Some years ago, the philosopher Mary Midgley wrote

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Some years ago, the philosopher Mary Midgley wrote"

Transcription

1 How and Why Animals Matter Strachon Donnelley Some years ago, the philosopher Mary Midgley wrote Animals and Why They Matter (Midgley 1983). The book speaks for itself eloquently; and despite much philosophic, theological, and ethical exploration of humans' relations to and use of animals in laboratory research and elsewhere, the central question remains: Why do animals matter? The question remains fundamentally important because we humans and the character and goodness of our lives are centrally implicated. Our attitude toward animals and wider animate life says much about who we are and about our basic human and moral stance toward the world. Moral concerns for animals in laboratory research settings are not new. Fundamental moral issues of pain, suffering, distress, death, and respect have long been recognized by animal care and use committees and researchers who have acknowledged the importance of guidelines for laboratory animal care (Donnelley and Nolan 1990; NRC 1992). Yet our basic attitudes and moral stances toward animals remain a crucial and ongoing issue, for these motivate our behavior and concern toward animals how we follow guidelines and what standards are used. I believe it is appropriate to reopen the issue of how and why animals matter and ask again: Is it possible to agree on an overall framework of thought or world view to orient ourselves and help guide our moral decision making on animal use with respect to institutional policies and individual research protocols? Animals matter to us within particular contexts of human interests, purposes, and concerns; frameworks of thought and action; and situations requiring moral judgment and response. These contexts are as numerous as the various opportunities for thought and action that involve both ourselves and animals. In this article, I explore our encounters with animals in various settings (laboratories, homes, and the wild) and then ask whether these various encounters suggest overall philosophic reflections on why animals matter to us in fundamentally important ways ways that might not be immediately obvious to us in laboratory settings. Finally, I explore what a robust philosophy of organism or organic life offers on this issue of animals "mattering" to humans. Strachan Donnelley, Ph.D., is Director of the Humans and Nature Program, The Hastings Center, Garrison, New York. Animal Encounters In the Laboratory Who or what is the animal (such as a mouse or frog) in laboratory research? First and foremost, it is an object of physiological or behavioral inquiry. It primarily "matters" because it is the practicing scientist's object of scientific curiosity. In the heat of scientific activity, the animal is essentially a physiological or behavioral system unconnected with the environing world. It is an isolated representative or model of physiological, behavioral, or animal (biological) existence. The practicing scientist is subjectively animated by scientific questions and uses reigning scientific paradigms and related conceptual approaches such as Galilean-Cartesian materialism, Watsonian genetics, or Skinnerian behaviorism to answer the questions and to formulate new inquiries. 1 These dominant scientific interests and conceptions are crucial in determining the animal's characteristics or identity for the scientist. The animals and scientists are embedded within an overarching scientific world view that includes its own particular ethos and mores. If the science is materialist and mechanistic, the scientist observes and acts on what is taken to be a mere material mechanism. In any case, science by definition is universal or abstractly general, and so the encounter is with the animal as a faceless instance of animate being. Typically a laboratory animal scientist, when acting in the role of a scientist, does not encounter an individual animal in its ordinary worldly context, including its relationships with other individual animals. As the object of scientific inquiry in the laboratory, the animal is an isolated "it," 'The scientific revolution of the 16th and 17th centuries, orchestrated by Galileo ( ), Descartes ( ), and Newton ( ), among others, has been particularly dominant in modern Western science and culture. Scientifically, nature has been understood to be essentially physical or material (matter or energy in motion or agitation); causally deterministic (physical antecedents solely determining physical consequents, with no room for mental spontaneity or any exercise of freedom, human or other); and amenable to prediction via mathematical expression of physical laws, statistical or not. These characteristics of natural science survive into the 20th century, for example, in the molecular biology and genetics inspired by the discovery of DNA by Watson and Crick (1953) and in the psychological behaviorism (stimulus and response, operant conditioning) of B. F. Skinner ( ). Significantly for us, the scientific study of animals characteristically ignores, if not denies outright, the individual liveliness, experience, and "subjectivity" of the animal, which are a central concern of ethics and moral consideration. 22 WAR Journal

2 viewed primarily as a representative of a genus or class and not as an individual living being with a life of its own. An abstract view of the animal as a "type" is necessary for universal, objective, and empirically verifiable biological knowledge. In the Home The situation described above changes significantly when the scientist or technician leaves the laboratory and goes home, where many of us encounter animals as pets. When I arrive home from a day of administration and bioethical reflection, there is Nasti, our aging black Labrador retriever. Galilean science, Skinnerian behaviorism, or moral philosophy are the farthest things from my mind. I want to know whether Nasti has been outside lately and whether he has raided the garbage bag. He is no faceless "it" or scientific model for me, but an all too familiar individual. He is lovable, difficult, and annoying, just like the other members of our household, which includes five daughters. Actually, I rarely think of Nasti explicitly in the thought frameworks of "animal" or "biology." He is simply Nasti, with whom I must live and deal, day in and day out. Nasti's importance for me is not equal to my wife's or daughters', and we often ignore him while pursuing our more immediate human interests. Nevertheless, Nasti receives similar attention and care, and he is definitely an integral member of the lively community that is our home. Moreover, there are times when Nasti and I prefer to be away from the others, whether crosscountry skiing along a river or wrestling in the grass. In short, Nasti exists for me as an individual within the framework and feeling of familial living. Encounters with domestic pets are very different from a scientist's involvements with laboratory animals. In the 2 contexts, the animals exist and matter for human beings in decidedly different ways, and the human actors are animated by dissimilar interests, feelings, and thoughts. Both the humans and the animals exist within different webs of human meanings and values. Central to the world of homes and families are the values of care, concern, and responsibility for one another; and pets fit integrally into this world. Thus, our feelings of concrete responsibility for the care of domestic pets are characteristically different than they are for laboratory animals. Animals experienced as uniquely individual and as "members" of human families have a stronger and more complex ethical importance to us; likewise, we have come to matter essentially to them. Without our family or human others to provide similar care and affection, Nasti in all probability would be unable to fend for himself. He has always, and more or less happily, lived within the walls of our home, irrespective of walks in the woods. In contrast, involvements with most laboratory animals, under the dominant umbrella of scientific meanings and values, are characteristically less personal and intimate. These animals, with the possible exceptions of certain higher mammalian individuals, matter differently and are less dependent on interactions with human others for their own individual wellbeing. They require the care and attention necessary for them to flourish as laboratory animals, not as members of human family households. In the Wild In addition to human and animal experiences of a domestic nature, encounters with animals in the wild, outside the "human city," constitute other philosophically and ethically significant experiences. These encounters are particularly important because the animals again matter differently and play, or can play, a decidedly different role in determining the terms of the human experience and the particular context or web of meanings and values. Human interests and activities become more and more attuned to animals and animate being within the natural world. This is how we culturally "civilized ones" recreate ourselves bodily, artistically, scientifically, and ethically. New vistas of human selfunderstanding derive from and are altered by the vital interplay of the human city (human cultural life) and the natural, animate world. Encounters with wild animals may occur close to home. While cooking weekend breakfasts, I look out a country kitchen window at birds around a feeder chickadees, blue jays, cardinals, woodpeckers, doves, sparrows, red-winged blackbirds, and numerous (but for me, nameless) others. I am drawn by the diverse bird species and by the antagonisms, cooperative efforts, and natively instituted pecking orders. I may in passing be provoked to think of Darwin, artists, or some ethological tract, since this is the kind of primary worldly experience that may have motivated those human explorers. Although I have enticed the birds onto the back lawn with a feeder, they come and leave on their own terms. They are familiar to me, yet are independent creatures that do not need me. My birdseed is gratis, a brief respite in their naturally rigorous lives. They are beyond my direct human responsibilities and dominantly human-centered frameworks of thought. As I peer out the window, the birds are in the world abroad, undisturbed. I am a mere spectator. I let them be. Correspondingly, I am more or less free to make of them what I will, elaborating my own web of thoughts, meanings, and values. My natural inclination to be a spectator may be transfigured, and I may be lured out-of-doors in search of other animals in wilder habitats. I may remain an amateur observer of the animal realm or imagine becoming a professional ethologist, progressing from native curiosity to scientific inquiry. In any case, this arguably is not our most richly complex and primordial human encounter with wild animals. Additional conceptions, meanings, and values are to be uncovered. Here a thinking human being stands "over against" the naturally active animals, viewing them across a divide constituted by disinterested "beholding." Something crucial to human self-understanding is missing in this example of the way animals matter to us. The human has not engaged, Volume 40, Number

