The Ethics of Work in the Music of Sholla Allyson Obaniyi. Lawrence O. Bamikole

Similar documents
UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

observation and conceptual interpretation

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Sample Lesson on Saworoide (Kelani, 1999)

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

AESTHETICS. Key Terms

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Reconstruction of Our Yoruba History - 5. Language has been described as ⠜(a) Communication of thoughts and feelings through a

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

PH 360 CROSS-CULTURAL PHILOSOPHY IES Abroad Vienna

None DEREE COLLEGE SYLLABUS FOR: PH 4028 KANT AND GERMAN IDEALISM UK LEVEL 6 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3. (Updated SPRING 2016) PREREQUISITES:

Hear hear. Århus, 11 January An acoustemological manifesto

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Art, Mind and Cognitive Science

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Pierre Hadot on Philosophy as a Way of Life. Pierre Hadot ( ) was a French philosopher and historian of ancient philosophy,

Review of Carolyn Korsmeyer, Savoring Disgust: The foul and the fair. in aesthetics (Oxford University Press pp (PBK).

Inter-subjective Judgment

Moral Judgment and Emotions

THE STRUCTURALIST MOVEMENT: AN OVERVIEW

Kent Academic Repository

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

THE RELATIONS BETWEEN ETHICS AND ECONOMICS: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS BETWEEN AYRES AND WEBER S PERSPECTIVES. By Nuria Toledano and Crispen Karanda

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

Emotions from the Perspective of Analytic Aesthetics

1) Three summaries (2-3 pages; pick three out of the following four): due: 9/9 5% due: 9/16 5% due: 9/23 5% due: 9/30 5%

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

In his essay "Of the Standard of Taste," Hume describes an apparent conflict between two

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

J.S. Mill s Notion of Qualitative Superiority of Pleasure: A Reappraisal

Integration, Ambivalence, and Mental Conflict

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

COURSE: PHILOSOPHY GRADE(S): NATIONAL STANDARDS: UNIT OBJECTIVES: Students will be able to: STATE STANDARDS:

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

CAROL HUNTS University of Kansas

The Doctrine of the Mean

Good and Beautiful: A Moral-Aesthetic View of Personhood in African Communal Traditions

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

CONRAD AND IMPRESSIONISM JOHN G. PETERS

EXPANDED COURSE DESCRIPTIONS UC DAVIS PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT SPRING, Michael Glanzberg MWF 10:00-10:50a.m., 176 Everson CRNs:

Introduction and Overview

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

[My method is] a science that studies the life of signs within society I shall call it semiology from the Greek semeion signs (Saussure)

Classical Political Economy, Ethics, Metaphysics and Knowledge-Based Economy

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

The Folk Society by Robert Redfield

CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK

Aristotle on the Human Good

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver

Humanities Learning Outcomes

Humanities 4: Lecture 19. Friedrich Schiller: On the Aesthetic Education of Man

124 Philosophy of Mathematics

On Recanati s Mental Files

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

AN INSIGHT INTO CONTEMPORARY THEORY OF METAPHOR

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Hamletmachine: The Objective Real and the Subjective Fantasy. Heiner Mueller s play Hamletmachine focuses on Shakespeare s Hamlet,

The Use of Music in Equipping the Nigerian Child for Civic Challenges

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

Virtue Theory and Exemplars

Thomas Szanto: Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes

VALUES AND VALUING [Adapted from Carl Mitcham, ed., Encyclopedia of Science, Technology, and Ethics (New York: Macmillan Reference, 2005).

