SIMON DUMAS PRIMBAULT European University Institute, Florence

Similar documents
Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

observation and conceptual interpretation

Introduction and Overview

(1) Writing Essays: An Overview. Essay Writing: Purposes. Essay Writing: Product. Essay Writing: Process. Writing to Learn Writing to Communicate

Ralph K. Hawkins Bethel College Mishawaka, Indiana

Spatial Formations. Installation Art between Image and Stage.

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

GV958: Theory and Explanation in Political Science, Part I: Philosophy of Science (Han Dorussen)

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

Any attempt to revitalize the relationship between rhetoric and ethics is challenged

Stenberg, Shari J. Composition Studies Through a Feminist Lens. Anderson: Parlor Press, Print. 120 pages.

Humanities Learning Outcomes

VISUAL ARTS. Overview. Choice of topic

Nature's Perspectives

Ontological and historical responsibility. The condition of possibility

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

The Debate on Research in the Arts

The Epistemological Status of Theoretical Simplicity YINETH SANCHEZ

What is Rhetoric? Grade 10: Rhetoric

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Article Critique: Seeing Archives: Postmodernism and the Changing Intellectual Place of Archives

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

TEST BANK. Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues

A STEP-BY-STEP PROCESS FOR READING AND WRITING CRITICALLY. James Bartell

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Owen Barfield. Romanticism Comes of Age and Speaker s Meaning. The Barfield Press, 2007.

Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

The Kelvingrove Review Issue 3

From Pythagoras to the Digital Computer: The Intellectual Roots of Symbolic Artificial Intelligence

1/9. The B-Deduction

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

Narrating the Self: Parergonality, Closure and. by Holly Franking. hermeneutics focus attention on the transactional aspect of the aesthetic

Care of the self: An Interview with Alexander Nehamas

234 Reviews. Radical History and the Politics of Art. By Gabriel Rockhill. New York: Columbia University Press, xi pages.

2 nd Grade Visual Arts Curriculum Essentials Document

Corcoran, J George Boole. Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2nd edition. Detroit: Macmillan Reference USA, 2006

Postmodernism. thus one must review the central tenants of Enlightenment philosophy

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner

EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PRAGMATISM AND AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY. The History of Reception of Charles S. Peirce in Greece 1

INTERVIEW: ONTOFORMAT Classical Paradigms and Theoretical Foundations in Contemporary Research in Formal and Material Ontology.

Pierre Hadot on Philosophy as a Way of Life. Pierre Hadot ( ) was a French philosopher and historian of ancient philosophy,

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Writing Guide for Term Paper Sociology 125 October, Regular assignment (i.e. for students not taking the course for honors credit)

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Emerging Questions: Fernando F. Segovia and the Challenges of Cultural Interpretation

SYLLABUSES FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS

Taiwan and the Auteur: The Forging of an Identity

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Thank you for choosing to publish with Mako: The NSU undergraduate student journal

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Durham Research Online

ARISTOTLE ON SCIENTIFIC VS NON-SCIENTIFIC DISCOURSE. Philosophical / Scientific Discourse. Author > Discourse > Audience

Review of Recursive Origins: Writing at the Transition to Modernity

ICOMOS ENAME CHARTER

Karen Hutzel The Ohio State University, Columbus, Ohio REFERENCE BOOK REVIEW 327

ISTORIANS TEND NOT TO BE VERY THEORETICAL; they prefer to work with

REFERENCE GUIDES TO RHETORIC AND COMPOSITION. Series Editor, Charles Bazerman

Four Characteristic Research Paradigms

Comparing Neo-Aristotelian, Close Textual Analysis, and Genre Criticism

Glossary of Rhetorical Terms*

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

1/10. The A-Deduction

These are some notes to give you some idea of the content of the lecture they are not exhaustive, nor always accurate! So read the referenced work.