3 or been engaged by, the animals in a single sphere of dynamic interaction. The human individual has not radically discovered its own animality and natural mode of organic being, its primary status in the natural scheme of things. Such firsthand revelations are left to other human encounters with wild animals, for example, those in hunting and fishing, described below. Human Involvement in the Wild Each June I go fishing during a mayfly hatch on a remote pond in northern Wisconsin. Other actors in this annual event (a natural high holiday) include my daughter Inanna, red-winged blackbirds and swallows, brown trout, and the mayflies. Typically the pond is still, or a slight breeze ripples the water. It is dusk with a red-orange sun setting behind a blackening forest of evergreen trees. The air is cool, and the sounds consist only of birds and mosquitoes. A swallow leaves its perch on a dead stump in the middle of the pond and dives through the air, to be joined immediately by other birds. Inanna and I quickly row over to the birds. A host of dun-colored mayflies emerges on the water's surface. The surface is broken by a swirl, and a mayfly disappears. The dusk deepens, with only the faint light of the horizon. There are slurps of feeding trout all around us. Inanna and I cast our flies to the sounds. Occasionally there is a decent cast, and we dimly see the dry fly riding high on the water. Reacting to a swirl and a sudden, strong pull on the rod, we fight the fish in the dark, trying to keep it away from submerged logs. Sometimes we lose the fish; other times we land it a cool, smooth, fat-bellied brown trout. We throw it back or put it in the boat's live-box and, along with the blackbirds, go home, leaving the other trout to continue their feast well into the night. Several things about this human involvement in a mayfly hatch are noteworthy. First, it is the natural and animal world that importantly sets the terms of the human experience and determines reflections on its meanings and values. The concerns and preoccupations of the human city are left far behind. Second, a human being enters the realm of action as only one among several actors, and the actors are fundamentally on equal terms. All are interlocked in a single dynamic realm, involved in characteristic living activities, whether seeking prey, avoiding predators, or preparing for mating. All of this activity takes place within a community of interaction. Being a participant actor "within," rather than a spectatorobserver "without," decisively transforms the human experience. The animals are seen in a different and arguably more complex and realistic light. The swallow in this context is no mere physiological and behavioral system or scientific object, nor is it an object of disinterested curiosity. It is a living individual, an animal subject actively involved in its own world. The swallow patiently and attentively awaits the anticipated mayflies, an unwitting lookout for the parasitic human fishermen. The brown trout are wily animate others lurking in the depths, strangely beautiful, intricately patterned and colored. The mayflies bring the trout to the surface, casting their natural caution to the winds. The mayflies themselves are shapely and delicate emissaries from the (for us) mysterious insect kingdom, the focus of this complex and compelling natural drama, even while they are having their 1 day in the sun after a year as nymphs in the muddy bottom of the pond. In short, these animals are not objects of science or everyday curiosity, nor are they familiar pets. They are living, individual, and interconnected wild presences, emerging from, while remaining in, nature. By the wild otherness of the animals and our firsthand interactions with them, we vividly confront our own existence as living organisms. We are shocked back from the provinces of the human city to our place within the wider natural scheme of things. We are forced to probe radically the nature of our own organic being and to question thoughtfully the natural world and its ultimate meaning, values, and goodness why we, animals, and nature matter and matter together. Two aspects of the scene described above stand out forcibly: the dynamic interconnection or interaction of animals and their own individual liveliness or being. In the pursuit of philosophic interpretation and ethical responsibility, I want to emphasize both dynamic interconnectedness and individuality, for they bear significantly on questions of the moral status of humans, animals, and nature. Philosophic Reflections The foregoing descriptions of animal encounters in different contexts how and why animals matter involve humanly reflective interpretations as well as descriptions of ourselves, animals, and nature. The example of the mayfly hatch includes not too distant echoes of Darwinian evolutionary biology and ecology as well as nature poets and philosophers. For humans, this cultural overlay seems to be characteristic and inevitable. It is harmless if explicitly recognized for what it is. Actually it is the interaction or intermingling of our firsthand experiences and culturally influenced reflections that allows us to understand and explicitly value ourselves, animals, and nature. The philosophical reflections on animals in the wild that follow are intended to explore the question, Why, most fully, do animals matter to us? Our reflections may enable us to take a moral stance that we, both as members of the human family and as researchers, can embrace. The reflections are derived, at least in part, from the thought of Charles Darwin, Aldo Leopold, Alfred North Whitehead, and Han Jonas. Charles Darwin I have chosen to begin this philosophic exploration with the thought of Charles Darwin (as interpreted by Ernst Mayr) because, in the present era, a theory of evolutionary biology 24 ILAR Journal

