Glasgow eprints Service

Similar documents
PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Hegel's Absolute: An Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

NATURE FROM WITHIN. Gustav Theodor Fechner and His Psychophysical. Michael Heidelberger. Translated by Cynthia Klohr. University of Pittsburgh Press

Frederick Burwick and James C. McKusick, eds. Faustus. From the German of Goethe.

Humanities Learning Outcomes

Hear hear. Århus, 11 January An acoustemological manifesto

6 The Analysis of Culture

Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive understanding.

Any attempt to revitalize the relationship between rhetoric and ethics is challenged

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

None DEREE COLLEGE SYLLABUS FOR: PH 4028 KANT AND GERMAN IDEALISM UK LEVEL 6 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3. (Updated SPRING 2016) PREREQUISITES:

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

CONRAD AND IMPRESSIONISM JOHN G. PETERS

English/Philosophy Department ENG/PHL 100 Level Course Descriptions and Learning Outcomes

Kuhn and coherentist epistemology

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

Research Projects on Rudolf Steiner'sWorldview

Culture and Art Criticism

Copyright Nikolaos Bogiatzis 1. Athenaeum Fragment 116. Romantic poetry is a progressive, universal poetry. Its aim isn t merely to reunite all the

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Major Philosophers II, 460, 3 credits; CRN 3068 Topic for the 2012 Winter Term: Philosophy, Hegel s Phenomenology of Spirit

The Observer Story: Heinz von Foerster s Heritage. Siegfried J. Schmidt 1. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2011

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

CAROL HUNTS University of Kansas

Misc Fiction Irony Point of view Plot time place social environment

Humanities 4: Lecture 19. Friedrich Schiller: On the Aesthetic Education of Man

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

AP English Literature 1999 Scoring Guidelines

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

observation and conceptual interpretation

Comparing Neo-Aristotelian, Close Textual Analysis, and Genre Criticism

Four Characteristic Research Paradigms

[T]here is a social definition of culture, in which culture is a description of a particular way of life. (Williams, The analysis of culture )

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

M E M O. When the book is published, the University of Guelph will be acknowledged for their support (in the acknowledgements section of the book).

Subjective Universality in Kant s Aesthetics Wilson

MAURICE MANDELBAUM HISTORY, MAN, & REASON A STUDY IN NINETEENTH-CENTURY THOUGHT THE JOHNS HOPKINS PRESS: BALTIMORE AND LONDON

Art, beauty and the Divine

Hegel and the French Revolution

The Romantic Age: historical background

Emerging Questions: Fernando F. Segovia and the Challenges of Cultural Interpretation

Self-Consciousness and Music in the Late Enlightenment

The art and study of using language effectively

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Philosophy Pathways Issue th December 2016

Environmental Ethics: From Theory to Practice

Challenging the View That Science is Value Free

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK

TRAGIC THOUGHTS AT THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

American Society The Social System The Social System Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature The Sociological Imagination

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

ARCHITECTURE AND EDUCATION: THE QUESTION OF EXPERTISE AND THE CHALLENGE OF ART

Notes on Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

Tradition and the Individual Poem: An Inquiry into Anthologies (review)

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

Student Performance Q&A:

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Georg Simmel and Formal Sociology

The Doctrine of the Mean

Marxism and. Literature RAYMOND WILLIAMS. Oxford New York OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS

De esthetische revolutie: Ontstaan en ontwikkeling van het moderne kunstbegrip in Verlichting en Romantiek Heumakers, A.J.A.

Texas Southern University. From the SelectedWorks of Anthony M Rodriguez Ph.D. Michael A Rodriguez, Ph.D., Texas Southern University

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF. the oxford handbook of WORLD PHILOSOPHY. GARFIELD-Halftitle2-Page Proof 1 August 10, :24 PM

NMSI English Mock Exam Lesson Poetry Analysis 2013

Book Reviews: 'The Concept of Nature in Marx', & 'Alienation - Marx s Conception of Man in Capitalist Society'

PH th Century Philosophy Ryerson University Department of Philosophy Mondays, 3-6pm Fall 2010

Georg Simmel's Sociology of Individuality

COPYRIGHT 2009 ASSOCIAZIONE PRAGMA

AESTHETICS. Key Terms

::::::::::::: lit::::::

Royce: The Anthropology of Dance

Review of Hume, Hegel and Human Nature. Hume Studies Volume IX, Number 2 (November, 1983) H. S. Harris

Lisa Randall, a professor of physics at Harvard, is the author of "Warped Passages: Unraveling the Mysteries of the Universe's Hidden Dimensions.

