TO SUZÊN AND INSTITUTIONAL ERGON: TOWARDS A NEO-ARISTOTELIAN ACCOUNT OF COLLECTIVE AGENCY AND INSTITUTIONAL VIRTUE

Similar documents
The Doctrine of the Mean

Aristotle on the Human Good

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

A Happy Ending: Happiness in the Nicomachean Ethics and Consolation of Philosophy. Wesley Spears

Valuable Particulars

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

ALIGNING WITH THE GOOD

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Practical Intuition and Deliberation in the Ethics of Aristotle. Word Count: 3,962 (With Notes, Header, and Abstract: 5,111)

Robert Solomon s Rejection of Aristotelian Virtue: Is the Passion of Erotic Love a Virtue that is Independent of Rationality?

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala

Simulated killing. Michael Lacewing

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Comments on Bence Nanay, Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

VIRTUE ETHICS-ARISTOTLE

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

The Theory and Practice of Virtue Education Edited by Tom Harrison and David I. Walker *

Rational Agency and Normative Concepts by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord UNC/Chapel Hill [for discussion at the Research Triangle Ethics Circle] Introduction

It is from this perspective that Aristotelian science studies the distinctive aspects of the various inhabitants of the observable,

ARISTOTLE. PHILO 381(W) Sec. 051[4810] Fall 2009 Professor Adluri Monday/Wednesday, 7:00-8:15pm

Anna Carabelli. Anna Carabelli. Università del Piemonte Orientale, Italy 1

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Two Initial Difficulties

Charles Taylor s Langue/Parole and Alasdair MacIntyre s Networks of Giving and Receiving as a Foundation for a Positive Anti-Atomist Political Theory

Introduction SABINE FLACH, DANIEL MARGULIES, AND JAN SÖFFNER

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Review of Carolyn Korsmeyer, Savoring Disgust: The foul and the fair. in aesthetics (Oxford University Press pp (PBK).

Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates Republic Symposium Republic Phaedrus Phaedrus), Theaetetus

PHILOSOPHY. Grade: E D C B A. Mark range: The range and suitability of the work submitted

Goldie on the Virtues of Art

Natural Genetic Engineering and Natural Genome Editing, Salzburg, July

On Recanati s Mental Files

observation and conceptual interpretation

GRADUATE SEMINARS

Perceptions and Hallucinations

THE ROLE OF THE PATHE IN ARISTOTLE S CONCEPTION OF VIRTUE

Care of the self: An Interview with Alexander Nehamas

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Assistant Professor in Philosophy, Cornell University (reappointed in 1969 to second 3-year term, resigned in 1970).

7AAN2026 Greek Philosophy I: Plato Syllabus Academic year 2015/16

Kent Academic Repository

In his essay "Of the Standard of Taste," Hume describes an apparent conflict between two

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

The Introduction of Universals

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

Substance, Nature, and Immanence Form in Aristotle s Constituent Ontology

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN:

Discourse analysis is an umbrella term for a range of methodological approaches that

Hegel and the French Revolution

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

Virtues of Art Peter Goldie and Dominic McIver Lopes

Can Art for Art s Sake Imply Ethics? Henry James and David Jones

The Value of Play and the Good Human Life

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

CONRAD AND IMPRESSIONISM JOHN G. PETERS

FICTIONAL ENTITIES AND REAL EMOTIONAL RESPONSES ANTHONY BRANDON UNIVERSITY OF MANCHESTER

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

Nature's Perspectives

Art and Morality. Sebastian Nye LECTURE 2. Autonomism and Ethicism

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

Emotions from the Perspective of Analytic Aesthetics

of perception, elaborated in his De Anima as an isomorphic motion of the soul. It will begin by

0:24 Arthur Holmes (AH): Aristotle s ethics 2:18 AH: 2:43 AH: 4:14 AH: 5:34 AH: capacity 7:05 AH:

Strategies for Writing about Literature (from A Short Guide to Writing about Literature, Barnett and Cain)

Image and Imagination

Julie K. Ward. Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) Mathesis Publications

THE RELATIONS BETWEEN ETHICS AND ECONOMICS: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS BETWEEN AYRES AND WEBER S PERSPECTIVES. By Nuria Toledano and Crispen Karanda

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

in order to formulate and communicate meaning, and our capacity to use symbols reaches far beyond the basic. This is not, however, primarily a book

Why Pleasure Gains Fifth Rank: Against the Anti-Hedonist Interpretation of the Philebus 1

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Comparing Neo-Aristotelian, Close Textual Analysis, and Genre Criticism