4 and ecology must fit into any philosophy of nature that we can honestly embrace (Mayr 1991). In a nutshell, Darwin's doctrine of evolution involves the evolution of all life and organic species from a common origin via genetic and behavioral variation and natural selection. For our purposes, certain crucial aspects of Darwin's theory merit emphasis. (1) There is the, by now famous, demise of the cosmic teleology or purpose, that is grand design/designer of nature. Now our understanding is that nature evolves its own forms of order and dynamic evolutionary and ecological processes. It is ruled or governed by no one. (2) The introduction of evolutionary thought has signaled an end to Newtonian causal determinism, which rests on the hegemony of efficient causation (antecedents solely determine consequents). Our fundamental framework of thought concerning nature now is that organic events (whether genetic, organismal, or ecological) are caused by myriad factors involving multispatial and temporal scales. These major features of Darwin's thought give rise to "systems thinking," that is, the importance of complex historical contexts and the recognition that outcomes are the product of multiple systems of interactive factors. Of greater importance, for our purposes, is the fact that Darwinian biology has resulted in the end of typological or essentialist thinking as a fundamental tool for interpreting nature. We no longer have the traditional species concept of "dog," "horse," and "human being." Rather we have moved to "populational thinking" or modes of thought, which considers individual differences among organisms to have central significance. Individual organisms live and interact within interbreeding populations (as well as within the wider world). Each individual organism is genetically and phenotypically unique, different from all the others. These fundamental themes of individuality, particularity, and diversity are the backbone of the evolutionary story and likewise characterize populations, communities of organisms, ecosystems, and bioregions. Moreover, these themes are conjoined with equally fundamental ideas of the importance of historical contexts, dynamism, and contingency the direct or indirect interconnections of all forms of life in the unique "story" that is the historical evolution of life on this planet. I suspect that for many of us, the fundamental lineaments of the evolutionary, ecological account appear interpretively much closer to our experiences of mayfly hatches and other animals in the wild than to our encounters with animals in scientific laboratories. Remember that in laboratories, the individuality and particularity of animals are minimized, if not totally eclipsed, by our focus on that which is universal and common to the objects of our studies. The emphasis in laboratory animal science is characteristically on constant laws of nature and organic being that allow Newtonian thought patterns to reign over those featured by Darwin. In latoratories, something important, something that matters to us as human beings, is invariably omitted from consideration namely, the world view and message of Darwinian evolutionary, ecological nature. From a philosophic and moral perspective, we must ask the question, Is laboratory science too partial, too abstract? Conversely, we must also ask, Does a Darwinian account of organic life and systems in scientific, evolutionary, and ecological theory omit something that matters to human beings? If we regard the objects of our study as mere behavioral cogs, energy exchangers, or genetic reproducers in a natural or cosmic system, we run the risk of missing the individual animals and all that they philosophically, spiritually, and ethically connote. Where, in this frame of thought, is Nasti, our family Labrador? We now proceed onto philosophically speculative ground, which inherently and by necessity is slippery. We simply do not know final philosophic truths with certainty. However, we must continue our explorations if we want to understand, no matter how imperfectly, why we and animals matter. Let us consider the following brief discussions of 3 philosophers Aldo Leopold, Alfred North Whitehead, and Hans Jonas who boldly ventured beyond science into speculative philosophy to interpret why we, animals, and nature matter. Aldo Leopold The patron saint of modern conservation ethics (protection of the natural environment), Aldo Leopold, is famous for his land ethic and for defining the human good and bad in terms of our impact on the "integrity, stability, and beauty" of the biotic community or the land (all biotic and abiotic elements of nature, including ourselves, that are implicated in life processes). In A Sand County Almanac (Leopold 1968), Leopold explicitly embraces a Darwinian evolutionary and ecological scientific and philosophic world view and exhorts us to become "plain members and citizens" of the land, rather than the conquerors of an alien or antihuman nature. The final piece of his philosophic revolution is the recognition of the genuine subjectivity and individual liveliness of animals. Some examples are the she-wolf of Thinking Like a Mountain, predators such as bears and cougars, and less imposing sandhill cranes, grebes, woodcock, chickadees, hunting dogs, and brook trout. Leopold's philosophic revolution or conversion is perhaps most vividly expressed by his encounter with the shewolf in Thinking Like a Mountain (Leopold 1968). Leopold had been professionally involved in the Southwest in game management, specifically the eradication of predators (wolves, bears, and mountain lions) for the purpose of increasing deer populations for hunters, if not paving the way for cattle ranging. While on a mountain trip, Leopold and his companions came upon a she-wolf crossing a river to join her cubs. Following the dictates of "wise-use" game management and the "trigger-itch" of young hunters, the group shot at the wolves, killing the she-wolf. As Leopold watched the "fierce green fire" dying in the she-wolf's eyes, he was humbled. The mountain and the wolf knew something that Leopold did not, and what they knew shamed him. Predators have an ultimate significance and central role to play in evolutionary, ecological, and geological time and the ongoing Volume 40, Number

5 well-being of ecosystemic nature and the humanly good life. Leopold had previously been thinking, feeling, and acting in a wrong frame of reference. He had not taken a long-range biotic, evolutionary, and ecological perspective and did not appreciate the roles that wolves and other large predators play in the overall health of specific ecosystems (keeping prey species at healthy levels, preventing the overcropping of plant resources, helping the ecosystemic whole maintain a "dynamic balance or equilibrium"). Henceforth, Leopold knew better. Two things are simultaneously happening to Leopold in this account. He is radically converted to a biotic, evolutionary, and ecological world view; and he comes to recognize the genuine individuality and subjective life of animals the fierce green fire of the she-wolf s eyes. Thus, Leopold enjoyed both a personal and "philosophic" relationship with animals that he encountered, and a similar appreciation for the wild interactive flora that is their habitat, precisely because he was convinced that all originated from and interacted in evolutionary, ecological nature that all life had a common origin and lively connections, a single historical home, which includes all. Leopold recognized a specific human difference or significance within nature; only humans could (imperfectly) comprehend the evolutionary story and be morally moved and motivated by its triumphs and tragedies. However, this difference can arise only because we share varying evolved capacities of life with all other animal and animate life. All are "commonly connected" by the very fact of life, which expresses itself and its capacities variously in its individual instances. Animals matter importantly, but their mattering to us involves both their individual liveliness and our common historical context. Meeting animals on equal terms in a common historical world is a characteristic theme of A Sand County Almanac. Alfred North Whitehead Earlier in the 20th century, Alfred North Whitehead made a similar philosophic and particularly telling move. In his classic essays "Nature Lifeless" and "Nature Alive" (Whitehead 1968), Whitehead traces the historical rise and demise of modern Galilean-Cartesian-Newtonian science a scientific world view of nature based dominantly on "superficial" common sense and sense perception (especially vision), assuming "nature at an instant" (no necessary and significant historical dimensions and interactions) and a "billiard-ballsin-motion" causal determinism and materialism. By the end of the 19th century, new scientific emphasis on electromagnetism, energetic dynamism, and field theory (the complex interconnections and interactions of all physical constituents of the world) led to what Whitehead claimed to be a "mystical chant over an unintelligible universe," a philosophical, if not scientific, dead end. Whitehead was particularly interested in what the reigning modern science and philosophy ("positivism," the claim that only empirically verifiable observations constitute knowledge) left unintelligible: the interconnections of life, thought, and nature among themselves and with fact and value, which also are experienced as interconnected. These are primary, "pre-philosophical" deliverances of our everyday human experience. In a revolt against contemporary forms of materialism and idealism, 2 Whitehead recoiled and philosophically examined intimate bodily feelings where he found "nature alive," genuine episodes of natural liveliness, characterized by "absolute self-enjoyment" (an immediate, emotional appropriation or taking account of the antecedent world), "creative activity" (the individual process of appropriation), and "aim" (the aim of becoming a uniquely individual instance of life). These bodily experiences disclose (or strongly suggest) the identity of the immediate self with the past self and with the world abroad. Our basic experience reveals the self in the world and the world in the self (mutual immanence). In mutual immanence, life, mentality, and nature are philosophically interpreted in their interconnections with antecedent fact (achievement) and immediate valuing (emotional appreciation and lively reaction). Armed with his new interpretative conceptual scheme of nature alive, Whitehead sought to make intelligible what materialist science left unexplained, if not incomprehensible. Whitehead philosophically interpreted or explained memory (the past functioning in the present); the perception both of one's body and the external world; causation (both efficient and final (effective purpose)); why we arise where and when we do (the primacy of historical context; worldly becoming; and natural, human, and cultural evolution). Moreover, Whitehead rediscovered a significant, valuable, and meaningful nature instances of life (including human and animal individuals) interconnected and aiming individually and collectively at particular worldly achievements and intensities of experience. This "democracy" of historical and "community" life imbued Whitehead with a naturalistic and cosmological spirit (aesthetic and philosophic enjoyment) and appreciation of animal and animate life akin to Leopold's, although he was characteristically more interested in human, particularly intellectual and cultural, history. In any case, the telling critique and grand synthesis of "Nature Lifeless" and "Nature Alive" are eminently worth reading (or rereading) if we want to comprehend how and why we and animals matter. Hans Jonas From quite a different mood and philosophic perspective, Hans Jonas also revolted against the hegemony of modern 2 As used here, philosophical materialism and idealism can roughly be understood as fundamental counterclaims: (1) that all of reality is at bottom physical or material (in terms of which experience or mental phenomena must be interpreted or explained); or (2) experiential, spiritual, or mental (in terms of which physical nature must be interpreted or explained). Philosophically, this is not a happy choice for those who want adequately to interpret organisms and organic life, including humans. Arguably, both materialism and idealism exclude organisms and organic life from philosophic sight and understanding. 26 ILAR Journal