Tamar Sovran Scientific work 1. The study of meaning My work focuses on the study of meaning and meaning relations. I am interested in the duality of

Scientific Revolutions as Events: A Kuhnian Critique of Badiou

Early Daoism and Metaphysics

Current Issues in Pictorial Semiotics

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA PRESS ADVERTISING RATES & INFORMATION

The Ancient Philosophers: What is philosophy?

Hoyningen Symposium Systematicity: The Nature of Science

Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates Republic Symposium Republic Phaedrus Phaedrus), Theaetetus

Principal version published in the University of Innsbruck Bulletin of 4 June 2012, Issue 31, No. 314

The Power of Ideas: Milton Friedman s Empirical Methodology

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

My thesis is that not only the written symbols and spoken sounds are different, but also the affections of the soul (as Aristotle called them).

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

PETER - PAUL VERBEEK. Beyond the Human Eye Technological Mediation and Posthuman Visions

Université Libre de Bruxelles

The History of Philosophy. and Course Themes

The Information. A History, a Theory, a Flood.

ENGLISH I STAAR EOC REVIEW. Reporting Category 1 Understanding and Analysis across Genres

Chapter 2: Reading for the Main Idea and Author s Purpose

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

MIRA COSTA HIGH SCHOOL English Department Writing Manual TABLE OF CONTENTS. 1. Prewriting Introductions 4. 3.

Derrida, Structure, Sign and Play in the Discourse of the Human Sciences. Part One, or When is a centre not a centre?

Writing an Honors Preface

Chapter Abstracts. Re-imagining Johannesburg: Nomadic Notions

Leverhulme Research Project Grant Narrating Complexity: Communication, Culture, Conceptualization and Cognition

Transcription:

Raphaële Garrod, Cosmographical Novelties in French Renaissance Prose (1550-1630) Dialectic and Discovery Turnhout (Belgium), Brepols Publishers, 2016 [ISBN: 9782503550459; 100 excl. tax] SIMON DUMAS PRIMBAULT European University Institute, Florence Since the reappraisal of the supposed Scientific Revolution by the historiography of knowledge, an expansive literature has been published on the making of facts in early modern natural philosophy. In particular, historians of knowledge and science have dwelled on the many technologies pertaining to the apparently paradoxical construction of facts, or invention of discoveries technologies ranging from theories through to field work and experimental instruments. Although so-called literary technologies have not escaped this focus, they have been too often reduced to publication and diffusion strategies, considering text as a mere medium of communication. Yet the rhetoric and poetics of science have much to tell us about how language itself shapes the scholarly view of the natural world; in other words, how scientific objectivity proper is also constructed through the use of words and arguments. By focusing on the rhetorical and poetic fabric of the written text (p.13), Raphaële Garrod s work intends to shed light on how dialectic as a literary technology helped early modern scholars in constructing facts and inventing discoveries. Based on thorough study of the argumentative structure of five early modern French publications on cosmology and cosmography, Cosmographical Novelties in French Renaissance Prose concentrates on how novelties understood as epistemological disturbances to the doxa (p.207) are dealt with from a dialectical and rhetorical point of view, so as to be granted discursive existence (p.3), censored, or tailored to fit in the expected framework. My main interest in this book lies in the literary epistemology it unveils for early modern natural philosophy as well as the one it deploys in twenty-first-century historiography, and the link between both. After a linear critical summary of the content of the book, I will consider each of these epistemologies in turn. The Discursive Existence of Novelties After a brief word history of the term novelty and the mise en intrigue of the epistemic troubles it raises, Garrod states her main objective in simple terms: how are novelties invented that is at once discovered and constructed through the use of rhetorical loci? (p.3) To try to answer that question, she focuses on five books of Cromohs (Cyber Review of Modern Historiography), ISSN 1123-7023, 20/2015-16 Firenze University Press