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

Nicomachean Ethics. Aristotle

A New Approach to the Paradox of Fiction Pete Faulconbridge

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

Review of "The Unexplained Intellect: Complexity, Time, and the Metaphysics of Embodied Thought"

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

Aristotle. Aristotle. Aristotle and Plato. Background. Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle and Plato

UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO INSTRUCTORSHIPS IN PHILOSOPHY CUPE Local 3902, Unit 1 SUMMER SESSION 2019

WHY STUDY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY? 1

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

A PRACTICAL DISTINCTION IN VALUE THEORY: QUALITATIVE AND QUANTITATIVE ACCOUNTS. Galen A. Foresman. A Dissertation

Transactional Theory in the Teaching of Literature. ERIC Digest.

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Emotion, an Organ of Happiness. Ruey-Yuan Wu National Tsing-Hua University

Creativity in Performance

Transcription:

TO SUZÊN AND INSTITUTIONAL ERGON: TOWARDS A NEO-ARISTOTELIAN ACCOUNT OF COLLECTIVE AGENCY AND INSTITUTIONAL VIRTUE FRITS GÅVERTSSON DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY, LUND UNIVERSITY Level: PhD Candidate Course: FPRA21:5 e-mail: frits.gavertsson@fil.lu.se For friendship is community, and we are related to our friend as we are related to ourselves. (NE1171b32)1 I. Introduction In recent years there has been a growing interest in a set of interrelated questions concerning agency and responsibility pertaining to collectives. This interest originates partly from the need we sometimes feel of holding groups such as corporate entities responsible for certain wrongdoings (such as cases where there is little or no blame to be placed on individual due to low or non-existent degrees of personal responsibility but where it nonetheless seems reasonable to hold them collectively responsible and blameworthy as a corporate enterprise) and partly from a more purely philosophical or metaphysical wonder regarding the nature of collective behaviour and other social phenomena as such. These two questions have usually been taken as connected in the sense that collective intentionality has been seen as a prerequisite for collective responsibility.2 This debate over collective intentionality can be seen as chiefly divided between an individualist approach that takes joint intention as the intentions of individuals related in certain ways but nevertheless being such that their content only concerns actions of the individual members (this includes pure reductionists3 and summative accounts that take collective agency to amount to nothing more than the summation of individual intentions with the same content4), accounts that understand collective action in terms of dispositions and causal agency5, accounts that takes the distinction to depend upon the content of the individual attitudes that All translations from the NE are from Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics, Translated with Introduction, Notes, and Glossary, by Terence Irwin, 2nd ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 1999). All other quotes from the Corpus Arostotelicum are from Barnes, Jonathan, (ed.) The Compolete Works of Aristotle, (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984). 2 As an exception from this general rule some theorists have argued that it is reasonable to hold a loosely structured, or even random, collection of individuals responsible (in a non-reductive sense) for omitting to take collective action, adopting a decision procedure or in some other way constituting itself as a group. See, for example, Held, Virginia, Can a Random Collection of Individuals be Morally Responsible?, Journal of Philosophy, 14 July 1970, pp. 471-481, Tännsjö, Torbjörn, the Myth of Innocence: On Collective Responsibility and Collective Punishment, Philosophical Papers, Vol. 36, No. 2, 4 May 2007, May, Larry, Collective Inaction and Shared Responsibility, Noûs 24(2) 1990, pp. 269-277, Idem, The Morality of Groups, (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1987). It should be noted that May, at least in his The morality of Groups, relies on Sartre s relational theory which might have some commonalities with my Aristotelian account. 3 This group takes its cue from standard accounts of agency and moral responsibility (which tend to focus on individuals) and argues that talk of collective agency and responsibility is merely rhetorically summative in character (and that any literal reading of such talk is to be seen as simple conceptual errors). See Weber Max, Economy and Society, Vol. 1, Berkeley: University of California Press, [1914] 1978, and Lewis, Hywel David, Collective Responsibility, Philosophy, Vol. 23 No. 84, January 1948, pp. 3-18. 4 See Quinton, Anthony, Social Objects, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 76, 1976, pp. 1-27. 5 See Petersson, Björn, Collectivity and Circularity, Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 104 No.3, 2007, pp. 138-156. 1