6 materialist science. He found his way to a philosophy of organic life that philosophically, morally, and spiritually rehabilitated humans and nature and that served as a basis for envisioning important ethical responsibilities to the human and natural future (Jonas 1984). As an active Jewish participant in the humanly fateful events of the World War II, Jonas was particularly concerned with the specters of philosophic and moral nihilism, the core feature of which is the denial of all moral truth, value, and goodness. An intellectually naive and unreflective scientific materialism (mechanistic determinism) denies the freedom and efficacy of mind and annihilates all subjective agency and achievements (realized values), human and other. Jonas held that mechanistic determinism involves or implies a philosophical and ethical nihilism that silently haunts our world, undermining the legitimacy of moral, political, and civic effort and authority. However, such an uncompromising materialism leads, according to Jonas, to manifest absurdity and incoherence. Nature, Darwinian or other, is rendered absurd by implanting in us the useless illusion of purpose, circumscribed freedom, and moral responsibility for no reason. Moreover, the philosophic materialists undercut their own rational argument by denying all efficacy to mind and thought (their "epiphenominalist" thesis of mind having no causal and thus real significance). Why, Jonas asks, should we follow materialists who self-cancel their own authority? In a philosophic countermove similar to Whitehead's, Jonas denies that materialist science needs to turn philosophical and metaphysical and interpret reality according to its own partial and abstract conceptual scheme. This humanly characteristic blunder is what Whitehead (1969) termed "the fallacy of misplaced concreteness" taking the abstract or partial aspects of things for concrete reality, the fullness of things. Jonas claimed that materialist science should confine itself to pursuing objective, empirically verifiable, "causal" knowledge, which is not all we know or understand about ourselves and the world, especially the efficacy or reality of freedom and responsibility. Such intellectual circumspection or modesty gives Jonas the speculative philosophic opportunity to return to everyday experience, move (like Whitehead) beyond inherited modes of materialism and idealism, and systematically explore the "nature purposive" that is manifest in all organic, evolutionary life, including that of animals and humans. Jonas conceives that animals and humans are psychophysical individuals with common but varied forms of organic identity and living capacities (Donnelley 1995). All genuine instances of organic (especially animal) life enjoy some form of self-feeling, selfhood, "needful freedom," and active commerce with the world. All have an important value and significance for themselves, and perhaps also for others. These fundamental features of organic life are engendered and necessitated by organisms' metabolic mode of existence, their active use of the "energetic" world to be their bodily selves and to maintain their precarious mode of existence. Metabolic and organic needs and capacities link humans and animals in a single world of significant activity and achievement, with the primary goal of being (organically existing) versus not being. This primordial existential and purposive endeavor "to be," shared by humans and animals, is the ultimate concrete value of reality that serves as the ground of value and the "good in itself and needs no other justification than our emphatic recognition. We humans have ultimate ethical responsibilities to uphold nature purposive this intrinsically valuable good in itself (especially purposive human nature) with its extraordinary moral, philosophic, and spiritual dimensions. These fundamental moral responsibilities are challenged by burgeoning modern scientific and technological societies, which take little long-term heed of nature purposive. Final Reflections The foregoing brief sketches of three different but important philosophies may help us to understand why we and animals philosophically and morally matter together. These Darwinian, naturalist, organicist perspectives place laboratory animal research and its supporters in an interesting moral situation. Neither Leopold, Whitehead, nor Jonas opposes the use of animals for morally legitimate human purposes, including (presumably) scientific research. Indeed, a Darwinian evolutionary and ecological nature lends powerful support for legitimate scientific uses of animals. Life must use itself to be and to realize its various values and goodness. Metabolic and organic rules govern our worldly realm. "Good" and "evil" (harm) are intractably entwined. Yet we and animals are also inextricably bound together physically, subjectively or experientially, and morally. These three philosophers of organic nature provide us with clues to understanding why either humans and animals are, taken together, morally significant, or neither humans nor animals have any significance (the nihilistic implication of materialism and determinism). If we want to argue that laboratory animal research, which produces advances in human knowledge and benefits to both humans and animals, is a moral enterprise, then assuming we wish to live morally coherent lives we must treat laboratory animals with genuine concern, care, and respect. In short, by philosophically coming to appreciate that humans, animals, and nature are intricately interwoven in a single morally (as well as aesthetically and religiously) significant reality, we can begin to see the outlines of an overall moral outlook or perspective that comprehends or includes humans, animals, and nature (all morally matter and matter together). The task then becomes to judge and coordinate our relative obligations to humans, animals, nature, and their worldly future within this overall framework of moral thought (Donnelley 1995). In any case, we have no good reason to slip into cynical moral nihilism, to fall into the fallacy of misplaced concreteness, and to forget humans' and animals' common origin, togetherness, and significance in evolutionary, ecological nature. Holistic reflection about our interrelatedness with Volume 40, Number

7 each other, with animals, and with nature is, understandably, absent from many of our somewhat provincial laboratory settings. Nevertheless, if we are to live morally coherent lives, we need a robust philosophy that persuasively interprets the dynamic whole in which humans, animals, and nature exist and interact. References Donnelley S Bioethical troubles: Animal individuals and human organisms. The Hastings Center Report 25: Donnelley S, Nolan K, editors. Animals, science, and ethics. The Hastings Center Report (Spec Suppl) 21:1-32. Jonas H The Imperative of Responsibility. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Also Donnelley S Hans Jonas, the philosophy of nature, and the ethics of responsibility. Soc Res 56: Leopold A Thinking like a mountain. In: A Sand County Almanac. New York: Oxford University Press, p MayrE One Long Argument. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press. MidgleyM Animals and Why They Matter. Athens GA: University of Georgia Press. NRC [National Research Council] Education and Care in the Care and Use of Laboratory Animals: A Guide for Developing Research Programs. Washington DC: National Academy Press. WhiteheadAN Modes of Thought. New York: The Free Press. Whitehead AN Science and the Modern World. New York: The Free Press, p WAR Journal

A S AND C OUNTY A LMANAC

A S AND C OUNTY A LMANAC Discussion Guide for A S AND C OUNTY A LMANAC by Aldo Leopold 1968 Oxford University Press, paperback In 1935, pioneering wildlife manager Aldo Leopold purchased a worn-out farm on the Wisconsin River