COSMOGRAPHICAL NOVELTIES IN FRENCH RENAISSANCE PROSE cosmology and cosmography published between 1575 and 1664. In these times of great epistemological shifts for cosmography with the Great Voyages and the humanist rediscovery of classics, as well as cosmology through the observations and modelling of Copernicus, Kepler, and Galileo, dialectic and rhetoric as disciplines and as intellectual tools were undergoing major changes. Indeed, at the turn of the 17 th century, a scholastic, logical tradition of dialectic overlapped with a humanist, rhetorical one while the mid-century rhetorical turn would eventually put an end to dialectic-as-logic (pp.9-10), thus paving the way for a modern use of language as a supposedly simple and transparent, hence objective, medium. The historiographical relevance of the five books is put forward on the basis of their intended audience vernacular readers and therefore of their diffusion and circulation, as well as of the wider philosophical project they undertake and epitomize (pp.30-34). Although the choice of these five sources is perfectly relevant, we could ask whether only printed published texts every single one of these last three words is of utmost importance were deemed worth studying. Perhaps a more variegated, albeit limited, selection of sources would have allowed the author to address more deeply the ontological issue that rhetoric and dialectic raise I will return to this in more detail later. The first chapter of this book is intended as a brief history of dialectic as a discipline and of its links with natural philosophy. Based on a selection of nine textbooks spanning from Aristotle through Boethius to Eustachius, this brief history highlights the ever-changing normative ideals of dialectic and rhetoric, their relation, and their use in argumentation. This chapter is a good introduction to dialectic understood in Aristotelian terms as the art of debating about probable issues (p.38), as opposed to syllogistic and more particularly to the loci, that is the argumentative structures used to construct a probable demonstration, such as from similars, from testimony, and from description. This chapter extends into no less than five appendices (pp.321-363) recapitulating every single locus and all the definitions and uses they had according to each of the nine textbooks a precious toolbox for someone eager to engage in similar inquiries. The strength of this first chapter is to get to the heart of the matter immediately: even though it is a brief aside on the sole normative aspects of dialectic and rhetoric as they were taught, it nonetheless makes prominent the important and too often neglected epistemological role dialectic and rhetoric play(ed) in natural philosophy. Now, apart from this main thesis, to which I will return, Raphaële Garrod also addresses a number of secondary issues in each chapter. After the first and introductory chapter, the book is divided in two parts containing respectively two and three chapters. The first part of the book, comprising chapters two and three, is Cromohs 20/2015-16 - p. 133

SIMON DUMAS PRIMBAULT devoted to cosmological novelties cosmology being understood as the part of natural philosophy concerned with the study of the universe as a whole. Chapter two, by comparing the uses of loci in Pierre de la Primaudaye s Troisième tome de l Académie françoise (1590) and Etienne Binet s Pour parler des cieux et de ses merveilles in Essay des merveilles de nature (1621), aims at showing how arguments of similitude, authority, or definition turn natural philosophical knowledge of the universe into theological tools for the parallel interpretation of nature and scripture. Therefore, Garrod intends to nuance the Harrison s hypothesis according to which the Reformation s biblical literalism has had a huge influence on the development of science during the early modern period the Protestant emphasis on the literal meaning of scriptures would have fostered a new hermeneutic highly profitable for science. Raphaële Garrod argues instead that French Huguenots were influenced by Hermetic or Neoplatonic doctrines that led to a redefinition of biblical literalism. In chapter three, the author focuses on two sharp critiques of dialectic and authority: Montaigne s Apologie de Raimond Sebond in his Essais (written between 1572 and 1592) and Descartes Le Monde (written between 1630 and 1633). Though both authors have the same target, they do not have the same objective. While Montaigne s criticism is fostered by his scepticism there can be no unique truth for human knowledge nor can there be any consensus ending dialectical debates, Descartes aims at promoting his epistemology of clear and distinct ideas no need for debate nor bookish authorities as incommensurably opposed to scholasticism. Garrod s stance regarding that confrontation is that the counterpart of such a slating of dialectic can only be a growing rhetorical and poetic use of loci as persuasive devices and as structures of cosmological fiction (p.153): for Montaigne to equate philosophy with poetry and sophistry, for Descartes as an intellectual tool to support his renewed and demonstrative mechanical philosophy. The second part of the book, composed of chapters four, five, and six, focuses on cosmographical novelties proper, cosmography being the description of the earth within the greater system of the world (p.212), the fourth chapter aiming to clarify cosmographical terms and disciplines through a quick review of the existing literature. Chapters five and six are indeed attempting to clarify the fragmentation of cosmography and the birth of geography by studying François de Belleforest s La Cosmographie universelle de tout le monde (1575), a translation and rewriting of Sebastian Münster s Cosmographica universalis (1550) that here acts as an unacknowledged sixth historical source. In the short period that separates both publications, Garrod witnesses an important change in the use of the locus from authority : while Münster uses it as a safeguard to protect the doxa by censoring any novelty, Belleforest systematically (re)assesses authorities in a critical manner. These discursive transfers of authority (p.4) are for Raphaële Garrod what permitted the cosmographical Cromohs 20/2015-16 - p. 134

