The Concept of "Third Cultures" in Intercultural Ethics. - Richard Evanoff

Similar documents
Intercultural Ethics: A Constructivist Approach. Richard Evanoff

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

The Research on Habermas' Communicative Action Theory

Mass Communication Theory

Normative and Positive Economics

REFERENCES. 2004), that much of the recent literature in institutional theory adopts a realist position, pos-

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Kent Academic Repository

Lia Mela. Democritus University of Thrace. Keywords: modernity, reason, tradition, good, Frankfurt School, MacIntyre, Taylor

Todd Hedrick

Review by Răzvan CÎMPEAN

UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO INSTRUCTORSHIPS IN PHILOSOPHY CUPE Local 3902, Unit 1 SUMMER SESSION 2019

Habermas and the Project of Immanent Critique Titus Stahl

Back to Basics: Appreciating Appreciative Inquiry as Not Normal Science

An essay on Alasdair MacIntyre s Relativism. Power and Philosophy

Marxist Criticism. Critical Approach to Literature

Black Marxism And American Constitutionalism An Interpretive History From The Colonial Background To The Ascendancy Of Barack Obama

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Idealism and Pragmatism: "Transcendent" Validity Claims in Habermas's Democratic Theory

Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Theory and Society.

Critical Theory. Mark Olssen University of Surrey. Social Research at Frankfurt-am Main in The term critical theory was originally

Deconstruction is a way of understanding how something was created and breaking something down into smaller parts.

SYA 4010: Sociological Theory Florida State University Fall 2017 T/TH, 2 3:15pm, HCB 214

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought

Philip Joseph Kain. Santa Clara University Scotts Valley, CA Santa Clara, CA fax

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Discourse analysis is an umbrella term for a range of methodological approaches that

AXIOLOGY OF HOMELAND AND PATRIOTISM, IN THE CONTEXT OF DIDACTIC MATERIALS FOR THE PRIMARY SCHOOL

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

BDD-A Universitatea din București Provided by Diacronia.ro for IP ( :46:58 UTC)

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

Holliday Postmodernism

Mitchell ABOULAFIA, Transcendence. On selfdetermination

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

The Capitalist Unconscious Marx And Lacan

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Logic and argumentation techniques. Dialogue types, rules

Kent Academic Repository

Reading/Study Guide: Lyotard. The Postmodern Condition

An Analysis of Communication Theory in the Media

Moral Geography and Exploration of the Moral Possibility Space

Colonnade Program Course Proposal: Explorations Category

SOED-GE.2325: The Learning of Culture Fall 2015, Wednesdays, 10:40 a.m. 12:20 p.m.

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

personality, that is, the mental and moral qualities of a figure, as when we say what X s character is

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Sociological theories: the tradition and current notions pt II

INTRODUCTION TO THE POLITICS OF SOCIAL THEORY

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner

Idealism and Pragmatism: Transcendent Validity Claims in Habermas s Democratic Theory

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Social Semiotic Techniques of Sense Making using Activity Theory

Exploration of New Understanding of Culture. Yogi Chaitanya Prakash, Osaka University, Japan

Literary Criticism. Literary critics removing passages that displease them. By Charles Joseph Travies de Villiers in 1830

Marxism and Education. Series Editor Anthony Green Institute of Education University of London London, United Kingdom

Adorno - The Tragic End. By Dr. Ibrahim al-haidari *

KEY ISSUES IN SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY Dept. of Sociology and Social Anthropology, CEU Autumn 2017

Chapter 2: Karl Marx Test Bank

Decisions, Actions, and Consequences

Course Structure for Full-time Students. Course Structure for Part-time Students

CONTEMPORARY SOCIAL THEORY

Watcharabon Buddharaksa. The University of York. RCAPS Working Paper No January 2011

Philosophy Department Electives Fall 2017 (All listings are

If Leadership Were a Purely Rational Act We Would be Teaching Computers. Chester J. Bowling, Ph.D. Ohio State University Extension

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

Capstone Design Project Sample

Nicholas Vrousalis Philippe Van Parijs. Analytical Marxism

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

MARXISM AND EDUCATION

City, University of London Institutional Repository. This version of the publication may differ from the final published version.

