuition serving throughout to reject alternative accounts. (This, even though among the many surprising consequences of Casati and Varzi's own account are (1) that when one sticks a solid object in water, one creates a hole in the water which the body completely fills (reedy swamps may thus have hundreds of tunnels in them), and (2) that there are no holes in aggregates, even if there are mock holes ("although the modifier 'mock' contains too much understatementn).)14 But even allowing for vagueness, as Casati and Varzi do, ought we to expect or desire a complete formalization of our concept of a hole and related concepts, adequate to all the ways we employ these concepts in everyday reasoning?l5 Even a formalization that includes, as does that contained in their semi-technical appendix "Outline of a Theory" (my emphasis), five non-logical primitives, 24 definitions, and seventeen axioms?16 Perhaps for the purpose of building a robot that can follow such instructions as "Put this rod in that hole," some formalism regimenting our ordinary concepts might prove quite useful, even if it doesn't agree with ordinary usage in all cases. I doubt, however, we are yet in a position to know.17 Exercising the reviewer's prerogative, I have raised some questions concerning, first, an aspect of Casati and Varzi's answer to the question 'What are holes?,' and second, a lack of clarity regarding the nature of their project. I should like to conclude, however, by emphasizing how much of interest is nevertheless contained in the details of their discussions. cp l~avid Lewis and Stephanie Lewis, "Holes," Au.rtralnsian Journal of Philosophy 48 (1970), pp. 206-212. Reprinted in David Lewis, Philosophical Papers, Volume I (Oxford University Press, 1983), pp. 3-9, which I will cite. 2~asati and Varzi, p. 236. 3Lewis, p. 9. lperhaps not. Perhaps one could reject (XI), and yet continue taking statements such as "There are three holes in that piece of cheesen at face value, by providing an account that warrants the assertion of such falsehoods. 5Lewis, p. 4. Note, by the way, that a successful scheme of reinterpretation could equally well serve as a basis for arguing that (I)-(111) do not, despite appearances, form an inconsistent triad, since once the apparent quantification over holes in (11) is reinterpreted, (11) and (111)

no longer imply the negation of (I). 'kewis, pp. 6-7. Frank Jackson, incidentally, has proposed deploying hole-linings in support of rejecting (11). Perhaps we ought not identtfy holes and hole-figs - the thought runs - but we can instead reinterpret putative reference to holes as in fact to hole-linings. See his Perception: A Representativc Z%eory (Cambridge University Press, 1977), p. 132. 7~asati and Varzi, pp. 3 and 37. They also consider and reject (as too reductionist) views according to which holes are identical to parts of the surfaces of their hosts, where surfaces - as far as I can make it out - are two-dimensional "geometrical" (p. 12) abstractions that, unlike hole-linings, are not material objects. *~asati and Varzi, p. 32. The objection to identlfylng holes and regions of space is that the former, but not the latter, can move. (Here, however, a familiar dialectic might ensue: (A) Why not go "four-dimensional" and identify holes - considered now as extended in time as well as space - with regions of space-time (to say a hole can move would then just be to say that a temporal part of a hole can be located in a different region of space than another temporal part of the same hole)? (B) Still, the hole and the region of space-time would possess dif ferent modal properties and so should not be identified. For example, the hole could have been elsewhere, not so the region of space-time. (A) But a counterpart-theoretic approach to modal discourse can explain away such differences. (Etc.) And (A) and (B) might further wonder whether regions of space or of space-time ought to be considered material. Cf. below.) 9p. 33, first three quotes; pp. 33-4, last quote. One might wonder, on either conception, why Casati and Varzi persist in calling holes immaterial objects. Presumably, the answer is that on the first conception, they would require of material objects that they be composed both of space and "ordinary matter," and on the second account they would require that they be composed of qualified matter. I suppose whether one should nonetheless construe Casati and Varzi as in fact rejecting (111), not (I), is immaterial. lo~uthen I suppose they are also consistent with the thesis that holes are composed of (quantities of) Nothing. (I don't claim that this idea is pellucid. That's my point.) ll~he area of inquiry one might have thought most relevant to such matters (viz., physics) does not make an appearance here. Perhaps Casati and Varzi's interest in the project of "naive physics" (mentioned below) explains their seeming indifference to real physics. 12~s Casati and Varzi make clear (pp. 18-19), they do not have in mind the mere de dicto claim that necessarily, all holes have hosts. But they do not distinguish the following de re claims: (1) For all x, necessarily, if x is a hole, then x has a host, and (2) For all x, if x is a hole, then necessarily x has a host. (l), bur not (2), allows of course that a hole might not have been one. I believe they have (2) in mind. Casati and Varzi deny, by the way, that if h is the host of hole x, then necessarily, h is x's host (in all worlds in which x exists). (One further note: it is of course just such facts pairing holes and material hosts that Argle attempts to exploit in identlfjnng holes and their linings.) 13p. 3. (My female colleague will perhaps slyly wonder whether women should take comfort in this exclusion from the naive.) Cf. Patrick Hayes' "The Naive Physics Manifesto" in The Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence, Margaret Boden, ed. (Oxford University Press, 1990). This collection also includes Drew McDermott's apostasy "A Critique of Pure Reason." In her "Introduction," Margaret Boden more aptly describes the brief of naive physics as the formalization and axiomatization of commonsense knowledge (pp. 11-2). 14pp. 145-146 and 149-151, respectively. I would not say, when I stick my hand in the bath to test the temperature, that I have made a hole in the water, or even simply that there is a hole in the water. Is this just due to some sort of cancelable pragmatic restriction? I woxld say, in appropriate circumstances, that there is a hole (a hole, not a "mock" hole) in my shirt, aggregate though it is. Can this be explained away as just a bit of loose talk? 15cf. the conclusion Casati and Varzi draw having brought out various complexities in our use of the word 'lake'(p. 171): "'Lake' is used with certain principal descriptive purposes in mind, which vary according to our changes of interest." Why not say something similar about 'hole'?

16casati and Varzi also helpfully include sixty-six elementary consequences thereof. 171 suspect Casati and Varzi would agree. The last exercise in their nice set of puzzles and exercises reads: "Exercise [very hard]. Write a program that a robot could profitably use to put certain objects into certain holes" (p. 218). (I might mention also that in addition to this puzzle/exercise set and the semi-technical appendix, the book contains a wealth of helpful diagrams and a richly annotated bibliography.)