COSMOGRAPHICAL NOVELTIES IN FRENCH RENAISSANCE PROSE revolution that replaced the elemental sphere of cosmology with a more geographical representation of our planet as a body made of earth and water. Furthermore, in the course of this process, Garrod identifies the birth of national geography as a discipline through Belleforest s use of the locus from notation to derive national borders from historical criteria. A Literary Epistemology Shedding light on the epistemic uses and criticisms of dialectic and rhetoric in the writing of cosmological and cosmographical essays in French Renaissance prose, Raphaële Garrod succeeds in unveiling a wide world of scholars for whom the natural philosophical discourse is not of pure necessity such as Descartes would have us believe with his clear and distinct ideas, Leibniz with his characteristica universalis or Newton with his prisca sapientia; scholars for whom knowledge is intrinsically debatable, for whom nature is in-between necessity and contingency as Melanchthon himself states (p.77). Be it for the sceptical reasons of Montaigne, for whom poetry and speculation amount to the same thing, or for epistemically grounded ones, the conscious and nonconscious uses these scholars made of dialectical loci speak in favour of an ontological reappraisal of the modal status of natural-philosophical knowledge during the early modern period. All the more so as, by the mid-17 th century, a rhetorical turn was occurring that would sweep everything away and root out the long-standing myth of (the existence of a) language as a mere, hence clear and distinct, medium of communication. Beyond epistemological issues, dialectic thus raises ontological ones and, indeed, for Ramus and Melanchthon (pp.73-82) as well as for Eustachio (p.93), dialectic is partly grounded in ontology (p.42) for, contrary to syllogistic which draws its demonstrative efficacy from the form of the propositions, dialectic does so from the matter of the terms implicated. Antique ontological issues that are nonetheless at the heart of contemporary dialectical debates in history and philosophy of science. Focusing on this period and these disciplines, Raphaële Garrod accomplishes with verve her goal of going beyond the traditional polar opposites of intellectual history such as bookish knowledge versus experience or dialectical versus analytical (p.4), for it is precisely the crossing of these dichotomies that she investigates. Hence, she brilliantly and dialectically demonstrates how words and arguments are as many tools and instruments used in the making of natural philosophical novelties, in just the same way as telescopes, air-pumps, and field samples. Addressing epistemological disturbances this way, Garrod also succeeds in bringing early modern science closer to the historiographical practice of debate and Cromohs 20/2015-16 - p. 135