Environmental Ethics: From Theory to Practice

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Course Description. Alvarado- Díaz, Alhelí de María 1. The author of One Dimensional Man, Herbert Marcuse lecturing at the Freie Universität, 1968

Notes 2 CLASSICAL LIBERALISM 3 MODERN LIBERALISM

PH th Century Philosophy Ryerson University Department of Philosophy Mondays, 3-6pm Fall 2010

MARXISM AND MORALITY. Sean Sayers. University of Kent

Decolonizing Development Colonial Power and the Maya Edited by Joel Wainwright Copyright by Joel Wainwright. Conclusion

The Rhetorical Structure of Editorials in English, Swedish and Finnish Business Newspapers

University of Huddersfield Repository

Course Description. Course objectives

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

Media as practice. a brief exchange. Nick Couldry and Mark Hobart. Published as Chapter 3. Theorising Media and Practice

Harris Wiseman, The Myth of the Moral Brain: The Limits of Moral Enhancement (Cambridge, MA and London: The MIT Press, 2016), 340 pp.

GV958: Theory and Explanation in Political Science, Part I: Philosophy of Science (Han Dorussen)

Semiotics of culture. Some general considerations

Columbia University Center for Contemporary Critical Thought. Fall 2015 Seminar. The Idea of a Critical Political Theory. Professor Linda Zerilli

Assistant Professor in Philosophy, Cornell University (reappointed in 1969 to second 3-year term, resigned in 1970).

Introduction: Varieties of Social Constructionism and the Rituals of Critique

SECTION I: MARX READINGS

Interpretive and Critical Research Traditions

THE RELATIONS BETWEEN ETHICS AND ECONOMICS: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS BETWEEN AYRES AND WEBER S PERSPECTIVES. By Nuria Toledano and Crispen Karanda

Key Term: Anti-Kantian Aesthetics. Peter Blouw. Innovative, influential, and always somewhat controversial, Immanuel Kant s

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

The Hegel Marx Connection


EXPANDED COURSE DESCRIPTIONS UC DAVIS PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT SPRING, Michael Glanzberg MWF 10:00-10:50a.m., 176 Everson CRNs:

Transcription:

The Concept of "Third Cultures" in Intercultural Ethics - Richard Evanoff 1933-8 Hazama-Cho Hachioji-Shi, Tokyo 193-0941 Email: evanoff@sipeb.aoyama.ac.jp Eubios Journal of Asian and International Bioethics 10 (2000), 126-129. Existing views of cultural adaptation in the field of intercultural communication suggest that it is the sole responsibility of people who are visiting or living in foreign cultures_"sojourners" as they are referred to in the literature_to adapt themselves to the cultural norms of their host cultures. This paper will criticize dominant theories of adaptation and show how the concept of "third cultures" offers a better model for understanding how people with different cultural norms interact with each other in cross-cultural situations. The concept of "third cultures" can be applied to a variety of cross-cultural problems in the fields of bioethics and environmental ethics. The concept of adaptation, as it has been developed in the theory of intercultural communication (see especially Furnham and Bocher 1986; Ellingsworth 1988; Kim 1989; Kim 1991; and the essays in Kim and Gudykunst 1988), emphasizes the necessity of sojourners adapting themselves to the norms of the host culture. This view is expressed in the popular slogan, "When in Rome do as the Romans do." In this model, the adaptive process is entirely one-way, with the burden for adaptation resting entirely with the sojourner. The notion that host cultures should also make efforts to adapt themselves to the needs and values of sojourners is missing. While sojourners are expected to "respect" the values of their host cultures, no burden is placed on host cultures to respect the values of sojourners. Sojourners are thus unable to critically reflect on whether the norms of their host cultures are really worth adopting or not, and host cultures are unable to critically reflect on the possible positive contributions that the norms of sojourners could make to their own cultures. This view of cultural adaptation is modeled on the concept of biological adaptation which, in classical Darwinian theory, sees adaptation as a matter of organisms fitting themselves into ready-made natural environments. The classical theory has been criticized more recently, however, by dialectical biologists (Levins and Lewontin 1985) who argue that the relationship between organisms and their environments is not one-way, but dialectical. Organisms both constitute and are constituted by their natural environments, in what Rose, Kamin, and Lewontin refer to as the "interpenetration of organism and environment" (1984, 272). Organisms cannot be understood apart from the environments they inhabit, while environments cannot be understood apart from the organisms which inhabit them. In Lewontin's words, "...an environment is nature organized by an organism" (1982, 160). Organisms do not simply find preexisting niches within a fixed ecosystem but rather create those niches by modifying their environments. Interactions between organisms and their environments are complex and reciprocal. Cause is multidirectional rather than unidirectional: organisms both change and are changed by their environments. This relationship is best described as "coevolutionary" (Durham 1978, 1991; Lumsden and Wilson 1981; Norgaard 1994) or "transactional" (Dewey 1949, 69; Weichhart 1993) because it involves mutual adaptation on the part of both organism and environment.