Frits Gåvertsson explain the behaviour of the group in question6, and collectivist approaches that view joint intentions as irreducible features of groups.7 The waters of these interrelated debates are muddled by the fact that different theorists seem interested in quite different aspects and levels of the overarching phenomenon of collective activity. It might, for instance, not be possible (or indeed preferable) to give a comprehensive or general account that is capable of accounting for all collective actions including loose, large, (possibly) hierarchical, collectives as well as two or few agents in an egalitarian setting where suppositions of common knowledge and high interdependence seems reasonable.8 Furthermore participants in the debate focusing on the content of collective intentions have had a hard time spelling out this content in a satisfactory manner.9 This might be due to the emphasis on conceptual analysis and the lack of extensive debate concerning psychological and phenomenological aspects of collective behaviour. This paper argues that Aristotle supplies the foundations for not only one, but two, distinct but compatible accounts of collective agency and institutional virtue that between them have several appealing features. Firstly, this two part Aristotelian account paints a plausible picture of shared activity structured around the life together with friends that is psychologically and phenomenologically appealing. Secondly, it takes seriously the essentially social nature of human life and thus, to a certain extent, challenges the priority usually given to individuals without collapsing into extreme forms of holism of a Hegelian kind. Thirdly, it is capable of accounting for corporate activity and institutions in a way that also has something to say regarding the roles we are assigned within such a community. It should be noted that my aims in what follows is not those of the interpreter. Rather, this is an attempt at establishing an outline of an account of collective agency that takes its cue from Aristotle but that goes beyond textual evidence and seeks to establish a neo-aristotelian position. II. The Friend as Another Self The notion of friendship (philia) plays a vital part in Aristotle s ethics and it seems like a given point of departure for any attempt at providing a distinctively Aristotelian account of collective agency. Toward the very end of Book IX of the Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle phrases his account of the life together with friends in what is strikingly collectivist terms: Whatever someone [regards as] his being, or the end for which he chooses to be alive, that is the activity he wishes to pursue in his friend s company. [ ] They spend their days together on whichever pursuit in life they like most; for since they want to live with their friends, they share the actions in which they find their common life. [ ] [T]he friendship of decent people is decent and increases the more often they meet. And they seem to become still better from their activities and their mutual correction. For each molds the other in what they approve of, so that [you will learn] what is noble form noble people. (NE1172a1-14) See, Bratman, Michael E., Shared Cooperative Activity (1992), and I intend that we J (1997), in Faces of Intention (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), and Kutz Christopher, Complicity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), These accounts are threatened by a circularity if they are read as (part of) a conceptual analysis since it is unclear if an independent account of the content of the relevant attitudes can be specified without making reference to collective action. Both Bratman and Kutz explicitly address this circularity charge in the works mentioned above and the issue is given a thorough treatment (together with the aforementioned causal analysis explicitly developed to handle the circularity) in Petersson, Björn, Collectivity and Circularity. 7 See Gilbert, Margaret, Sociality and Responsibility (Boston: Rowman & Littlefield, 2000). It might be that Gilbert s account which makes explicit normative claims perhaps should not be read as an attempt at conceptual analysis and does thus not necessarily fall prey to the circularity charge. This might give rise to a different set of problems however, since it is not in any way clear that normativity is essential to intentionality or should enter into this stage of analysis. Gilbert s account does point to an important feature of collectivity that should not be ignored: relations to others stands as the source of many normative aspects of our lives. 8 Kutz points to the fact that extensive focus on the latter case might yield too strong requirements. See Kutz, Christopher, Acting Together, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 61, No. 1, July 2000, pp. 1-31. 9 Another important challenge in this context has been to explain how it is possible for me to form an intention that makes necessary reference to something that is, at least partly, up to you that is, the intention that we Φ. 6 2