More information

Another Look at Leopold. Aldo Leopold, being one of the foremost important figures in the science of natural

Another Look at Leopold. Aldo Leopold, being one of the foremost important figures in the science of natural Another Look at Leopold Aldo Leopold, being one of the foremost important figures in the science of natural resources, has been evaluated and scrutinized by scholars and the general population alike. Leopold

More information

Science and Values: Holism and Radical Environmental Activism

Science and Values: Holism and Radical Environmental Activism Science and Values: Holism and Radical Environmental Activism James Sage [ jsage@uwsp.edu ] Department of Philosophy University of Wisconsin Stevens Point Science and Values: Holism & REA This presentation

More information

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

The Shimer School Core Curriculum Basic Core Studies The Shimer School Core Curriculum Humanities 111 Fundamental Concepts of Art and Music Humanities 112 Literature in the Ancient World Humanities 113 Literature in the Modern World Social

More information

J.S. Mill s Notion of Qualitative Superiority of Pleasure: A Reappraisal

J.S. Mill s Notion of Qualitative Superiority of Pleasure: A Reappraisal J.S. Mill s Notion of Qualitative Superiority of Pleasure: A Reappraisal Madhumita Mitra, Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy Vidyasagar College, Calcutta University, Kolkata, India Abstract

More information

Part 1: A Summary of the Land Ethic

Part 1: A Summary of the Land Ethic Part 1: A Summary of the Land Ethic For the purpose of this paper, I have been asked to read and summarize The Land Ethic by Aldo Leopold. In the paragraphs that follow, I will attempt to briefly summarize

More information

Environmental Ethics and Species: To be or not to be?

Environmental Ethics and Species: To be or not to be? Environmental Ethics and Species: To be or not to be? Darren L. Weber Copyright c 1993 Written in November, 1993 Philosophy: Environmental Ethics Environmental Ethics and Species 1 1 Environmental Ethics

More information

The Moral Animal. By Robert Wright. Vintage Books, Reviewed by Geoff Gilpin

The Moral Animal. By Robert Wright. Vintage Books, Reviewed by Geoff Gilpin The Moral Animal By Robert Wright Vintage Books, 1995 Reviewed by Geoff Gilpin Long before he published The Origin of Species, Charles Darwin was well acquainted with objections to the theory of evolution.

More information

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 7, no. 2, 2011 REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY Karin de Boer Angelica Nuzzo, Ideal Embodiment: Kant

More information

Environmental Ethics: From Theory to Practice

Environmental Ethics: From Theory to Practice Environmental Ethics: From Theory to Practice Marion Hourdequin Companion Website Material Chapter 1 Companion website by Julia Liao and Marion Hourdequin ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS: FROM THEORY TO PRACTICE

More information

THE EVOLUTIONARY VIEW OF SCIENTIFIC PROGRESS Dragoş Bîgu dragos_bigu@yahoo.com Abstract: In this article I have examined how Kuhn uses the evolutionary analogy to analyze the problem of scientific progress.

More information

PHIL 314 Varner 2018a Midterm exam Page 1 Filename = EXAM-1 - PRINTED - KEY.wpd

PHIL 314 Varner 2018a Midterm exam Page 1 Filename = EXAM-1 - PRINTED - KEY.wpd PHIL 314 Varner 2018a Midterm exam Page 1 Your FIRST name: Your LAST name: Part one (multiple choice, worth 15% of course grade): Indicate the best answer to each question on your Scantron by filling in

More information

In Search of Mechanisms, by Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden, 2013, The University of Chicago Press.

In Search of Mechanisms, by Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden, 2013, The University of Chicago Press. In Search of Mechanisms, by Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden, 2013, The University of Chicago Press. The voluminous writing on mechanisms of the past decade or two has focused on explanation and causation.

More information

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS) KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS) Both the natural and the social sciences posit taxonomies or classification schemes that divide their objects of study into various categories. Many philosophers hold

More information

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008. Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008. Reviewed by Christopher Pincock, Purdue University (pincock@purdue.edu) June 11, 2010 2556 words

More information

Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2d ed. transl. by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (London : Sheed & Ward, 1989), pp [1960].

Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2d ed. transl. by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (London : Sheed & Ward, 1989), pp [1960]. Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2d ed. transl. by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (London : Sheed & Ward, 1989), pp. 266-307 [1960]. 266 : [W]e can inquire into the consequences for the hermeneutics

More information

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values Book Review Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values Nate Jackson Hugh P. McDonald, Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values. New York: Rodopi, 2011. xxvi + 361 pages. ISBN 978-90-420-3253-8.

More information

Harris Wiseman, The Myth of the Moral Brain: The Limits of Moral Enhancement (Cambridge, MA and London: The MIT Press, 2016), 340 pp.

Harris Wiseman, The Myth of the Moral Brain: The Limits of Moral Enhancement (Cambridge, MA and London: The MIT Press, 2016), 340 pp. 227 Harris Wiseman, The Myth of the Moral Brain: The Limits of Moral Enhancement (Cambridge, MA and London: The MIT Press, 2016), 340 pp. The aspiration for understanding the nature of morality and promoting

More information

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis Keisuke Noda Ph.D. Associate Professor of Philosophy Unification Theological Seminary New York, USA Abstract This essay gives a preparatory

More information

The Experience of God: Being, Consciousness, Bliss Part II of II

The Experience of God: Being, Consciousness, Bliss Part II of II The Experience of God: Being, Consciousness, Bliss Part II of II From the book by David Bentley Hart W. Bruce Phillips Wonder & Innocence Wisdom is the recovery of wonder at the end of experience. The

More information

Objectives: Performance Objective: By the end of this session, the participants will be able to discuss the weaknesses of various theories that suppor

Objectives: Performance Objective: By the end of this session, the participants will be able to discuss the weaknesses of various theories that suppor Science versus Peace? Deconstructing Adversarial Theory Objectives: Performance Objective: By the end of this session, the participants will be able to discuss the weaknesses of various theories that support

More information

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki 1 The Polish Peasant in Europe and America W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki Now there are two fundamental practical problems which have constituted the center of attention of reflective social practice

More information

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART Tatyana Shopova Associate Professor PhD Head of the Center for New Media and Digital Culture Department of Cultural Studies, Faculty of Arts South-West University

More information

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT This article observes methodological aspects of conflict-contractual theory

More information

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy 1 Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy Politics is older than philosophy. According to Olof Gigon in Ancient Greece philosophy was born in opposition to the politics (and the

More information

Albert Borgmann, Holding on to Reality: The Nature of Information at the Turn of the Millennium, University of Chicago Press, 2000.

