[The LSE Social Representations Group] London School of Economics, United Kingdom

Similar documents
CRITIQUE OF PARSONS AND MERTON

A Theory of Structural Constraints on the Individual s Social Representing? A comment on Jaan Valsiner s (2003) Theory of Enablement

Mixing Metaphors. Mark G. Lee and John A. Barnden

Discourse analysis is an umbrella term for a range of methodological approaches that

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

Social representations and discursive psychology

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

Emotion, Reason and Self: Reconsidering the Understanding of Others in Multicultural Education

Title: Narrative as construction and discursive resource Author: Stephanie Taylor

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

Mass Communication Theory

Week 25 Deconstruction

Architecture is epistemologically

ARCHITECTURE AND EDUCATION: THE QUESTION OF EXPERTISE AND THE CHALLENGE OF ART

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Integration, Ambivalence, and Mental Conflict

7. This composition is an infinite configuration, which, in our own contemporary artistic context, is a generic totality.

Ambiguity/Language/Learning Ron Burnett President, Emily Carr Institute of Art + Design

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

PHIL106 Media, Art and Censorship

The book Opportunities and Deprivation in the Urban South by Eduardo Cesar

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK

Challenging the View That Science is Value Free

Contradictions, Dialectics, and Paradoxes as Discursive Approaches to Organizational Analysis

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

INTUITION IN SCIENCE AND MATHEMATICS

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

CUST 100 Week 17: 26 January Stuart Hall: Encoding/Decoding Reading: Stuart Hall, Encoding/Decoding (Coursepack)

Semiotics of culture. Some general considerations

Introduction and Overview

The Meaning of Abstract and Concrete in Hegel and Marx

Q1. Name the texts that you studied for media texts and society s values this year.

Slide 1. Slide 2. Slide 3 Historical Development. Formalism. EH 4301 Spring 2011

A Handbook for Action Research in Health and Social Care

Watcharabon Buddharaksa. The University of York. RCAPS Working Paper No January 2011

University of Huddersfield Repository

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

SOCIAL REPRESENTATON. Yohan Bhatti. Thesis submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Psychology.

Conversation Analysis, Discursive Psychology and the study of ideology: A Response to Susan Speer

Comparing Neo-Aristotelian, Close Textual Analysis, and Genre Criticism

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

The Senses at first let in particular Ideas. (Essay Concerning Human Understanding I.II.15)

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

Learning to see value: interactions between artisans and their clients in a Chinese craft industry

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

Any attempt to revitalize the relationship between rhetoric and ethics is challenged

Kent Academic Repository

Critical Theory. Mark Olssen University of Surrey. Social Research at Frankfurt-am Main in The term critical theory was originally

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

Hamletmachine: The Objective Real and the Subjective Fantasy. Heiner Mueller s play Hamletmachine focuses on Shakespeare s Hamlet,

Sandra Jovchelovitch. Social representations, public life and social construction

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

Communication Mechanism of Ironic Discourse

Aesthetics and meaning

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

observation and conceptual interpretation

Post Structuralism, Deconstruction and Post Modernism

On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth

Royce: The Anthropology of Dance

On Recanati s Mental Files

The Revealed Yet Still Hidden Relation between Form & the Formless

Culture in Social Theory

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

S/A 4074: Ritual and Ceremony. Lecture 14: Culture, Symbolic Systems, and Action 1

Homo Ecologicus and Homo Economicus

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

Categories and Schemata

Adisa Imamović University of Tuzla

RESPONSE AND REJOINDER

Special Issue Introduction: Coming to Terms in the Muddy Waters of Qualitative Inquiry in Communication Studies

In his essay "Of the Standard of Taste," Hume describes an apparent conflict between two

This text is an entry in the field of works derived from Conceptual Metaphor Theory. It begins

1/10. Berkeley on Abstraction

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

Misc Fiction Irony Point of view Plot time place social environment

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN

Image and Imagination

2. Preamble 3. Information on the legal framework 4. Core principles 5. Further steps. 1. Occasion

Derrida, Structure, Sign and Play in the Discourse of the Human Sciences. Part One, or When is a centre not a centre?

Harris Wiseman, The Myth of the Moral Brain: The Limits of Moral Enhancement (Cambridge, MA and London: The MIT Press, 2016), 340 pp.

Reading/Study Guide: Lyotard. The Postmodern Condition

Ethnographic R. From outside, no access to cultural meanings From inside, only limited access to cultural meanings

Deconstruction is a way of understanding how something was created and breaking something down into smaller parts.