An essay on Alasdair MacIntyre s Relativism. Power and Philosophy

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Aesthetics Mid-Term Exam Review Guide:

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Studia Philosophiae Christianae UKSW 49(2013)4. Michigan Technological University, USA

Comparing Neo-Aristotelian, Close Textual Analysis, and Genre Criticism

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Poznań, July Magdalena Zabielska

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

Architecture is epistemologically

Objective vs. Subjective

African Philosophy. Polycarp Ikuenobe A N I NTRODUCTION

The Debate on Research in the Arts

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

PHILOSOPHICAL APPLICATIONS OF COGNITIVE SCIENCE COURSE STRUCTURE

BOOK REVIEW. ALL THINGS SHINING: READING THE WESTERN CLASSICS TO FIND MEANING IN A SECULAR AGE (Hubert Dreyfus and Sean Dorrance Kelly)

Nicomachean Ethics. p. 1. Aristotle. Translated by W. D. Ross. Book II. Moral Virtue (excerpts)

Normative and Positive Economics

Instantiation and Characterization: Problems in Lowe s Four-Category Ontology

MAURICE MANDELBAUM HISTORY, MAN, & REASON A STUDY IN NINETEENTH-CENTURY THOUGHT THE JOHNS HOPKINS PRESS: BALTIMORE AND LONDON

Transcription:

The Ethics of Work in the Music of Sholla Allyson Obaniyi Lawrence O. Bamikole Ethics and aesthetics as axiological disciplines Axiology can simply be defined as the study of values. In philosophical parlance, ethics and aesthetics are regarded as value oriented disciplines. Such disciplines are concerned with evaluation of ideas, thoughts, statements and expressions in relation to standards that are not purely empirical. The history of the relationship between ethics (human conduct) and aesthetics (beauty) has been a chequered one. Thus, for instance, Plato (2000) had advocated for an intimate connection between the good and the beautiful thereby drawing some substantive implications for how human beings ought to live; while Kennick (1965) held that it is a mistake to hold that there is a logical symmetry between moral judgments and aesthetic judgments. Kennick based his views on the belief that ethics has a standard of evaluation while aesthetics does not. Moreover, some thinkers about Western axiology (Ayer 2001) have held that the value disciplines in philosophy, such as ethics and aesthetics can be analyzed in purely scientific terms and if this cannot be done, then such disciplines can only be regarded as performing only emotional functions without any cognitive values. There are also analytic philosophers, for instance, Moore (1978) who had gone as far as to claim that terms like good and beauty are unanalyzable because they are already simple notions. It was only in the era of pragmatism as witnessed in the works of Dewey (2005) and Rorty (2001) that we are witnessing the existential and cultural dimensions of the value disciplines and a discouragement of the water tight distinction between science and values. Rorty, in particular, has suggested a kind of ecumenical relationship between all disciplines, identifying them within solidarity with the community. Given the predominant view within the African conceptual scheme that entities bear organic relationship with one another, the connection between ethics and aesthetics becomes perspicuous. With the exemption of the philosophers that have been tagged African neo-positivist, scholars that have examined the relationship between ethics and aesthetics have identified logical, epistemic, ontological and existential connections between the two disciplines. In this connection, Hallen (2000, 113) has this to say: I have chosen the term (values) because it is a way to avoid the arbitrary division that has been introduced into English-language discourse by the use of the separate terms ethics (arising from art) as if naming two different intellectual realms. For in the discussions with the onisegun, the transition from the good to the beautiful was as systematic and coherent as was the case with that between the epistemological and the moral And Bewaji (2003, 161-162) asserts that Songs (a form of art) are a useful medium for the development of the sense of right and wrong (ethics) in members of society as they teach the young and the old accepted codes and norms of socio-political, cultural and religious behaviour There are two essential lessons that could be learnt from the linkage of ethics with aesthetics. The first is that the African world view does not condone individualistic and atomistic conception of reality; rather it sees all the items in the conceptual system as being related to one another- humans are related to non-human, living to non-living, the sacred to 1