Albert Borgmann, Holding on to Reality: The Nature of Information at the Turn of the Millennium, University of Chicago Press, 2000. Techné 6:1 Fall 2002 Fernandez, Information and Ersatz Reality / 10 Information and Ersatz Reality: Comments on Albert Borgmann s Holding On to Reality Eliseo Fernandez Linda Hall Library Albert Borgmann,

More information

Lecture 04, 01 Sept Conservation Biology ECOL 406R/506R University of Arizona Fall Kevin Bonine Kathy Gerst

Lecture 04, 01 Sept Conservation Biology ECOL 406R/506R University of Arizona Fall Kevin Bonine Kathy Gerst Lecture 04, 01 Sept 2005 Conservation Biology ECOL 406R/506R University of Arizona Fall 2005 Kevin Bonine Kathy Gerst 1 Conservation Biology 406R/506R 1. Ethics and Philosophy, What is Conservation Biology

More information

Deep Ecology A New Paradigm 19 September 2012 Page 1 of 6

Deep Ecology A New Paradigm 19 September 2012 Page 1 of 6 Deep Ecology - A New Paradigm This book is about a new scientific understanding of life at all levels of living systems - organisms, social systems, and ecosystems. It is based on a new perception of reality

More information

The Concept of Nature

The Concept of Nature The Concept of Nature The Concept of Nature The Tarner Lectures Delivered in Trinity College B alfred north whitehead University Printing House, Cambridge CB2 8BS, United Kingdom Cambridge University

More information

Loggerhead Sea Turtle

Loggerhead Sea Turtle Loggerhead Sea Turtle Introduction The Demonic Effect of a Fully Developed Idea Over the past twenty years, a central point of exploration for CAE has been revolutions and crises related to the environment,

More information

8/28/2008. An instance of great change or alteration in affairs or in some particular thing. (1450)

8/28/2008. An instance of great change or alteration in affairs or in some particular thing. (1450) 1 The action or fact, on the part of celestial bodies, of moving round in an orbit (1390) An instance of great change or alteration in affairs or in some particular thing. (1450) The return or recurrence

More information

The Spell of the Sensuous Chapter Summaries 1-4 Breakthrough Intensive 2016/2017

The Spell of the Sensuous Chapter Summaries 1-4 Breakthrough Intensive 2016/2017 The Spell of the Sensuous Chapter Summaries 1-4 Breakthrough Intensive 2016/2017 Chapter 1: The Ecology of Magic In the first chapter of The Spell of the Sensuous David Abram sets the context of his thesis.

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 26 Lecture - 26 Karl Marx Historical Materialism

More information

Mainstream Eco Tourism: Are we pushing the right buttons? Insights from Environmental Ethics

Mainstream Eco Tourism: Are we pushing the right buttons? Insights from Environmental Ethics Mainstream Eco Tourism: Are we pushing the right buttons? Insights from Environmental Ethics Global Eco: Asia-Pacific Tourism Conference Adelaide, South Australia 27-29 November 2017 Dr Noreen Breakey

More information

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics REVIEW A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics Kristin Gjesdal: Gadamer and the Legacy of German Idealism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009. xvii + 235 pp. ISBN 978-0-521-50964-0

More information

3. The knower s perspective is essential in the pursuit of knowledge. To what extent do you agree?

3. The knower s perspective is essential in the pursuit of knowledge. To what extent do you agree? 3. The knower s perspective is essential in the pursuit of knowledge. To what extent do you agree? Nature of the Title The essay requires several key terms to be unpacked. However, the most important is

More information

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave. Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave. The Republic is intended by Plato to answer two questions: (1) What IS justice? and (2) Is it better to

More information

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education The refereed journal of the Volume 9, No. 1 January 2010 Wayne Bowman Editor Electronic Article Shusterman, Merleau-Ponty, and Dewey: The Role of Pragmatism

More information

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192 Croatian Journal of Philosophy Vol. XV, No. 44, 2015 Book Review Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192 Philip Kitcher

More information

Review by Răzvan CÎMPEAN

Review by Răzvan CÎMPEAN Mihai I. SPĂRIOSU, Global Intelligence and Human Development: Towards an Ecology of Global Learning (Cambridge MA: MIT Press, 2004), 287 pp., ISBN 0-262-69316-X Review by Răzvan CÎMPEAN Babeș-Bolyai University,

More information

2 Unified Reality Theory

2 Unified Reality Theory INTRODUCTION In 1859, Charles Darwin published a book titled On the Origin of Species. In that book, Darwin proposed a theory of natural selection or survival of the fittest to explain how organisms evolve

More information

Homo Ecologicus and Homo Economicus

Homo Ecologicus and Homo Economicus 1: Ho m o Ec o l o g i c u s, Ho m o Ec o n o m i c u s, Ho m o Po e t i c u s Homo Ecologicus and Homo Economicus Ecology: the science of the economy of animals and plants. Oxford English Dictionary Ecological

More information

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn The social mechanisms approach to explanation (SM) has

More information

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture Hans Jakob Roth Nomos 2012 223 pages [@] Rating 8 Applicability 9 Innovation 87 Style Focus Leadership & Management Strategy Sales & Marketing Finance

More information

ALIGNING WITH THE GOOD

ALIGNING WITH THE GOOD DISCUSSION NOTE BY BENJAMIN MITCHELL-YELLIN JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE JULY 2015 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT BENJAMIN MITCHELL-YELLIN 2015 Aligning with the Good I N CONSTRUCTIVISM,

More information

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education Marilyn Zurmuehlen Working Papers in Art Education ISSN: 2326-7070 (Print) ISSN: 2326-7062 (Online) Volume 2 Issue 1 (1983) pps. 56-60 Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

More information

Existential Cause & Individual Experience

Existential Cause & Individual Experience Existential Cause & Individual Experience 226 Article Steven E. Kaufman * ABSTRACT The idea that what we experience as physical-material reality is what's actually there is the flat Earth idea of our time.

More information

Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015):

Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015): Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015): 224 228. Philosophy of Microbiology MAUREEN A. O MALLEY Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2014 x + 269 pp., ISBN 9781107024250,

More information

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective DAVID T. LARSON University of Kansas Kant suggests that his contribution to philosophy is analogous to the contribution of Copernicus to astronomy each involves

More information

Kuhn and the Structure of Scientific Revolutions. How does one describe the process of science as a human endeavor? How does an

Kuhn and the Structure of Scientific Revolutions. How does one describe the process of science as a human endeavor? How does an Saket Vora HI 322 Dr. Kimler 11/28/2006 Kuhn and the Structure of Scientific Revolutions How does one describe the process of science as a human endeavor? How does an account of the natural world become

More information

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)? Kant s Critique of Judgment 1 Critique of judgment Kant s Critique of Judgment (1790) generally regarded as foundational treatise in modern philosophical aesthetics no integration of aesthetic theory into

More information

body Salk Institute Louis I. Kahn

body Salk Institute Louis I. Kahn body Salk Institute Louis I. Kahn Andrew Pun EVDA 621 November 1, 2011 Meeting Place Laboratories Pacific Ocean Oxygen scholars collaboration analyzing innovating originality new brilliance thinking inspiration

More information

The Rhetorical Modes Schemes and Patterns for Papers

The Rhetorical Modes Schemes and Patterns for Papers K. Hope Rhetorical Modes 1 The Rhetorical Modes Schemes and Patterns for Papers Argument In this class, the basic mode of writing is argument, meaning that your papers will rehearse or play out one idea

More information

(as methodology) are not always distinguished by Steward: he says,

(as methodology) are not always distinguished by Steward: he says, SOME MISCONCEPTIONS OF MULTILINEAR EVOLUTION1 William C. Smith It is the object of this paper to consider certain conceptual difficulties in Julian Steward's theory of multillnear evolution. The particular

More information

APPEARANCE IN TIME: WHITEHEAD AND VON UEXKÜLL ON AISTHĒSIS

APPEARANCE IN TIME: WHITEHEAD AND VON UEXKÜLL ON AISTHĒSIS APPEARANCE IN TIME: WHITEHEAD AND VON UEXKÜLL ON AISTHĒSIS IN EVOLUTIONARY PROCESS ADAM ROBBERT SAN FRANCISCO, CA PAPER GIVEN AT THE 10TH INTERNATIONAL WHITEHEAD CONFERENCE, JUNE 6, 2015, CLAREMONT, CA