The character who struggles or fights against the protagonist. The perspective from which the story was told in.

Segundo Curso Textos Literarios Ingleses I Groups 2 and 4 Harold Pinter and The Homecoming. Outline

Paradigm paradoxes and the processes of educational research: Using the theory of logical types to aid clarity.

THE WORK OF ART: exploring art as a social practice. helma sawatzky

Introduction to Special Issue: Linking Two Theories HOW CAN THE SOCIAL REPRESENTATIONS THEORY BE MADE DIALOGICAL?

Stenberg, Shari J. Composition Studies Through a Feminist Lens. Anderson: Parlor Press, Print. 120 pages.

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

Art Education for Democratic Life

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

Transcription:

[The LSE Social Representations Group] London School of Economics, United Kingdom Abstract: This paper challenges the notion that consensus defined as 'agreement in opinion' is at the heart of the theory of social representations. We suggest that the problem of consensus is a highly complex aspect of social life requiring appraisal. Consensus refers neither to mere agreement nor to the mere sharedness of attitudes, opinions and values by a social group. While these are the most common interpretations circulating in the literature, they fail to apprehend the different levels of analysis required to understand the social construction of symbolic realities. In this paper we criticise the most common notions of consensus and propose an alternative view. There is space in the theory of social representations to develop a more refined approach to the issue. We make use of this space in order to construct our argument that consensus in social representations exists at several levels. We propose the idea of a representational field simultaneously characterised by consensus, inconsistency and ambivalence. The issue of power within this heterogenous representational field is discussed. The `consensual' nature of social representations is often equated with their widely shared nature. Common to certain proponents of the theory and to some of its critics alike is a conception of consensus which renders it synonymous with agreement. Both * This paper was presented at The Second International Conference on Social Representations, Rio de Janeiro, August 29th - September 1st 1994, and The British Psychological Society, Social Psychology Section Annual Conference, Downing College, Cambridge, 20th - 22nd September 1994. p a p e r s o n s o c i a l r e p r e s e n t a t i o n s t e x t e s s u r l e s r e p r é s e n t a t i o n s s o c i a l e s ( 1 0 2 1-5 5 7 3 ) V o l. 4 ( 2 ), 1-1 5 5 ( 1 9 9 5 ).

2 D. Rose, et. al. Jaspers and Fraser argue that the most distinctive feature of social representations is that they are shared by many individuals and as such constitute a social reality. Indeed, Fraser (1994) seems to propose that social representations are a sub-set of the more general field of attitudes. From this perspective, sets of widely shared attitudes are termed social representations whilst more idiosyncratic beliefs are simply envisaged as individual attitudes. Perhaps it is this assumption that leads Fraser (1994) to propose that survey methodology should be a primary methodological tool used for the investigation of social representations. However, while surveys are often useful in providing a snapshot of the attitudes and opinions of large, representative samples, used alone they cannot capture the diverse processes involved in the construction of social representations. They tend to focus on consensual or widespread opinions, ignoring non-consensual opinions, absent opinions and other levels of consensus, all of which are integral parts in the forging of social representations. Survey methodology reifies the concept of consensus, thereby failing to acknowledge the co-existence of oppositional themes and the consequences of this for the functioning of social representations in social life. For example, if a survey finds that 70% of teenagers are opposed to drugs surely it would still be necessary to explore the attitudes of the 30% who do not oppose drugs. Minority representations are neither independent nor unimportant. They constantly interact with the majority representations through conversations, the media, schools and peer groups. From a different perspective, discourse analysts (Potter and Litton, 1985; Potter and Wetherell, 1987; McKinlay & Potter, 1987) have criticised what they see as consensus in a social representation. They have implied that social representations theory posits that agreement will be found at the level of specific conversations. They have used examples of such conversations to demonstrate that "consensus" does not exist at this level. The argument of discourse analysts concerning the concept of consensus in social representational theory seems to be misguided. To imagine that consensus exists at the level of specific communications would render the theory of social representations entirely static, with the possibility of conversation and thought being completely impossible. Indeed, substantive research, including the work of Jodelet (1991), Duveen & Lloyd (1990), De Rosa (1987) and Giami (1987) has shown how oppositional themes can be found in a whole range of social representations. This echoes Billig's (1987, 1993) notion that social thinking has an argumentative rather than a consensual structure. Unfortunately, Billig fails to draw social representations theory into his own rhetorical position. Ironically, the views of attitude theorists and discourse analysts rest on a common assumption concerning social representations theory. They assume that consensus requires a static and banal agreement between participants at all levels of their interaction. Mention of consensus in Moscovici's and his colleagues' work is taken to imply that any act of social communication must spring from, and result in, superficial agreement or "consensus". However, Moscovici (1988) does not identify consensus with sharedness, agreement, uniformity or homogeneity. He asserts: "It seems an aberration... to consider representations as homogeneous and shared as such by a whole society. What we wished to emphasise by giving up the word "collective" was this

