ARABIC LOGIC AND ITS INFLUENCE

Similar documents
Fatma Karaismail * REVIEWS

ASPECTS OF ARISTOTLE'S LOGIC OF MODALITIES

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Humanities 116: Philosophical Perspectives on the Humanities

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

- 1 - I. Aristotle A. Biographical data 1. Macedonian, from Stagira; hence often referred to as "the Stagirite". 2. Dates: B. C. 3.

On Language, Discourse and Reality

Introduction p. 1 The Elements of an Argument p. 1 Deduction and Induction p. 5 Deductive Argument Forms p. 7 Truth and Validity p. 8 Soundness p.

Ed. Carroll Moulton. Vol. 1. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, p COPYRIGHT 1998 Charles Scribner's Sons, COPYRIGHT 2007 Gale

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

Table of Contents. Table of Contents. A Note to the Teacher... v. Introduction... 1

On Recanati s Mental Files

Review Notices 149. Note

Riccardo Chiaradonna, Gabriele Galluzzo (eds.), Universals in Ancient Philosophy, Edizioni della Normale, 2013, pp. 546, 29.75, ISBN

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press,

Dominican School of Philosophy and Theology PH 1115: Aristotelian Logic

Aristotle: an ancient mathematical logician

Corcoran, J George Boole. Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2nd edition. Detroit: Macmillan Reference USA, 2006

THE ROOTS OF LOGICAL HYLOMORPHISM

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

ABSTRACTS HEURISTIC STRATEGIES. TEODOR DIMA Romanian Academy

Ideas of Language from Antiquity to Modern Times

The Philosophy of Language. Frege s Sense/Reference Distinction

Partial and Paraconsistent Approaches to Future Contingents in Tense Logic

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

Alexander of Aphrodisias s Account of Universals and Its Problems

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

Claim: refers to an arguable proposition or a conclusion whose merit must be established.

IBN RUŠD: KNOWLEDGE, PLEASURES AND ANALOGY

Aristotle The Master of those who know The Philosopher The Foal

WITHOUT QUALIFICATION: AN INQUIRY INTO THE SECUNDUM QUID

Avicenna on Relations and the Bradleyan Regress, in La tradition médiévale des Catégoires, ed. J. Biard & I. Rosier-Catach (Louvain, 2003) Avicenna

ABELARD: THEOLOGIA CHRISTIANA

Философская логика Philosophical Logic. The Roots of Logical Hylomorphism 1

EPISTEMOLOGICAL GROUNDS OF INTERSUBJECTIVITY IN THOMAS AQUINAS S PHILOSOPHY

Predication and Ontology: The Categories

Theories of linguistics

Wolff and Kant on Scientific Demonstration and Mechanical Explanation van den Berg, H.

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

Kant IV The Analogies The Schematism updated: 2/2/12. Reading: 78-88, In General

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

in this web service Cambridge University Press

Marya Dzisko-Schumann THE PROBLEM OF VALUES IN THE ARGUMETATION THEORY: FROM ARISTOTLE S RHETORICS TO PERELMAN S NEW RHETORIC

2 Introduction as well, we surely could not have dealt adequately with later medieval philosophy. And, in the second place, scholarship in those areas

Upon mention of the logical structure of anything in the title of a book. many

Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring Russell Marcus Hamilton College

The History of Philosophy. and Course Themes

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1

In Parts of Animals I 1 (and elsewhere) Aristotle makes it clear that his goal in the study of nature is a

Z.13: Substances and Universals

Is Hegel s Logic Logical?

Three Acts of the Mind

Rhetoric - The Basics

MATTHEWS GARETH B. Aristotelian Explanation. on "the role of existential presuppositions in syllogistic premisses"

The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall Class #7 Final Thoughts on Frege on Sense and Reference

The Embedding Problem for Non-Cognitivism; Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism

Nissim Francez: Proof-theoretic Semantics College Publications, London, 2015, xx+415 pages

Sean Coughlin. PERSONAL DATA Born 27 May 1982 in Hamilton (Canada) Citizen of Canada, the United States of America, and the United Kingdom

ARISTOTLE. PHILO 381(W) Sec. 051[4810] Fall 2009 Professor Adluri Monday/Wednesday, 7:00-8:15pm

Lecture 12 Aristotle on Knowledge of Principles

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

of all the rules presented in this course for easy reference.