PH 360 CROSS-CULTURAL PHILOSOPHY IES Abroad Vienna

What have we done with the bodies? Bodyliness in drama education research

Film-Philosophy

Language & Literature Comparative Commentary

AP Literature and Composition

Anna Carabelli. Anna Carabelli. Università del Piemonte Orientale, Italy 1

Thomas Szanto: Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes

Introduction: Mills today

Durham Research Online

Kant s Critique of Judgment

J D H L S Journal of D. H. Lawrence Studies

Part II. Rational Theories of Leisure. Karl Spracklen

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

HEGEL S CONCEPT OF ACTION

Transcription:

Stephenson, R. (2002) Review of Nicholas Boyle, Goethe: the poet and the age, vol. 2: Revolution and renunciation (1790-1803). Modern Language Review 97:pp. 484-487. http://eprints.gla.ac.uk/3306/ Glasgow eprints Service http://eprints.gla.ac.uk

Goethe: The Poet and the Age. Vol. ii: Revolution and Renunciation (1790 1803). By Nicholas Boyle. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2000. xiv+949 pp. 30. Readers who enjoyed the first volume of Nicholas Boyle s biography (The Poetry of Desire (1749 1790), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991) will not be disappointed by the second. Here, too, one finds a wealth of fascinating detail represented with a raconteur s mastery of vivid evocation and dramatic, telling phraseology. The thesis announced in the sub-title is set firmly in the real world, both private and public, in which Goethe found himself on his return from his second (1790) Italian journey: faced with the challenge of the French Revolution to the world-order in which he had grown to maturity, Goethe learned, painfully and slowly, to re-commit himself to his German bourgeois public, spurred on by his openness to the German Revolution (pp. 66, 73) initiated by the post-kantian Idealism that came to replace the Leibnizianism which had hitherto dominated German intellectual life. Boyle argues that the thwarting of Goethe s hopes for a third trip to Italy in 1796 97 symbolized the failure not only of the cultural (and personal) ambitions with which he had returned from Italy in 1788 but also of the ideals that animated his collaboration with Schiller on Die Horen. Goethe s Entsagung of courtly aestheticism in favour of a compromise with the kind of middle-class realism popular with his contemporary German audience, embodied in his growing acceptance of his de facto marriage to Christiane, eventually took him beyond Schiller (p. 569). In making his case (neatly summarized on pp. 323 24) Boyle provides a marvellously succinct account of the events, in France and Germany alike, that followed 1789. Against this backdrop, his masterly exposition of the main points of Kant s, Fichte s, Schelling s, and the young Hegel s thought is enormously helpful in placing Goethe in the intellectual atmosphere of his middle age (p. vii). Boyle s readings of Goethe s own writing are as lively and provocative in this second volume as in the first; naturally, not everyone will be able to agree with his interpretations, but few will not be grateful for the trenchant clarity with which he sets them forth. His interpretations of, for example, Hermann und Dorothea (pp. 518 32) and Die natürliche Tochter (on which, as ever, he writes brilliantly, on pp. 772 94) hold out the promise of fruitful scholarly disagreement. Equally productive in their expositional clarity are his reflections on the (aesthetic) meaning for Goethe of colour (p. 102); on the insistently recurrent theme of Goethe s marriage, in Life and Works, in the spirit of Anthony Burgess definition of marriage as a little civilization (pp. 150, 457); and on Goethe s ultimately resilient creativity (p. 200). Those who have read the first volume will find in the second the same weaknesses that I criticized in my review of the former (British Journal for Eighteenth-Century Studies, 18 (1995), 241 42), namely a lack of engagement with current scholarship and an undue emphasis on historicist contextualization. The discussion of Goethe s science would, for instance, have benefited from coming to terms with works published after 1978 (the date of George Wells Goethe and the Development of Science, the most recent item cited on the topic in the bibliography), some of it by reputable scientists highlighting Goethe s methodological sophistication. Frederick Burwick s Damnation of Newton: Colour Theory and Romantic Perception (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1986), like Karl G. Fink s Goethe s History of Science (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), would, surely, have gone a long way to modifying Boyle s opinion that Goethe s realistic objective phase in the 1790s was a repression of theoretical reflexion; to suppose Goethe s realistischer Tic to be anything more than a temporary subordination of one pole of the complementarity of Idea and Experience is, in the light of more recent scholarship than that on which Boyle typically relies,