There are well-known difficulties with attempts to derive theories of culture from theories of biology (cf. Sahlins 1976), and any connection between the two is at best analogous. Arguments in favor of a dialectical view of the relationship between individuals and cultures, while similar in logic to the relationship between organisms and environments, must be developed independently. Probably the best attempt thus far to develop a dialectical view of the relationship between individuals and cultures can be found in social constructionist theory (Berger and Luckman 1966). In the constructivist view, individuals are socialized into accepting the dominant views of reality given to them by their cultures. The socialization process involves not only accepting particular understandings of how the world is (i.e., knowledge), but also particular understandings of how the world should be acted in (i.e., values). Nonetheless, knowledge and values are themselves cultural creations. The world itself does not tell us how it should be understood or acted in, as naturalism contends. And precisely because knowledge and values are cultural constructions they can always be reconstructed in different ways. Individuals are capable of engaging in critical reflection on how the world is to be understood and acted in, and to thus transform existing social understandings and relationships. Cultural norms and laws are social constructs which constrain human freedom, but humans are nonetheless free to change the cultural norms and laws which govern their societies. The constructivist view is more radical than either traditional liberal voluntarism or Marxist determinism (cf. Bhaskar 1979; Giddens 1984, 1990, 1994). The liberal view sees individuals as being "free" to do what they want without recognizing the extent to which internalized social norms constrain individual action. Marxist determinism (e.g., Althusser 1971, 1977), on the other hand, sees individuals as being so constrained by the cultural norms that they have been socialized into that independent action is impossible. All thought is "false consciousness," arising out of existing social relations, and social change occurs only in the context of larger historical processes which individuals themselves have no control over. The constructivist view acknowledges that individuals are to a large extent socialized into accepting certain worldviews and cultural values, but nonetheless sees individuals as being able to step outside of their own culture and to criticize its norms and values. This "stepping out" may result in nothing more than alienation, i.e., the attempt to create alternative values which exist independently of the dominant culture but do not really challenge its ultimate legitimacy. Constructivism becomes radical, however, when people are empowered to actually change existing social norms and social structures. Constructivism can thus be linked to a radical democratic political theory which goes beyond both traditional liberalism and Marxism. Constructivists share with recent communitarian thinkers (Sandel 1982, 1996; MacIntyre 1985, 1988) the idea that individuals are to a large extent constituted by the cultures they inhabit and therefore that mutual moral obligations exist between individuals and society. Individuals must act in ways that take into account not only their own benefit but also the benefit of others. Societies as well have a moral obligation to provide for the good of their members. In the Aristotelian maxim good individuals cannot be produced in the absence of good societies and good societies cannot be produced in the absence of good individuals. Communitarians go wrong, however, if they completely suppress individual autonomy and see the individual as nothing more than a cog in the social machine. Here constructivists agree with liberal political theorists (Rawls 1971, 1996; Dworkin 1977) that certain fundamental individual rights must be protected. Liberals go wrong, however, if they think that society can be constructed purely on the basis of individuals seeking their own self-