the profane, and the living to the dead. The second lesson is that values do not exist in themselves; rather they exist in relation to particular existential and practical experiences of the people. Gbadegesin (1998) for instance, has observed that Yoruba ethics is a pragmatic one. Aesthetic expressions as reflection of existential realities One of the philosophical problems of aesthetics is concerned with the relationship between the artist and what he/she expresses by his/her work. The predominant view in Western philosophy is that art and beauty is expression of feeling or emotion (Charlton 1970:84). However, feelings and emotions have objects and the further problem is the relationship between these feelings and emotions and what they are about, that is what they represent. Different philosophical (cultural) traditions have given responses to these questions on the basis of their own peculiar world views. Onyewuenyi (1984, 239) observed that: The ultimate basis for cultural differences in interpreting and appreciating art works rests principally on differences in metaphysics, which is an integral vision of reality as such. Thus it has been traditionally held that Western ontology and epistemology are based on the yardstick of individualism. The individual, according to this view, is the primary reference on all issues relating to existence and knowledge. The tradition has been exemplified in the philosophical systems of the 17 th Century Continental rationalists, especially Descartes (1911) and British empiricists, like David Hume (1955). As it relates to aesthetics, the belief is that it is the individual artist that is the sole judge of his/her works because he/she has intended something by them and as long as the works of art correspond to the thing intended, then they are good/beautiful works of art.. This is an allusion to Carroll (2000, 59) claim that: In the West, as the eighteenth century dissolved into the nineteenth,... ambitious artists--both in theory and in practice--began to turn inward; they became less preoccupied with capturing the appearance of nature and manners of society than to exploring their own subjective experiences Another feature of the Western conception of aesthetics, which also derives from its ontology and epistemology, is the idea of art for art s sake, a position that stresses only the intrinsic worth of a work of art. Onyewuenyi (1984, 141) also explains this feature in the following way: Much emphasis is placed on the perfection of art works, the prestige possess because of a long history of unquestioned admiration. Descriptive terms such as lively expression, naturalistic, disinterested gratification, ugly, beautiful, etc. characterize European/American evaluation of designs and motifs of art works. Thus they are separated from conditions of history and origin and operation in experience Duran (2006, 38) is essentially in agreement with the views expressed by Onyewuenyi when she observed: "Historically speaking, we can trace the notions of detachment in European aesthetics to a period far beyond the Enlightenment; we can, of course, trace notions to Plato. Because Western philosophy is rooted in the notion of give account of, where the term to be given an account of is divorced from contextual considerations, we can with a fair degree of accuracy say that the notions of beauty found throughout Western aesthetics are lineal descendants of some sort of Platonic conception of Beauty. In contrary to the above position, Duran later observed that in the late twentieth century things started to change in respect to this conception of aesthetics. The reason for 2

this change is connected with the current attitude of human beings to nature, where nature is regarded as a kind of force. One of the implications of this belated understanding of nature is that human beings nowadays regard degradation of the environment as their own degradation and therefore aesthetics is no longer seen in detached and disinterested perspectives. In contrast to Western conception of aesthetics, the Yoruba (African) aesthetics is closely and inextricably linked to her metaphysics. As Onyenwuenyi (1984, 242) observes: Its (aesthetics) theory or standard of evaluation must conform to the theories of its sister disciplines and stem identical metaphysical foundations. Hence African art is functional, community-oriented, depersonalized, contextualized, and embedded. In the same vein, Duran (2006, 39) while comparing European aesthetics with Yoruba aesthetics observes that Yoruba aesthetics is predicated upon the Yoruba world view in the sense that one cannot remove oneself from one s self concerns and peculiarities because these concerns are intimately linked to cosmological functioning. The essential point being made by these scholars is that aesthetics cannot be divorced from specific cultural and historical realities. The position has captured the kernel of sociology of knowledge in our time, to the effect that all branches of knowledge are interconnected and that they serve the function of connecting knowledge with the concrete realities of human beings in different cultures and in different historical periods. Thus, aesthetic expressions, judgments and attitudes are always related to concrete life situations of the artist and his/her socio-cultural realities, be it ethical, social, economic and political. Yoruba art forms and ethical, social and political behaviours Most of Yoruba art forms- proverbs, music, poems, films, story telling and oratory are didactic in character. They are meant to inculcate in persons, good behaviours both at personal and institutional levels. They do this by special appeal to the consciousness of the audience in order to bring about certain ethical, social and political attitudes which are meant to promote harmonious relationships between individuals and the community of which individuals are integral parts. These art forms are not just expressed in ordinary language; rather they are couched in aesthetically fascinating fashions that are captivating to the audience. Art forms are meant to induce particular ethical/political/social behaviour and this requires that the speaker or performer is well attuned to the existential realities around him/her at a particular time in the history of the people. Thus, ewa e de (beautiful language) is meant to induce ewa iẁa (beautiful character) in the participants in any Yoruba art form. Music/songs (orin) is an important art form among the Yoruba. According to Levinson (2005, 232) music is sounds temporarily organized by a person for the purpose of enriching or intensifying experience through active engagement (e.g. listening, dancing and performing) with the sounds regarded primarily, or in significant measure as sounds Within the Yoruba context, the function of music goes beyond mere listening, dancing and performing to the sounds of music; rather it is meant to induce a particular (ethical, social, courageous) behaviour on the part of a given hearer or audience. Music is capable of effecting change in behaviour or action of a person to whom the music is intended. Two illustrations of what we are saying here suffice from Fagunwa books: Ogboju Ode Ninu Igbo Irunmale (1950, 2005) and Igbo Olodumare (1949, 2005). In the first of the two books, Olo huǹ Iyo, one of the Courageous Seven (Akoni Me je) who volunteered to travel to O ke 3