Questioning Consensus 3 plurality of representations and their diversity within a group." (Moscovici, 1988; p. 219. Emphasis added). Indeed, one of the reasons why Moscovici abandoned the Durkheimian concept of "collective representations" was precisely because it was too static and was appropriate only to a previous era and type of society. It could not account for the centrality of representational diversity, tension and even conflict in modern life. Having highlighted some misconceptions of consensus, we move on to discuss the issues which are central to a more appropriate notion of consensus in social representations theory. First we will consider how social processes rely on shared background assumptions. Secondly we will discuss how this relates to the structure of the social representation. If straightforward and total agreement is not what is meant by consensus in the theory of social representations then what is the meaning of this concept? Let us begin by reminding ourselves that social representations are social and cultural entities, rather than the mere symbolic productions of isolated individuals. In Moscovici's terms, they are an "environment". This is what Fraser's (1994) argument, discussed earlier, fails to grasp: Social representations exist both in culture and in people's minds. They could not exist without being collectively realised. They are rooted in social life. They express and structure both the identity and social conditions of the actors who reproduce and change them. Social representations are generated in the communicative practices of everyday life. These are embedded in a stock of historically constrained social knowledge. There is a tension between a commonly shared historical background and the diverse everyday interaction of individuals who can construct and construe, invent and transform. Yet social actors do not encounter a blank background waiting to be written. Any given society has the force to gather and to transmit not only descriptions but also prescriptions attached to a historical time. So, social representations do not presuppose a purely consensual universe, and yet, they presuppose a degree of consensuality. The theory of social representations attempts to conceptualise both the power of social reality and the agency of social subjects. There is always a level of consensual reality in a society, which allows for cognition and recognition, for a language to be spoken and for debate and argumentation to take place. Such a level of consensus does not relate to general agreement or to the sharedness of the same opinion in everyday talk. It relates to the fact that even in disagreement social subjects still know what they are talking about, what they are referring to. This tacit knowledge provides a common basis upon which people discuss, compete or argue. This common ground does not result from the sharing of the same views. Rather, its existence is permitted by the "taken-for-grantedness" of social life. This taken-forgrantedness is built up mainly through language, images and ritualistic practices. It follows, then, that it is necessary to make a distinction between (1) the level of the underlying ground-rules of social representation formation, which make understanding possible, are located in institutional settings, draw upon the weight of history and

4 D. Rose, et. al. possess a consensual dimension, and (2) the level of immediate social interaction which involves disagreement and argumentation. Of course these two levels are integral to one another in social practice. This distinction between levels cannot be understood if social representations are seen as exclusively "mental entities" replicated in the heads of all individuals in a group. This is clearly illustrated in Jodelet's (1991) study of madness. She found that it was at the level of consensual ritualistic practices, such as the separate washing of lodgers' clothes and eating utensils, that the most exclusionary representations were given form. At the same time, there was constant discussion and disagreement amongst the villagers concerning their lodgers in respect of who was dangerous and who was harmless. At the level of manifest discourse they would argue and disagree. Yet, they would enact the same rituals to express the unspeakable. To keep themselves apart and protect their identity, the villagers were representing the mad not only through discourse but also through ritualistic practices that were beyond dissent within the community. We have argued that there is a level of `consensus' in the background assumptions that makes interaction possible. Does it then follow that these background assumptions must themselves constitute a coherent and unified system? The answer to this question relates directly to the structure of the social representation. Since history and everyday social interaction are fraught with tensions, social representations generated in this context cannot be monolithic. Communication, representation and action are fragmented and contradictory. Thus social representations include in their very structure the resources for dilemmatic thinking. Moscovici states that the structure of a social representation allows for the simultaneous presence of divergent concepts, inconsistent ideas and paradoxical meanings. "Representations assume a configuration where concepts and images can coexist without any attempt at uniformity, where uncertainty as well as misunderstandings are tolerated, so that discussion can go on and thoughts circulate." (Moscovici, 1988: p.233) Contradictory views co-exist in people's minds as well as in their social and representational contexts. One only has to think about Hitler's Germany where Jews were accused at once of being fierce capitalists and uncompromising communists, hugely successful and totally degenerate. Against notions of monolithic and homogenous representations, we propose the idea of a representational field, susceptible to contradiction, fragmentation, negotiation and debate. In such a representational field, there is incoherence, tension and ambivalence. Yet, permeating all these disparate elements there is a consensual reality, which forms the common ground of historically shared meanings within which people discuss and negotiate. We have argued that `consensus' is always temporary and precarious since social interaction and communication constantly threaten its stability. However, whilst the