More information

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience Introduction Naïve realism regards the sensory experiences that subjects enjoy when perceiving (hereafter perceptual experiences) as being, in some

More information

Confronting the Absurd in Notes from Underground. Camus The Myth of Sisyphus discusses the possibility of living in a world full of

Confronting the Absurd in Notes from Underground. Camus The Myth of Sisyphus discusses the possibility of living in a world full of Claire Deininger PHIL 4305.501 Dr. Amato Confronting the Absurd in Notes from Underground Camus The Myth of Sisyphus discusses the possibility of living in a world full of absurdities and the ways in which

More information

Aristotle. Aristotle. Aristotle and Plato. Background. Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle and Plato

Aristotle. Aristotle. Aristotle and Plato. Background. Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle and Plato Aristotle Aristotle Lived 384-323 BC. He was a student of Plato. Was the tutor of Alexander the Great. Founded his own school: The Lyceum. He wrote treatises on physics, cosmology, biology, psychology,

More information

The Doctrine of the Mean

The Doctrine of the Mean The Doctrine of the Mean In subunit 1.6, you learned that Aristotle s highest end for human beings is eudaimonia, or well-being, which is constituted by a life of action by the part of the soul that has

More information

Phenomenology Glossary

Phenomenology Glossary Phenomenology Glossary Phenomenology: Phenomenology is the science of phenomena: of the way things show up, appear, or are given to a subject in their conscious experience. Phenomenology tries to describe

More information

GV958: Theory and Explanation in Political Science, Part I: Philosophy of Science (Han Dorussen)

GV958: Theory and Explanation in Political Science, Part I: Philosophy of Science (Han Dorussen) GV958: Theory and Explanation in Political Science, Part I: Philosophy of Science (Han Dorussen) Week 3: The Science of Politics 1. Introduction 2. Philosophy of Science 3. (Political) Science 4. Theory

More information

Mary Evelyn Tucker. In our search for more comprehensive and global ethics to meet the critical challenges of our

Mary Evelyn Tucker. In our search for more comprehensive and global ethics to meet the critical challenges of our CONFUCIAN COSMOLOGY and ECOLOGICAL ETHICS: QI, LI, and the ROLE of the HUMAN Mary Evelyn Tucker In our search for more comprehensive and global ethics to meet the critical challenges of our contemporary

More information

7. This composition is an infinite configuration, which, in our own contemporary artistic context, is a generic totality.

7. This composition is an infinite configuration, which, in our own contemporary artistic context, is a generic totality. Fifteen theses on contemporary art Alain Badiou 1. Art is not the sublime descent of the infinite into the finite abjection of the body and sexuality. It is the production of an infinite subjective series

More information

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD Unit Code: Unit Name: Department: Faculty: 475Z022 METAPHYSICS (INBOUND STUDENT MOBILITY - JAN ENTRY) Politics & Philosophy Faculty Of Arts & Humanities Level: 5 Credits: 5 ECTS: 7.5 This unit will address

More information

The Teaching Method of Creative Education

The Teaching Method of Creative Education Creative Education 2013. Vol.4, No.8A, 25-30 Published Online August 2013 in SciRes (http://www.scirp.org/journal/ce) http://dx.doi.org/10.4236/ce.2013.48a006 The Teaching Method of Creative Education

More information

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers Cast of Characters X-Phi: Experimental Philosophy E-Phi: Empirical Philosophy A-Phi: Armchair Philosophy Challenges to Experimental Philosophy Empirical

More information

Before doing so, Read and heed the following essay full of good advice.

Before doing so, Read and heed the following essay full of good advice. Class Meeting 2 Themes: Human Systems: Levels and aspects of organization and development in human systems: from the level of molecules and cells and tissues and organs and organ systems and organisms

More information

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile Web: www.kailashkut.com RESEARCH METHODOLOGY E- mail srtiwari@ioe.edu.np Mobile 9851065633 Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is What is Paradigm? Definition, Concept, the Paradigm Shift? Main Components

More information

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article Reading across Borders: Storytelling and Knowledges of Resistance (review) Susan E. Babbitt Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp. 203-206 (Review) Published by Indiana University Press DOI: 10.1353/hyp.2006.0018

More information

Japan Library Association

Japan Library Association 1 of 5 Japan Library Association -- http://wwwsoc.nacsis.ac.jp/jla/ -- Approved at the Annual General Conference of the Japan Library Association June 4, 1980 Translated by Research Committee On the Problems

More information

Unified Reality Theory in a Nutshell

Unified Reality Theory in a Nutshell Unified Reality Theory in a Nutshell 200 Article Steven E. Kaufman * ABSTRACT Unified Reality Theory describes how all reality evolves from an absolute existence. It also demonstrates that this absolute

More information

PROFESSORS: Bonnie B. Bowers (chair), George W. Ledger ASSOCIATE PROFESSORS: Richard L. Michalski (on leave short & spring terms), Tiffany A.

PROFESSORS: Bonnie B. Bowers (chair), George W. Ledger ASSOCIATE PROFESSORS: Richard L. Michalski (on leave short & spring terms), Tiffany A. Psychology MAJOR, MINOR PROFESSORS: Bonnie B. (chair), George W. ASSOCIATE PROFESSORS: Richard L. (on leave short & spring terms), Tiffany A. The core program in psychology emphasizes the learning of representative

More information

Chapter Six Integral Spirituality

Chapter Six Integral Spirituality The following is excerpted from the forthcoming book: Integral Consciousness and the Future of Evolution, by Steve McIntosh; due to be published by Paragon House in September 2007. Steve McIntosh, all

More information

Beatty on Chance and Natural Selection

Beatty on Chance and Natural Selection Digital Commons@ Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School Philosophy Faculty Works Philosophy 9-1-1989 Beatty on Chance and Natural Selection Timothy Shanahan Loyola Marymount University, tshanahan@lmu.edu

More information

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN zlom 7.5.2009 8:12 Stránka 111 Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN 0826486320 Aesthetics and Architecture, by Edward Winters, a British aesthetician, painter,

More information

Moral Geography and Exploration of the Moral Possibility Space

Moral Geography and Exploration of the Moral Possibility Space Book Review/173 Moral Geography and Exploration of the Moral Possibility Space BONGRAE SEOK Alvernia University, Reading, Pennsylvania, USA (bongrae.seok@alvernia.edu) Owen Flanagan, The Geography of Morals,

More information

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November -2015 58 ETHICS FROM ARISTOTLE & PLATO & DEWEY PERSPECTIVE Mohmmad Allazzam International Journal of Advancements

More information

Culture and Art Criticism

Culture and Art Criticism Culture and Art Criticism Dr. Wagih Fawzi Youssef May 2013 Abstract This brief essay sheds new light on the practice of art criticism. Commencing by the definition of a work of art as contingent upon intuition,

More information

THE RELATIONS BETWEEN ETHICS AND ECONOMICS: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS BETWEEN AYRES AND WEBER S PERSPECTIVES. By Nuria Toledano and Crispen Karanda