To Suzên and Institutional ergon A central notion in this passage is living together, or sharing one s life (to suzên). To live together, Aristotle seems to claim, is what we most desire from our friends. Indeed, this togetherness is what seems most of all to be the mark of true friendship as opposed to mere goodwill (eunoia) etc. (NE1157b19-25; 1158a8-10). A natural and influential reading of Aristotelian friendship is to see friendship as an extension, or even redefinition, of an individual s life in terms of the introduction of new or redefined boundaries so that this individual s happiness (eudaimonia) comes to include the happiness of others.10 In her Love Life: Aristotle on Living Together with Friends 11 Irene Liu presents an account that challenges this standard reading of the nature of the shared life that is both plausible and better suited for present purposes in that it opens up the possibility of making a metaphysically bolder collectivist claim.12 At the heart of Liu s account lies the so-called argument from nature at (NE1170a16-1170b20)13. The argument looks something like this: (i) Human life (to zên) is characterised by understanding and perceiving (to aisthanesthai) and pleasant14 in itself. (ii) We are engaged in a kind of self-perception that is the same as perceiving our being alive15 (hoti esmen). (iii) This self-perception of our own existence is pleasant. (iv) The friend is like another self, and therefore this friend s existence is desirable (hairetos), like one s own. (v) To perceive this friend s existence we must jointly perceive (to sunaisthanesthai) as friends and this requires us to live together (to suzên).16 This argument thus moves from a claim pertaining to what is characteristic of human life to the importance of living together. Central here is the idea that we do not perceive our lives directly. Rather, we do this through other activities (Cf. NE1170a29-b1) in a way such that a part becomes a representation of the whole, what Liu terms synecdochic activities (so named after the poetic device).17 This goes for the way we perceive the lives of friends as well for we enjoy our friend s good activities as our own (oikeios) and in a pleasurable way (NE1170a3; 1169b33). Moreover this special perception (sunaisthêsis) of the friend s life is mutual and reciprocal, friends perceive each other (NE1155b27-1155a5); it is a form of joint perception. Our life as a whole the central organizing concern of eudaimonist ethics is thus made available to us through the life together with friends. The joint perception of these synecdochic activities makes self-awareness of life as a whole (both our own and those of friends) possible in such a way that we see the structure of our lives and can organise them accordingly. As such, joint perception is to be regarded as an indispensible tool for organising life, but it is also an expression of solidarity with For a clear statement of this view see Sherman, Nancy, Aristotle on Friendship and the Shared Life, Philosophy and Phenomenological research, Vol. 47, No. 4, June 1987, pp. 589-613. 11 Liu, Irene, Love Life: Aristotle on Living Together with Friends, Inquiry, Vol. 53, No. 6, pp. 579-601, December 2010. 12 I do not wish to take an exegetical stand here. It could be rather forcefully argued that the standard reading fits better with the corresponding passages in the EE and the MM and that the reading proposed here borders on the eisegetical. However, the contexts of the relevant passages differ in such a way as to make any definitive conclusions hard to reach. 13 Cf. MM1213a10-1213b1, EE1244b20-1245b10. 14 Irene Liu writes: by claiming that it is pleasant, Aristotle implies that this activity has a phenomenological character perhaps more akin to sense perception than to intellectual apprehension (Liu, Irene, Love Life: Aristotle on Living Together with Friends, p. 585). Perhaps this could be understood, Liu further argues, as akin to the way we talk of feeling alive in certain especially invigorating circumstances and that this connect to the way we perceive life as a whole and that [a]ccordingly, we might understand Aristotle s perception hoti semen or hoti zêi as the selfconsciousness of oneself having or better, living a life (ibidem p. 585). 15 Possible alternatives here would be that we live, that we are or that we exists. 16 For other formalisations of the argument see, for example, footnote to NE1170b19 in Ross translation in The Works of Aristotle Translated into English, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1915, Vol. IX, Cooper, John, M., Friendship and Good in Aristotle, The Philosophical Review, Vol. 86 No. 2, 1977:290-315:293, Broadie, Sarah, and Rowe, Christopher, Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics Translated and with commentary by Sarah Broadie and Christopher Rowe (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), p. 426, and Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics, Translated with Introduction, Notes, and Glossary, by Terence Irwin, 2nd ed., (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 1999), p. 298. 17 Cf. Liu, Irene, Love Life: Aristotle on Living Together with Friends, p. 586. See also NE1171b34-1172a6. 10 3