Questioning Consensus 5 multiplicity of social representations, or of contradictory elements within a given representation of any one object needs to be emphasised, relativism must be avoided. A relativist position denies the fact that social representations held by certain groups in a society have greater authority than those of other groups. There is power to be found in the symbolic field, in which very unequally equipped agents must compete to exert their influence. Nowhere is this clearer than with respect to the location of social representations in institutional settings which stabilise, control, and even segregate social groups and individuals. The mass media, for example, is one of the institutions which establishes the representational field in which people take up their (often contradictory) positions. The theory of social representations' understanding of the interaction between the media and lay thinkers has the potential to provide a sense both of the power of the media, and of the creativity of its audience. Unfortunately these two components are seldom integrated by the principal proponents of the theory. In fact, social representations theory has rightly been accused of ignoring issues of power. For this reason we stress that the debate and negotiation which occur in the representational field do not necessarily undermine existing power relations. Consensus is already the outcome of power struggles occurring in the social fabric. Specific social groups have more access than others to the means for establishing dominant meanings. However, history is an open-ended process. Negotiation, debate and the forging of new practices may allow relations of power to change over time. In this paper we have challenged the idea that the notion of consensus, defined in terms of agreement, is central to the theory of social representations. Consensual realities do exist in society and it would be an error not to acknowledge them. However, it would be yet another error to conceive of these consensual realities as the agreement of autonomous individuals. We have proposed that the notion of consensus exists in an area of the representational field which is in permanent interaction with more mobile and unstable elements. We have suggested that this field is itself heterogenous, contested and diverse. This results from everyday life being marked by competing versions of reality and by power relations. Social representations arise from these contradictions and it is their very meaning that the theory attempts to understand. Billig M (1987) Arguing and Thinking: A rhetorical approach to social psychology. European Monographs in Social Psychology. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge. Billig M (1993) Studying the thinking society: social representations, rhetoric and attitudes. In G Breakwell & D Canter (eds) Empirical Approaches to Social Representations. Clarendon Press: Oxford. De Rosa A (1987) The social representations of mental illness in children and adults. In W Doise & S Moscovici (eds) Current Issues in European Social Psychology, Volume 2. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

6 D. Rose, et. al. Duveen G & Lloyd B (eds) (1990) Social Representations and the Development of Knowledge. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge. Fraser C (1994) Attitudes, social representations and widespread beliefs. Papers on Social Representations, 3 (1), 13-25. Giami A (1987) Les représentations du handicap: Une approche psycho-sociale clinique. In G Bellelli (ed) La Représentation Sociale de la Maladie Mentale. Ligouri: Naples. Jaspers J M & Fraser C (1984) Attitudes and social representations. In R M Farr & S Moscovici (eds) Social Representations. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge. Jodelet D (1991) Madness and Social Representations. Harvester Wheatsheaf: Hemel Hempstead. McKinlay A & Potter J (1987) Social representations: a conceptual critique. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 17, 471-88. Moscovici S (1988) Notes towards a description of social representations. European Journal of Social Psychology, 18, 211-250. Potter J & Litton I (1985) Some problems underlying the theory of social representations. British Journal of Social Psychology, 24, 81-90. Potter J & Wetherell M (1987) Discourse and Social Psychology: Beyond attitudes and behaviour. Sage Publications Ltd: London. Diana Rose, Danielle Efraim, Marie-Claude Gervais, Hélène Joffe, Sandra Jovchelovitch, Nicola Morant [The LSE Social Representations Group], Department of Social Psychology London School of Economics Houghton Street London WC2A 2AE United Kingdom