interest. In the constructivist view the relationship between individuals and society is dialectical: each is mutually dependent on the other. In applying constructivist thought to the problem of cross-cultural dialogue on ethics (Evanoff 1996, 1998, 1999), it can be noted that the ethical norms individuals bring with them to the dialogue process tell them how to deal with people in the context of their own culture, not with people from another culture whose norms are different_thus the need to arrive at a shared set of ethical norms for cross-cultural interactions. There are at least three different ways in which cross-cultural dialogue on ethics can be approached. Modernist/foundational approaches attempt to ground ethics in a set of universal principles that are seen as being valid for all persons, irrespective of cultural background. The difficulty with this view is that it fails to acknowledge the extent to which all such principles are themselves cultural constructions, and thus ends up simply privileging one particular cultural perspective over others; historically this has most often been a Eurocentric worldview. Postmodern/relativist approaches avoid such "totalizing" by arguing that cross-cultural dialogue on ethics is impossible given the incommensurable nature of cultural discourses. But the difficulty with this view is that it provides no basis for joint action among people from different cultural backgrounds in situations in which require it. A third approach, and the one argued for here, is a constructivist approach which argues that if ethics is indeed a matter of social construction, then there is no reason why ethical principles and norms cannot be constructed across cultures as much as they are within cultures. Cross-cultural encounters create an entirely new context in which the rules that will govern the relations between cultures do not yet exist and hence must be constructed. New ethical frameworks can be negotiated through a process of cross-cultural dialogue which draws on, but does not remain bound by, the ethical insights contained in any one tradition. The constructivist position endorses the democratic principle most fully worked out by "discourse ethics" (Apel 1980; Benhabib 1986, 1992; Habermas 1989, 1993) that everyone who will be affected by the adoption of a particular norm should have the right to participate in the decision-making process through which the norm is constructed. Norms in this view arise directly out of the communicative process, occasioned by the need of individuals to coordinate their actions with others. They are not universal in a foundational sense, but apply only to the specific individuals involved. This caveat is important because it protects the ability of cultural groups which neither have nor want cross-cultural interactions with others to preserve their own culture from forced assimilation and other forms of cultural imperialism. In situations in which such interactions are either desired or inevitable, however, there is the need for individuals from the respective cultures to work out in advance the specific norms that will govern their interaction. It should not simply be assumed that the norms of the dominant culture will prevail, nor that the norms of the sojourner must be unquestioningly respected. The outcome of the dialogue process should, ideally, not be a mere compromise in which either or both of the sides is obliged to give up values deemed important to them, but rather an "integrative agreement" (Pruitt 1994) which combines positive aspects of each of the respective cultural traditions in a new conceptual framework, or what social psychologists would call a "higher order schema" (Stotland and Canon 1972, chap. 7). Reaching such agreements requires each of the two sides to critically reflect on existing norms within their respective cultural traditions, to distinguish positive and negative aspects of each, and to integrate the positive aspects into a new, more comprehensive perspective. The result will be a entirely new set of norms capable of dealing effectively with mutually shared problems. The similarities between this process and Hegelian dialectical logic should be obvious.

The success of the dialogue process can be determined by the pragmatic criteria of whether the problems are eventually resolved to the satisfaction of the interacting groups or not. Instead of simply comparing divergent and perhaps incommensurable cultural traditions with each other, the adequacy of the traditions can be tested against the particular problems to be solved. While each of the cultures may have something to contribute to the resolution of the problem, each may also be lacking in certain conceptual and normative resources which would help them to solve it. Since all cultures simplify the range of potential human experience, none can regard itself as "universal" and there can be no single culture which serves as a model for all others. Particular cultures offer myriad alternatives for human behavior. By engaging in cross-cultural dialogue we are able to extend the range of our own potential experience. Holenstein writes, "Foreign cultures give us access to possibilities of development which are apparently at our disposal by nature and which only circumstances prevent from appearing in our own culture. Different cultures develop different human skills to varying degrees" (1995, 76). This dialectical approach to cross-cultural dialogue involves the ability to not only appreciate cultural differences, but also to integrate aspects of various cultural traditions into our own ways of thinking and behaving (Bennett 1993)_a process that can be engaged in by both sojourners and their host cultures. Cross-cultural dialogue employs a transactional model of communication (Barnlund 1970) which moves beyond merely understanding or "respecting" cultural differences towards creating a "third culture" which combines elements of each of the participants' original cultures in novel ways. John Useem, one of the originators of the term "third culture" (Useem, Useem, and Donoghue 1963), defines it as "...cultural patterns inherited and created, learned and shared by the members of two or more different societies who are personally involved in relating their society, or segments thereof, to each other" (1971, 14). Yoshikawa has similarly spoken of a state of "dynamic inbetweenness" in cross-cultural exchanges between Asians and Westerners, a "third perspective" which "...does not represent exclusively either the Eastern perspective or the Western perspective" (1987, 329). Adler, quoting Tillich, contends that the development of a multicultural personality involves the creation of "...a third area beyond the bounded territories, an area where one can stand for a time without being enclosed in something tightly bounded" (1977, 26). The concept of "hybridity" has also gained currency in post-colonial cultural studies in Britain (Young 1995; Werbner and Modood 1997). In attempting to maintain nationalistic purity in the face of colonial domination, dominated groups often merely reproduce an "us-them" mentality which does not effectively challenge the source of their oppression. Bhabha (1994) contends, contra separatist theories, that the creation of a "third space," which hybridizes various aspects of both the dominating and the dominated culture, transforms those who were formerly colonized and disrupts the authority of those who were former colonizers. The creation of "third cultures" is by no means a simple task and there are still a number of difficulties which must be overcome. For example, there may be disagreements not only over substantive issues but also with respect to the reasoning processes that should be used in conducting the dialogue. Researchers in the field of intercultural communication have identified cultural differences not only with regard to what is expressed, but also with regard to how it is expressed. Communication styles vary from culture to culture (Barnlund 1975), as do "epistemic structures" (how arguments are built) and rhetorical patterns (how arguments are presented) (Condon and Yousef 1975, chap. 10). Morioka (1998), in a criticism of my earlier attempt to outline a constructivist approach to intercultural ethics has further suggested that many individuals regard "blind conformity" to the status quo as a good thing and therefore see no reason to engage in reflective criticism or cross-