Lańgbo do for the well- being of their state, used his melodious song to overwhelm E ru (Sinister spirit) who cannot be defeated by bullets and arrows of the most powerful among the group, Ka ko, Oniḱu mo Eku ǹ. By the same token, Oloẃo Aye, in the second book, having engaged E su Keḱere O de in a seemingly no win fight decided to sing a song that is capable of inducing a compromising attitude in Esu Kekere Ode. As a matter of fact, both occasions worked in favour of A ka ra Oo guǹ and Olowo Aye; Eru ran away from the Courageous Seven and Esu Kekere Ode made peace with Olowo Aye. These two examples illustrate the Yoruba saying that ohuǹ rere lo n yo obi lapo, ohuǹ buruku a yo ofa nińu apo. (Good exchange draws a kolanut (gift) from the pocket and a bad one draws an arrow from its sheath). In the next section we shall briefly discuss conceptions of work in order to illustrate how art music expresses an ethical position about work as a productive activity. The Ethics of work: A philosophical overview Work as productive activity is a universal phenomenon. However, Gbadegesin (1991) has made a distinction between many human activities that are productive and work. According to him, the need and raison d être of work is embedded in both oral and written narratives across cultures. According to Gbadegesin (1991) work is one of the essential activities of the human condition. Through work, nature is transformed in various ways, directly or indirectly, to produce the material conditions of life. Work has been categorised as manual and non- manual. This can further be divided into two according to the degree of freedom of choice and operation which the worker enjoys, as well as the amount of satisfaction he/she derives from work. Manual workers are either wage labourers, working for a person or an organisation and artisan/crafts people who are on their own. Non-manual workers can also be divided into two-those that are often called white collar workers who work either in the private or the public sector. The other group falls to persons who make use of their talents towards their own unique development of their potentialities. Whether a person works for another person, organisation or for herself, the commitment to what one is doing in form of work is always valued. Philosophers across different ages and culture have disagreed about what constitutes the meaning of work. While some have identified work with the physical exertion of the body, others believed that it is only the mental exertion on nature that constitutes work. Experience shows that both manual and non-manual works are essential to transform nature for the production of the material conditions of life. What is important is that human beings are made up of physical and mental attributes and it makes sense to suggest that both attributes play important roles in the transformation of the natural and social environment for the production of the material conditions of life. The Yoruba saying that alagbara ma lero, baba ole (A person having physical strength without (mental) plan is really a lazy person) exemplifies the roles played by both physical and mental abilities in the meaning of work. There is no culture that condones laziness; for laziness is antithetical to the essential need for transformation of the natural and social conditions of life for the purpose of producing the material conditions for life. Within the African society, persons frown upon laziness. A lazy person is not even regarded as a genuine person, given the fact that she or he does not contribute to the material welfare of the community, especially when he/she has the opportunity and the physical and mental abilities to do so. Nyerere (1995, 67) for 4