as implausible as ascribing a complete failure of self-understanding (p. 87) to a Goethe who (in a diary entry of 26 March 1780) set himself the daily task of observing the circle that turns within me. So keen is Boyle to present Goethe as a man of his time that he seems to forget that Goethe had claimed to live in 10,000 years, had recommended an historical perspective of 3,000 years as the minimum for proper cultural awareness (HA, ii. 49), shared with Schiller the view that human greatness transcends time and space (pp. 228 29), and thus did not see his own destiny as necessarily implicated in what Boyle reifies as the German future (p. 91). The wisdom of the ages (pp. 107, 636) was, from early on (witness Urfaust), of living relevance to Goethe. Boyle s tendency to rigid, indeed hermetic, periodization tends not just to overlook the relevance of this long perspective, but also to obscure the continuities in Goethe s own life and intellectual development: the Entsagung, for instance, that Goethe expressed in Wilhelm Meister is already present in the achingly sad last lines of Willkommen und Abschied ; and the fact that he only reluctantly renounced in his own life what he could not possibly avoid giving up without losing something else yet more valuable (pp. 437, 563) is entirely consonant with what, since the Stoics, distinguishes renunciation from mere resignation. The novelty Boyle ascribes to Goethe s conceptualization in 1792 of polarity likewise ignores the presence of the concept, if not the term, in such early Sturm und Drang imagery as wanderer and hut or light and dark, as David Wellbery has shown. Indeed, the pervasive use, repeatedly punctuating the text, of the rhetoric of a new epoch in Goethe s life and thought (designating limited initiatives taken by Goethe on a regular basis) seems to owe more to Boyle s historicist compartmentalization of twoyear to three-year time periods, with its attendant blindness to continuity, than to the facts of the case. It is simply an exaggeration to say that by 1793 all the plans and certainties of Goethe s earlier life had foundered (p. 168) or that he had begun to reconstruct the whole building from the foundations (p. 175), just as no evidence is offered for the claim that the symbolische Pflanze, to which Goethe refers in Glückliches Ereignis, is entirely unrelated to the Urpflanze (pp. 837 38). Similarly, Goethe s new commitment to the contemporary reading public, which is emphasized over and over again (pp. 216, 252, 271, 305, 450, 607, 635), turns out, on Boyle s own account, to be neither new (but, rather, a would-be return to the relationship enjoyed in the 1770s) nor one of commitment (given Goethe s sceptical irony in respect of his public: pp. 292, 313); nor, again, did Goethe limit his readership to Germany but wrote for humanity (p. 546). Like a fly caught in amber, Goethe and, particularly, his works (above all, Faust, the tragedy of Goethe s own time, p. 688), seem trapped in the past. Similarly, commonplaces of the Western tradition are frequently assigned to contemporary sources, thus obscuring the traditions in which the thinkers to whom they are ascribed are participating: putting one s moral duty above any other consideration is not peculiarly Kantian (p. 319), but unites Kant with the Stoics and Aquinas, and citing Schelling s absolute Identity in the context of Faust s longing to transcend earthly conditions obscures the relevance of the long tradition of Platonic eros. The historicist tendency to assume that past events and situations cannot be understood in universal terms, while it may help illuminate the non-repeatable uniqueness of concrete objects, cannot possibly help clarify theory. For theory consists in the coherent co-ordination of concepts and its logical implications; it is, by definition, universalistic in its claims (a point Boyle explicitly concedes only in respect of Kant, on p. 51). Mere exposition of the constituent concepts employed is not sufficient; attention must also be given to their logical interaction. Although Boyle is eminently sensible in not making too much of the legendary first meeting