cultural dialogue. No doubt this criticism is empirically valid. Constructivists themselves speak of personal constructs as being "tenacious" (Kelly 1963, 9) and of social constructs as tending towards "inertia" (Arbib and Hesse, 1986, 133ff.). Even when individuals recognize that the social system they live in is evil or unjust, the socialization process can sometimes be so powerful that change is inconceivable. Societies can exert powerful pressures on individuals to think and act in certain ways, either by suppressing innovation or by not making other alternatives available, and powerful elites can manipulate the communication process to their own advantage. From a normative perspective, however, what are the alternatives? Either we resign ourselves to the status quo, along with whatever evils and injustices it contains, or we attempt to work for something better through radical social change. Either we suppress the points of view of those who disagree with us or we attempt to create forums through which differences can be aired and, hopefully, mutually satisfactory agreements can be reached. References Adler, Peter S. (1977). "Beyond Cultural Identity: Reflections upon Cultural and Multicultural Man." In Topics in Culture Learning: Concepts, Applications, and Research, ed. Richard W. Brislin. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press. Althusser, Louis (1971). Lenin and Philosophy and Other Essays. Trans. Ben Brewster. London: NLB. (1977). For Marx. Trans. Ben Brewster. London: NLB. Apel, Karl-Otto (1980). Towards a Transformation of Philosophy. Trans. Glyn Adey and David Frisby. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Arbib, Michael A. and Mary B. Hesse (1986). The Construction of Reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Barnlund, Dean C. (1970). "A Transactional Model of Communication." In John Akin, Alvin Goldberg, Gail Myers, and Joseph Stewart, eds., Language Behavior. The Hague: Mouton. (1975). Public Self and Private Self In Japan and the United States. Tokyo: Simul Press. Bhabha, Homi (1994). The Location of Culture. London: Routledge. Benhabib, Seyla (1986). Critique, Norm, and Utopia. New York: Columbia University Press. (1992). Situating the Self. Cambridge: Polity Press. Bennett, Milton (1993). "Towards Ethnorelativism: A Developmental Model of Intercultural Sensitivity." In Education for the Intercultural Experience, ed. R. Michael Paige. Yarmouth: Intercultural Press. Berger, Peter L. and Thomas Luckmann (1966). The Social Construction of Reality. New York: Anchor. Bhaskar, Roy (1979). The Possibility of Naturalism. Brighton: Harvester. Condon, John C. and Fathi Yousef (1975). An Introduction to Intercultural Communication. New York: Macmillan. Dewey, John (1949). "The Field of Value." In Ray Leplay, ed., Value: A Cooperative Inquiry. New York: Columbia University Press. Durham, William H. (1978). "Toward a Coevolutionary Theory of Human Biology and Culture." In The Sociobiology Debate, ed. Arthur L. Caplan. New York: Harper and Row. (1991). Coevolution. Stanford: Standford University Press. Dworkin, Ronald (1977). Taking Rights Seriously. London: Duckworth. Ellingsworth, Huber W. (1988). "A Theory of Adaptation in Intercultural Dyads." In Young Yun Kim and William B. Gudykunst, eds., Theories in Intercultural Communication. Newbury Park:

Sage. Evanoff, Richard (1996). "Intercultural Ethics: New Ways of Learning to Get Along with Each Other." In Koku-sai komyunikeeshon ni okeru gengo to bunka [Language and Culture in International Communication]. Tokyo: Aoyama Gakuin Daigaku Sougou Kenkyu Jyo [Research Institute of Aoyama Gakuin University] and Kokusai Seiji Kezai Kenkyu Sentaa [Center for Research in International Studies]. (1998). "A Constructivist Approach to Intercultural Ethics," Eubios Journal of Asian and International Bioethics 8(3): 84-87. (1999). "Towards a Constructivist Theory of Intercultural Dialogue." In Nobuyuki Honna and Yoshiki Kano, eds., International Communication in the 21st Century, ed. Tokyo: Sanseido, 1999. Furnham, A. and S. Bochner (1986). Culture Shock: Psychological Reactions to Unfamiliar Environments. London: Methuen. Giddens, Anthony (1984). The Constitution of Society. Cambridge: Polity Press. (1990). The Consequences of Modernity. Cambridge: Polity Press. (1994). Beyond Left and Right: The Future of Radical Politics. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Habermas, J_rgen (1989). Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Trans. Christian Lenhardt and Shierry Weber Nicholsen. Cambridge: Polity Press. (1993). Justification and Application. Trans. Ciaran Cronin. Cambridge: MIT Press. Holenstein, Elmar (1995). "Human Equality and Intra- as Well as Intercultural Diversity." The Monist 78:65-79. Kelly, George A. (1963). The Psychology of Personal Constructs. New York: W. W. Norton. Kim, Young Yun (1989). "Intercultural Adaptation." In Molefi Kete Asante and William B. Gudykunst, eds., Handbook of International and Intercultural Communication. Newbury Park: Sage. (1991). "Communication and Cross-Cultural Adaptation." In Larry A. Samovar and Richard E. Porter, eds., Intercultural Communication: A Reader, 6th ed. Belmont: Wadsworth. Kim, Young Yun and William B. Gudykunst, eds. (1988). Cross-Cultural Adaptation: Current Approaches. Newbury Park: Sage. Levins, Richard and Richard Lewontin (1985). The Dialectical Biologist. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Lewontin, R. C. (1982). "Organism and Environment." In H. C. Plotkin, ed., Learning, Development, and Culture. Chichester: John Wiley and Sons. Lumsden, Charles J. and Edward O. Wilson (1981). Genes, Mind, and Culture. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. MacIntyre, Alasdair (1985). After Virtue. 2nd ed. London: Duckworth. (1988). Whose Justice? Which Rationality? London: Duckworth. Morioka, Masahiro (1998). "Commentary on Evanoff." Eubios Journal of Asian and International Bioethics 8(3): 87. Norgaard, Richard B. (1994). Development Betrayed: The End of Progress and a Coevolutionary Revisioning of the Future. London: Routledge. Pruitt, Dean G. (1994). "Achieving Integrative Agreements in Negotiation." In Gary R. Weaver, ed., Culture, Communication and Conflict. Needham Heights: Simon and Schuster. Rawls, John (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Belknap Press. (1996). Political Liberalism. New York: Colubmia University Press.

Rose, Steven, Leon J. Kamin, and R. C. Lewontin (1984). Not in Our Genes: Biology, Ideology and Human Nature. Middlesex: Penguin. Sahlins, Marshall (1976). The Use and Abuse of Biology. London: Tavistock. Sandel, Michael J. (1982). Liberalism and the Limits of Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (1996). Democracy's Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy. Cambridge: Belknap. Stotland, Ezra and Lance K. Canon (1972). Social Psychology. Philadelphia: W. B. Saunders. Useem, John (1971). "The Study of Cultures." Originally published in Sociological Focus; reprinted in Studies of Third Cultures: A Continuing Series, No. 6. East Lansing: Institute for International Studies in Education, Michigan State University, no date. Useem, John, Ruth Hill Useem, and John Donoghue (1963). "Men in the Middle of the Third Culture: The Roles of American and Non-Western People in Cross-Cultural Administration," Human Organization 22(3):169-179. Weichhart, Peter (1993). "How Does the Person Fit into the Human Ecological Triangle? From dualism to duality: the transactional worldview." In Dieter Steiner and Markus Nauser, eds., Human Ecology, London: Routledge. Werbner, Pnina and Tariq Modood, eds. (1997). Debating Cultural Hybridity: Multi-Cultural Identities and the Politics of Anti-Racism. London: Zed Books. Yoshikawa, Muneo Jay (1987). "The Double-Swing Model of Intercultural Communication between the East and the West." In Communication Theory, ed. Lawrence D. Kincaid. San Diego: Academic Press. Young, Robert J. C. (1995). Colonial Desire: Hybridity in Theory, Culture and Race. London: Routledge. (Presented at the Fifth International Tsukuba Bioethics Roundtable Tsukuba University, November 20-23, 1999.)