example, noted that, in traditional African society, everybody was a worker. There was no other way of earning a living for the community. Even the elder, who appeared to be enjoying himself without doing any work and for whom everybody else appeared to be working, had in fact worked hard all his younger days Nyerere also believed that everybody must work in order to contribute to the public wealth. Consequently, apart from the child or the infirm, nobody is expected to be an idler. Certain ethical conclusions could be drawn from this short analysis about the concept of work. The first is that work is essentially bound with the human person. This is evidenced in the Biblical and philosophical accounts of work in which it is believed that it is human labour that creates wealth. The necessity for work is replicated in an aspect of the original sin in which all human beings have been condemned to work, just like the Sartrean phrase that human beings are condemned to freedom. The belief in work as a universal phenomenon could be linked to the values of freedom, fairness and equity. This is because every person is expected to contribute his/her own effort into a common wealth and by so doing, nobody will feel cheated within a community in which its essential nature is tied to the necessity to work in order to produce the material condition for its well-being. Furthermore, no person is expected to be a parasite on another person. Even when the traditional African society believes that hospitality is a virtue, the society does not believe in one person being parasitic on another. Again, Nyerere reminds us of the Swahili saying translated as, Treat your guest as a guest for two days; on the third day, give him a hoe! In the next section of this paper, this conception and ethics of work will be illustrated by a track in one of the albums of Sholla Allyson Obaniyi, ADUN (Galaxy Music, September, 12, 2012).In the tract, Sholla Allyson Obaniyi expresses the Yoruba ethical view concerning the necessity for human beings to engage in productive activity, thereby illustrating the existential connection between a work of art (aesthetics) and human conduct (ethics) Sholla Allyson Obaniyi: Music as expression of ethics of work. In line with other classical and modern thinkers like Aristotle and Mar, the Yoruba believe that work is essentially a human activity. This is exemplified in one of the age old Yoruba poems: Ise loo guǹ i se Muŕa siśe re o re mi Ise la fi n deni giǵa Bi a ko ba reńi fe hiǹti Bi o le la a ri Bi a ko ba reńi gbeḱe le A tera mośe eni Iỳa ŕe le loẃo lϙẃϙ Ki ba ba leśin leé kaǹ Bi ó ba gbo ju le won O te tań ni mo so fuń o Iya nbe fuń omo ti ko gboń Work is the antidote for poverty My friend take your work seriously It is work that uplifts a person If there is no supporter One is like a lazy person If there is no one to rely upon One takes his/her work seriously Your mother might be wealthy And your father exceedingly rich If you rely on their riches You will be terribly disappointed Suffering awaits the unwise child 5