Frits Gåvertsson one s friends and a necessary component of genuine friendship in that it makes it possible for us to truly see and enjoy the good lives of friends (NE1156b9-10) and share in them in such a way that we go beyond the lesser forms of friendship (outlined at NE1156a6-b6) and share in each other s lives (NE1171b12-14) as ends in themselves (NE1156b7-14). What this amounts to is an austere form of holism that maintains collectivity as an essential feature of human life. Friendship in thus seen as built into the very structure of human life. Liu illustrates this by way of an example, likening friendship to a chess-game: Chess is defined as a strategic game played by two players. While these sides must remain distinct, they are also logically inseparable. [ ] Thus, a one-sided chess-game is no game at all.18 The foundational claim of the argument from nature and the Aristotelian dictum that humans are social by nature can thus be understood as saying that friendship is not only beneficial to human life (the greatest of external goods) but part of what makes life human.19 In understanding collective agency with regards to small collectives this ideal picture of the best kind of friendship between virtuous persons can be used as something akin to how prominent examples function in the prototype theory of concept learning. In categorizing collective behaviour on the level of small egalitarian groups we can rely on a hierarchical inventory (Cf. the types of friendship identified by Aristotle at NE1156a6ff) based on similarity. We thus end up with a more fine-grained, continuous, way of understanding collectives. III. The Virtues of Institutions In her Can there be Institutional Virtues Miranda Fricker attests that [w]e cannot literally apply concepts of virtue and vice to institutions considered purely procedurally, for they do not have any of the features of the normal subjects of virtue and vice: they are not agents [ ]. I contend, therefore, that it is only in combination with the individuals and groups whose work realizes an institution s procedures at any given time that the institution may literally be said to exhibit virtues and vices. 20 While this might be, there is, on an Aristotelian picture, something special about institutions they can, in the fullest sense, be said to possess a function, or characteristic activity (ergon).21 They have a purpose for which they are made and this purpose ties them closely to the particular human goods with which they are concerned. Sean Cordell has argued that this tie gives us a possibility to distinguish institutions into kinds (corresponding to a certain good or set of goods) and evaluating them qua institutions of their respective kind.22 The task for such evaluation, Cordell claims, is to say why this institution, and not some other(s), should be linked to this or these specific good(s) and not others, in a way that helps determine whether it is doing well as an instance of its kind.23 This idea of the institutional ergon is then used to shed light on another important debate in the context of normative ethics related to collectives, namely the issue of role-specific duties.24 This Aristotelian approach, Cordell claims, is Liu, Irene, Love Life: Aristotle on Living Together with Friends, p. 595. This goes nowhere to deny the fact that friendship is also contributory in making life eudaimon on the Aristotelian picture. 20 Fricker, Miranda, Can There Be Institutional Virtues?, pp. 235-252 in Szabó Gendler, T, and Hawthorne, J (eds.) Oxford Studies in Epistemology 3, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010, p. 249. 21 The ergon argument, beginning at NE1097b22, is hugely complex and subject to an extensive debate which need luckily not detain us here. What is important for present purposes is that institutions, in virtue of being man-made, can be said to possess such a function in the fullest sense, at least with regards to prime examples of such entities. 22 Cordell, Sean, Virtuous Persons and Social Roles, pp. 254-272 Journal of Social Philosophy, Vol. 42 No. 3 2011. 23 Ibid., pp. 266-267. 24 An undisputed classic in this field is obviously F. H. Bradley s My Station and Its Duties, pp. 160-213 in Ethical Studies (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1927). From a virtue ethical perspective this issue has been discussed by amongst others Christine Swanton in her Virtue Ethics, Role Ethics, and Business Ethics, pp. 207-224 in Walker, Rebecca L. and Ivanhoe, Philip J. (ed.), Working Virtue (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), Julia Annas, My Station and its Duties: Ideals and the Social Embeddedness of Virtue, pp. 109-123 in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Vol. 102 No. 1, 2002, and Rosalind Hursthouse in her Two Ways of Doing the Right Thing, pp. 236-255 in Farelly, Colin, and Solum, Lawrence B. (ed.) Virtue Jurisprudence (Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillian, 2007) 18 19 4

To Suzên and Institutional ergon capable of side-stepping a dilemma pertaining to the normative force of social and professional roles. On the one hand we might think of roles in such a strict internalist way that it becomes impossible for the virtuous person not to find herself in a irresolvable tension between the right and the role-given, on the other hand we might resort to abstract ideals such as justice to transcend the normativity of our social and professional roles but this manoeuvre leaves us in the open with regards to how to connect them to our role-specified obligations and threatens to eradicate completely the normative force of such role-specific duties. Thinking of institutions in the Aristotelian manner suggested might help the virtuous person in her deliberative process to come to terms with a given role and its requirements as well as the limitations of its normative scope, or so Cordell claims. The proposed model might, I would like to suggest, also help us understanding institutional virtues. By connecting the function of an institution with the particular human good it is set up to promote and which is unique to it we have identified a particular sphere pertaining to that institution with regards to which it can be said to be well or ill functioning and therefore virtuous or vicious. An institution might also exhibit additional features not directly linked to its particular sphere well or ill functioning structures whom might encourage virtuous or vicious behaviour on behalf of its members etc. that can be accounted for in the more reductive spirit of Fricker, that is, by saying that they possess these traits when their structures are brought to life by the individuals and collectives whose activity puts flesh on the institutional bone 25, but the idea behind the more ambitious reading here proposed is that institutions can be said to operate primarily within a sphere unique to it that is also connected to a particular human good. This good then constitutes the telos of the particular institution and it can be said to be virtuous to the extent that it is productive of this good, that is performs its ergon well: each function is completed well by being completed in accord with the virtue proper [to that kind of thing] (NE1098 a 16). 25 Fricker, Miranda, Can There Be Institutional Virtues? p. 249. 5