SIMON DUMAS PRIMBAULT consensus through rhetoric and poetic (p.292sq) a rapprochement worth making today while the contemporary historical discipline is claiming its scientificity. Yet it seems at the very conclusion of her work that the author yields to the Cartesian perspective, arguing that the effectiveness of dialectic rested on the frailty of an Aristotelian ontology under attack as if we could detach the ontological enterprise from the use of words, for there would be an object already there before its mise en texte (p.5), just waiting for its integration (p.318). This said, if ontology is indeed displaced during this period through the reorganisation of the scholarly landscape between natural philosophy, experimental philosophy, and mathematical physics, we do find such dialectic and rhetorical threads in the fabric of the myriad mechanical philosophies that are as many supposedly steady ontological grounds. By considering only printed published texts, I think that the author has only been able to draw part of the picture regarding that specific issue. A quick look at the socalled method of invention revealed by drafts and notes, for example as opposed to the method of exposition that the printed published texts reveal, could allow us to go beyond the mise en texte and take into account the fact that there can be no thinking without textual operations, and that there is actually no strict dichotomy between invention and exposition, as if they were two separate and successive intellectual operations. Thus, discursive existence is not just a supplementary, hence dispensable, ontological layer. It is rather a mode of existence. Something silenced is not merely refused discursive existence it is not censored discovery, it is properly refused existence it is not discovery. Despite Descartes clear and distinct ideas, ontology is intrinsically entwined with the use of language, it is always a matter of dialectic and rhetoric. History as a Dialectic Such a use of language is not necessarily conscious or intentional and that is where Raphaële Garrod s philosophy of history-as-a-dialectic is of utmost importance. Indeed, by looking at the argumentative structure of such sources and by acknowledging that she is investigating neither authorial intentions nor conscious manipulations of precise sources (p.64), Garrod bypasses the straightforward issue concerning what the authors wanted to do even in terms of speech acts and focuses rather on how they did what they actually did. She therefore judiciously goes beyond the mere meaning of the text in its etymological sense of intending or having in mind to address its proper poetic and rhetorical fabric, which betrays not solely what the text means but most importantly what it does not mean. Garrod makes the text talk; she makes it say more than it would have wanted to say, more than it actually means. Cromohs 20/2015-16 - p. 136

COSMOGRAPHICAL NOVELTIES IN FRENCH RENAISSANCE PROSE Although it would have benefited from a short discussion on the use of the English language to write a book about French prose a choice that might be profitable as well, for translation may also smooth linguistic bias (e.g. p.121 and pp.169-170), it is thanks to this extremely stimulating hermeneutics that Raphaële Garrod unravels the latent mechanisms at work in the natural philosophical thought of the early modern period: faint stirrings deep under the surface of a conscious writing that nonetheless are the cause of the waves and currents; somehow dormant thought processes that only such a historical reading may reveal. Choosing this object and this perspective, Garrod is under no illusion that she is attempting the construction of a supposedly scientific fact it might not state a fact, but it brings forth a valid meaning (p.64) and this is worth emphasising, all the more so today while scientificity is dangerously appealing to the practice of history, even though being scientific is no longer a title of nobility. Hence, the thinking and writing of this book are themselves rooted in rhetoric and dialectic as acknowledged by the author herself (p.64): taking chance into account, relying on probable reasoning, making use of loci, and most importantly opening a space for debate far beyond an illusion of historical objectivity. As a concluding remark, the author underlines the epistemic ambivalence (p.318) generated by the use of dialectical invention, for there was no unique way to grant discursive existence to novelties, no straightforward path to the resolution of such epistemic disturbances. Hence the large number of variegated natural philosophical world-views competing in the early modern scholarly world; hence also the epistemic shift from the search for the ontological grounds of the natural world towards the construction of models on the basis of experiment i.e. empiricism (p.317). Thus echoing issues raised by historical research, thus deconstructing the intertwining of an early modern literary epistemology and a contemporary history as a dialectic, Raphaële Garrod accomplishes the difficult task of recasting the issues raised both by the practice of science and the practice of history on common matters relating to modality and objectivity, reopening the dialectical debate about the rhetorical and poetic invention of the world by scholarly endeavours. As such, this book does indeed bring forth a valid meaning (p.64). *** Cromohs 20/2015-16 - p. 137