Ekuń uń be fuń omo to nsa kiri Ma faàŕo sere o re mi Muŕa siśe ojo uń lo. Tears await the unthinking child Do not joke with your early days Be hardworking, for time flies. Obaniyi adopts this poem in track three of her Album, ADUǸ ( Galaxy Music, September, 2012) as follows: 1. O re mi ma rosẹ My friend do not be lazy 2. Ma fa si ko so fo, muŕa giŕi si se rẹ Waste no time, do your work with all seriousness 3. Ma duŕo, ma rosẹ Do not tarry, do not be lazy 4. Ise loò guǹ i se, muŕa si se re o re mi Work is the antidote for poverty, take your work seriously 5. Bi a ko ba reńi fe hiǹti, bi o le laà ri One appears to be lazy when one does not have a supporter 6. Bi á ko ba reńi gbeḱe le, a tera mośe eni When there is no one to rely on, we face our work squarely 7. Iỳa re le loẃo loẃo, ki ba ba leśin leé kaǹ Your parents may be very wealthy 8. Bi o ba gbo ju le won o te tań ni mo so fuń o If you rely on their riches you will be disappointed 9. Te te tera mo se Please, work very hard 10. Eniti o laṕa ti ó fi sise One who has hands and does not want to work 11. Aso iỳa ni o fi bora suǹ He/she will be covered with poverty 12. Ma fa si ko so fo muŕa siśe ojo n lo Do not waste time, time is moving fast 13. O re mi ma rose My friend, do not be lazy 14.I se la fi ndeni giǵa, apaĺara i guǹpa niye kan One is uplifted through hard work, one s hand is one s total being 15. Oníse i joba tepa mośe, a ki sise i joba laàǵuǹ Civil servants work hard, do not take public job as nobody s job 16. Oniśe owo tepa mośe Artisans, take your work seriously 17. Ise di e, oorun di é, oǹa i se ni yen Mixing work with idleness paves way for poverty 18. Oniśoẁo muŕa si se re Business person, take your work seriously 19. Ma fo le ko le ta se bi ta Do not employ laziness to pave way to poverty 20. E mi so te mi I have spoken 21. O o niśe loẃo won pe alaáru o saŕe lo The unemployed person hardly have a choice in relation to a job offer 22. Woò ebi a pa o enu re a guǹ de I ba daǹ You will be harshly treated with hunger. 23. Te te muŕa si se Take your work seriously 24. O lẹ ji loẃuro, o yi aso moŕi A lazy person is always uncomfortable at the beginning of a new day 25. O san poń o saŕe kiri Only becoming serious when it is noon, when the day has gone so far. 6

26. O di oju ale o n saŕe kiri Running helter-skelter seeking for help when it is too late 27. Eǹiỳaǹ mi e tera mośe My people take your work seriously 28. Eniti o ba sise ko gbodϙ jeun He who does not work should not eat 29. O ro Oluẃa lo wi beé This is God s injunction 30. Oniýań nḱe e woju iyań One who works advertises her business 31. Olo be nḱe e woju obe A worker has something to advertise 32. A tije a timu ni gbogbo wa nẃa kiri Everybody works in order to eat 33. O le tió fi nkaǹkan bole A lazy person who does not plant anything 34. Kini Ele duẁa maá bu si? What would God bless? 35. Riŕi lo nsaa ju ji je You have to work before you eat 36. Eniti o ri ḱan ko le je nkaǹ Without working you cannot become somebody 37. Eǹiỳaǹ mi e tera mośe My people, work hard 38. Ise loo guǹ ise, e tera mośe Work is an antidote to poverty 39. Ojo nlo e tera ḿośe Time waits for nobody, work hard. A Philosophical analysis of the song Lines 1-3. In these lines, the artist (Sholla Obaniyi) exhorts her audience about the need to work and shun laziness. Lines 4-6: The artist stresses the human virtue of autonomy as a means to selffulfilment Lines 7-9: The artist emphasises the ethical position that persons should be independent through hard work and that they should not wholly rely on the achievement of their progenitors, especially their immediate parents. In the African society, it is always regarded as a self-deception when a young man/woman wholly relies on the wealth of parents in order to make it in life. Lines 10-12: The artist stresses that poverty is a logical outcome of laziness and given that poverty is a negative human experience, persons should work in order to avoid poverty. On a critical reflection, however, these lines are oblivious of the fact that poverty may not necessarily result from lack of work; poverty may be as a result of the structural relations between persons in a given society. Lines 13-15: Obayemi stresses the fact that there is dignity in labour and that a person who believes in work- hard-work, is an ethically regarded person. Lines 16-20: Obayemi does not discriminate between the commitment to work in whatever situation we find ourselves, whether as a self- employed person or as a civil servant. This is a warning to certain civil servants who entertain the belief that public service is a means to cheat given the fact that whether one works hard on not one is going to get paid at the end of the month. Lines 21-23: In these lines, the artist points attention to the need for the unemployed not to shun any employment offer. This is because half bread is better than none. This is an admonition to the young graduate who is insisting on a particular job as the only alternative to unemployment. 7