between Goethe and Schiller and their reported fundamental difference over the symbolic plant as an Idea or Experience (p. 223), and he is surely right to question Schiller s misleading characterization of [Goethe s] genius in the famous birthday-letter of 23 August 1794, the account that he gives of Schiller s cultural theorizing is deficient in several important respects: narrative for Schiller is not aesthetic, as is implied on p. 231, nor is freedom necessarily moral, let alone perfect, and the aesthetic only mediates between the dynamic state and the ethical state in its superordinate modality, a concept that Boyle never adduces (pp. 231 32) but which is essential for Goethe s theory of symbolism, which is, therefore, entirely compatible with Schiller s theory (see p. 546). Most crucially (not least for his own central argument), Boyle is wrong in his account of Schiller s idealism. Schiller does not share the post-kantian Idealist s faith in Geist, in the sense of a Reason to which Nature is to be subjugated (p. 65). It is true that the sense in which Kant is an Idealist, in holding that an Idee (a VernunftbegriV ) may regulate reality (p. 42), is also Schiller s, and Schiller also uses the word ideal, beyond the ordinary notion (of perfection), to mean having existence only as idea ; but, since on his theory, Art articulates Geist (as a synonym for Gehalt ) in the broad sense of the inner life ( das Innere ), Kunst des Ideals (Aesthetic Letters, ii. 3; xxvii. 1) is not perfect art, nor is it intellectual art (presenting a concept of reason), but art replete with significant import. It is this insistence that the content of art (Gehalt) is more than intellectual, even if its material (its Inhalt) is wholly or partly intellectual, that distinguishes Schiller s Idealism from that of Hölderlin, Wackenroder, and Friedrich Schlegel (p. 510), and from Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel, who all subordinate Art to Philosophy (and Religion). Moreover, Art is ideal for Goethe in precisely the same way: insofar as it embodies an idea in the broadest sense (Gehalt), and not in the sense of gesturing towards any intellectual or moralizing norm (as Boyle argues on pp. 311 12). Schiller did not think Art enabled one to grasp the Ideal in appearance (p. 728); he thought it enabled one to grasp import (Gehalt) in appearance. That is why Goethe could so enthusiastically endorse Schiller s 1791 review of Bürger s poetry (p. 91), and why he could subscribe to Schiller s epistemology in 1799 as to my own credo (p. 597), in the face of Schelling s increasingly uncongenial Naturphilosophie. For both of them, the aesthetic could be reduced to neither the (objective) empirical nor the (subjective) rational. It is, therefore, misleading to interpret Goethe (and Schiller) as bound together with the Schlegels, Schelling, Hegel, Hölderlin and Fichte by a belief in the culturally transformative power of Idealism (p. 709) and as participating in the Idealist aesthetic (p. 710). It not only drastically oversimplifies the Kulturkampf Goethe and Schiller were allied in conducting (p. 718). It also obscures the central role that Schiller s concept of wahrer (schöner) Schein, as distinct from the delusion of logischer Schein in competition with reality, played in Goethe s science and in his thinking in general. When he speaks in his 1796 essay, Morphology, of his conviction that everything that is must also manifest and show itself [...] as what it is (p. 459), he is speaking of Nature as an aesthetic phenomenon, one that cannot be reduced either to an empirical object (p. 598) or to an intellectual idea. Nature is rather, and, in this respect, like Art, the embodiment of significance. Goethe went beyond Schiller only in the meticulous application to natural and cultural phenomena of the theory they had hammered out together. To read the available evidence in the way Boyle does (drawing on an impressionistic reading of the poem Der neue Pausias in support of his thesis) seems to be the product of an unduly historicist (and, therefore, inevitably a-theoretical) approach.

Boyle argues convincingly that Goethe in his 1795 essay Literarischer Sansculottismus is not so much disowning Classicism as a regulative aesthetic ideal as rejecting the term as both a description of what had so far been achieved in German letters and as a French-derived counsel of perfection that could only demoralize (pp. 274, 447). It may seem a pity, then, that Nicholas Boyle did not grasp the evaluative nettle and debate the appropriateness of labelling the years of Goethe s middle age classical, a term he concedes was deservedly bestowed on it by official history (p. vii). However, as Leszek Kolakowski has remarked, conceptualization and experience move in opposite directions. Could it be that the genre of biography, with its unavoidable reliance on supposition about what must have been done, thought, and felt, and with its implicit trust in the correlation of outward events and the inward workings of the creative mind, cannot address such significant cultural issues? University of Glasgow R. H. Stephenson