THE RELATIONS BETWEEN ETHICS AND ECONOMICS: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS BETWEEN AYRES AND WEBER S PERSPECTIVES. By Nuria Toledano and Crispen Karanda PhilosophyforBusiness Issue80 11thFebruary2017 http://www.isfp.co.uk/businesspathways/ THE RELATIONS BETWEEN ETHICS AND ECONOMICS: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS BETWEEN AYRES AND WEBER S PERSPECTIVES By Nuria

More information

MAURICE MANDELBAUM HISTORY, MAN, & REASON A STUDY IN NINETEENTH-CENTURY THOUGHT THE JOHNS HOPKINS PRESS: BALTIMORE AND LONDON

MAURICE MANDELBAUM HISTORY, MAN, & REASON A STUDY IN NINETEENTH-CENTURY THOUGHT THE JOHNS HOPKINS PRESS: BALTIMORE AND LONDON MAURICE MANDELBAUM HISTORY, MAN, & REASON A STUDY IN NINETEENTH-CENTURY THOUGHT THE JOHNS HOPKINS PRESS: BALTIMORE AND LONDON Copyright 1971 by The Johns Hopkins Press All rights reserved Manufactured

More information

Whaplode (Church of England) Primary School Mill Lane, Whaplode, Spalding, Lincolnshire PE12 6TS. Phone:/Fax:

Whaplode (Church of England) Primary School Mill Lane, Whaplode, Spalding, Lincolnshire PE12 6TS. Phone:/Fax: Whaplode (Church of England) Primary School Mill Lane, Whaplode, Spalding, Lincolnshire PE12 6TS Phone:/Fax: 01406 370447 Executive Head Teacher: Mrs A Flack http://www.whaplodeprimary.co.uk Spirituality

More information

The Psychology of Justice

The Psychology of Justice DRAFT MANUSCRIPT: 3/31/06 To appear in Analyse & Kritik The Psychology of Justice A Review of Natural Justice by Kenneth Binmore Fiery Cushman 1, Liane Young 1 & Marc Hauser 1,2,3 Departments of 1 Psychology,

More information

6 The Analysis of Culture

6 The Analysis of Culture The Analysis of Culture 57 6 The Analysis of Culture Raymond Williams There are three general categories in the definition of culture. There is, first, the 'ideal', in which culture is a state or process

More information

Analysis of the Instrumental Function of Beauty in Wang Zhaowen s Beauty- Goodness-Relationship Theory

Analysis of the Instrumental Function of Beauty in Wang Zhaowen s Beauty- Goodness-Relationship Theory Canadian Social Science Vol. 12, No. 1, 2016, pp. 29-33 DOI:10.3968/7988 ISSN 1712-8056[Print] ISSN 1923-6697[Online] www.cscanada.net www.cscanada.org Analysis of the Instrumental Function of Beauty in

More information

observation and conceptual interpretation

observation and conceptual interpretation 1 observation and conceptual interpretation Most people will agree that observation and conceptual interpretation constitute two major ways through which human beings engage the world. Questions about

More information

Literary and non literary aspects

Literary and non literary aspects THE PLAYWRIGHT The playwright -most central and most peripheral figure in the theatrical event -provides point of origin for production (the script) -in earlier periods playwrights acted as directors -today

More information

SECTION I: MARX READINGS

SECTION I: MARX READINGS SECTION I: MARX READINGS part 1 Marx s Vision of History: Historical Materialism This part focuses on the broader conceptual framework, or overall view of history and human nature, that informed Marx

More information

Learning Approaches. What We Will Cover in This Section. Overview

Learning Approaches. What We Will Cover in This Section. Overview Learning Approaches 5/10/2003 PSY 305 Learning Approaches.ppt 1 What We Will Cover in This Section Overview Pavlov Skinner Miller and Dollard Bandura 5/10/2003 PSY 305 Learning Approaches.ppt 2 Overview

More information

Review of Bug Music: How Insects Gave Us Rhythm and Noise. David Rothenberg Picador pp., Paperback

Review of Bug Music: How Insects Gave Us Rhythm and Noise. David Rothenberg Picador pp., Paperback 159 Between the Species Review of Bug Music: How Insects Gave Us Rhythm and Noise David Rothenberg Picador 2014 278 pp., Paperback Jonathan L. Friedmann Academy for Jewish Religion California jfriedmann@ajrca.edu

More information

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content Book review of Schear, J. K. (ed.), Mind, Reason, and Being-in-the-World: The McDowell-Dreyfus Debate, Routledge, London-New York 2013, 350 pp. Corijn van Mazijk

More information

CAROL HUNTS University of Kansas

CAROL HUNTS University of Kansas Freedom as a Dialectical Expression of Rationality CAROL HUNTS University of Kansas I The concept of what we may noncommittally call forward movement has an all-pervasive significance in Hegel's philosophy.

More information

Juxtapositionalism: Meaning in Environmental Ethics. Sometimes it seems that philosophy is too, well, philosophical when we would rather it be

Juxtapositionalism: Meaning in Environmental Ethics. Sometimes it seems that philosophy is too, well, philosophical when we would rather it be Brett Wagner Jennifer Atkinson Environmental Ethics 14 March 2016 Juxtapositionalism: Meaning in Environmental Ethics Sometimes it seems that philosophy is too, well, philosophical when we would rather

More information

Objectivity and Diversity: Another Logic of Scientific Research Sandra Harding University of Chicago Press, pp.

Objectivity and Diversity: Another Logic of Scientific Research Sandra Harding University of Chicago Press, pp. Review of Sandra Harding s Objectivity and Diversity: Another Logic of Scientific Research Kamili Posey, Kingsborough Community College, CUNY; María G. Navarro, Spanish National Research Council Objectivity

More information

Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology

Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology We now briefly look at the views of Thomas S. Kuhn whose magnum opus, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962), constitutes a turning point in the twentiethcentury philosophy

More information

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation Cogent Science in Context: The Science Wars, Argumentation Theory, and Habermas. By William Rehg. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2009. Pp. 355. Cloth, $40. Paper, $20. Jeffrey Flynn Fordham University Published

More information

WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS

WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS AN INTRODUCTION TO HIS THOUGHT by WOLFE MAYS II MARTINUS NIJHOFF / THE HAGUE / 1977 FOR LAURENCE 1977

More information

Capstone Design Project Sample

Capstone Design Project Sample The design theory cannot be understood, and even less defined, as a certain scientific theory. In terms of the theory that has a precise conceptual appliance that interprets the legality of certain natural

More information

Essay on evolution of man as a tool making animal

Essay on evolution of man as a tool making animal Essay on evolution of man as a tool making animal What are essay transitions in essays examples transition words and phrases? Essay on evolution of man as a tool making animal Air pollution research. You

More information

A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique of Pure Reason for Describing Epistemological Trends in IS

A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique of Pure Reason for Describing Epistemological Trends in IS Association for Information Systems AIS Electronic Library (AISeL) AMCIS 2003 Proceedings Americas Conference on Information Systems (AMCIS) December 2003 A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique

More information

Challenging Times. Introduction. Evolution of Galilean Newtonian Scientific Thinking

Challenging Times. Introduction. Evolution of Galilean Newtonian Scientific Thinking Introduction Challenging Times Evolution of Galilean Newtonian Scientific Thinking Some people are sufficiently fortunate to have their most creative years coincide with great mysteries in human knowledge.

More information