Lines 24-26: In these lines, Obaniyi draws attention to the consequences of laziness. According to her, laziness is the cause of lack of achievement and the consequence is that such a person will live an unfulfilled life. Lines 27-29: The artist emphasises the necessity to work as a universal experience given the fact that work is an injunction which dates back to the beginning of time and which is still regarded as a defining attribute of the human person. Lines 30-36. In these lines, Sholla Allyson Obaniyi recognises the metaphysical doctrine of cause and effect. For her, one who does not work cannot expect any material thing which can add to the quality of human life. This also stresses the importance of human freedom in our world where persons sometimes pray to God for the good things of life without necessarily putting enough effort to transform nature in order to produce the material conditions of life. Lines 37-39: Finally, The artist re-emphasises the fact that work, productive work, is the only antidote to poverty. This is a position that has been recognised across all civilizations. Conclusion What this paper has sought to do was to argue that there is an existential relationship between the two axiological disciplines in philosophy. This position is a response to a prevalent view that only seeks to find a logical connection between the two disciplines and that if this connection cannot be found, then there is no other connection available. The paper suggests that in the works of art, especially in music, the artist musician sometimes uses songs to reflect on certain existential situations, whether as experienced by him/her or as reflective of the social and cultural practices of a given people. This position was illustrated by the music of a Yoruba art musician, Sholla Allyson Obaniyi. On a broader philosophical note, the paper is an exemplification of the need to relate the philosophical discipline to all areas of human endeavour in an attempt to understand and appreciate the ethical, metaphysical and epistemological underpinnings of human cultures. References Ayer, A.J. (2001) Language, Truth and Logic. England: Penguin Books. Bewaji, J.A.I. (2003) Beauty and Culture: Perspectives in Black Aesthetics. Ibadan: Spectrum Books Ltd. Charlton, W. (1970) Aesthetics: An Introduction. London: Hutchinson University Library. Descartes, Rene (1911) Philosophical Works of Descartes. E.S. Haldane and G.T.R. Ross (eds.) Cambridge University Press. Duran, Jane (2006) Yoruba Work and Art Categorization Philosophia Africana 9:1, 35-40. Fagunwa, D.O. (1950,2005) Igbo Olodumare. Lagos: Thomas Nelson and Sons Ltd. (1949, 2005) Ogboju Ode Ninu Igbo Irunmale. Lagos: Thomas Nelson Ltd. Gbadegesin, Segun, (1991) African Philosophy: Traditional Yoruba Philosophy and Contemporary Realities. New York: Peter Lang. Hallen, Barry (2000) The Good, The Bad and the Beautiful. Bloomington and Indianapolis University Press. Hume, David (1955) An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. New York: The Liberal Arts Press. 8

Kennick, W.E. (1965) Does Traditional Aesthetics Rest on Miracle? in Cyril Barret (ed.) Collected Papers on Aesthetics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Pp. 1-23. Levinson, Jerrold (2005) On the Concept of Music in David Goldblatt and Lee B. (eds.) Aesthetics: A Reader in Philosophy of the Arts. New Jersey: Prentice Hall pp. 229-233. Moore, G.E (1978) Principia Ethica. London: Cambridge University Press. Obaniyi, Sholla Allyson. (2012) Adun. Lagos, Nigeria: Galaxy Music. Onyewuenyi, Innocent C. (1984) Traditional African Aesthetics: A Philosophical Perspective International Philosophical Quarterly. XXIV:3, 237-243. Plato (2000) The Republic in The Philsosopher s Handbook: Essential Readings from Plato to Kant. Stanley Rosen (ed.) USA: Random House. Rorty, Richard (2001) Consequences of Pragmatism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. 9