Types of perceptual content

Aristotle. Aristotle. Aristotle and Plato. Background. Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle and Plato

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Aristotle on False Reasoning: Language and the World in the Sophistical Refutations

On The Search for a Perfect Language

'Aspects of Avicenna

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Understanding Aristotle. Lonergan Institute for the Good Under Construction

HENRY GEORGE FARMER STUDIES IN ORIENTAL MUSIC

Non-Classical Logics. Viorica Sofronie-Stokkermans Winter Semester 2012/2013

Dialectic: Not Just a Game for Schoolboys. James M. Tallmon, Ph.D.

COURSE SYLLABUS. He psuche ta onta pos esti panta. Aristotle, De Anima 431 b21

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates Republic Symposium Republic Phaedrus Phaedrus), Theaetetus

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

Glossary alliteration allusion analogy anaphora anecdote annotation antecedent antimetabole antithesis aphorism appositive archaic diction argument

Comparing Neo-Aristotelian, Close Textual Analysis, and Genre Criticism

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN:

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

An introduction to biological essentialism. John Wilkins Biohumanities Project University of Queensland

Aesthetics Mid-Term Exam Review Guide:

Valuable Particulars

MEANING AND INFERENCE IN MEDIEY AL PHILOSOPHY

Intentionality is the mind s capacity to direct itself on things. Mental states like

Content. Philosophy from sources to postmodernity. Kurmangaliyeva G. Tradition of Aristotelism: Meeting of Cultural Worlds and Worldviews...

The late Donald Murray, considered by many as one of America s greatest

Classifying the Patterns of Natural Arguments

Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan. by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

Some Basic Concepts. Highlights of Chapter 1, 2, 3.

MEDIEVAL FORMAL LOGIC

Colonnade Program Course Proposal: Explorations Category

Lecture 1: Introduction

Transcription:

ARABIC LOGIC AND ITS INFLUENCE Henrik Lagerlund 175 (The University of Western Ontario) Abstract. In this paper, I introduce Arabic logic and outline three distinctive features of Avicenna s logic. I also place Arabic logic in the context of Western Medieval logic and point to a few areas where Arabic logic seems to have had an influence on Western logic. ملخ ص أحاول في هذه المقالة التعريف بالمنطق العربي و تىضيح ثالث خصائص لمنطق ابه سينا. كما أقىم أيضا بىضع المنطق العربي في سياق المنطق الغربي الىسيطي مع التأكيد على بعض النقاط ال تي يبدو أن المنطق العربي فد ترك أثره فيها على المنطق الغربي. Résumé. Dans cet article, je présente la logique arabe et j esquisse un aperçu des trois traits distinctifs de la logique d Avicenne. Je place également la logique arabe dans le contexte de la logique médiévale occidentale, tout en montrant les points sur lesquels la logique arabe semble avoir influencée la logique occidentale. Arabic logic begins in the mid-eight century. It has its foundation in Ancient Greek logic foremost in Aristotelian logic. The Syriac Christians adopted a teaching tradition in logic that included Porphyry s Isagoge, Categories, De interpretatione and the first seven chapters of the Prior Analytics (these are the chapters that include the non-modal theory of the syllogisms). This teaching tradition was taken over and spread through the Arab conquest in the seventh century. In the following centuries during the Abbasid Caliphate (750-1258), there was a continuously growing interest in philosophy and logic. It is this time period that is often referred to as the golden age of Arabic philosophy and logic.

AL-MUKHATABAT المخاطبات 01/2012 n 01- pp. 175-183. Gradually the whole Organon (the logical works of Aristotle) was made available in Arabic translation. The first more important logician in this tradition is Ishâq al-kindî (d. 870). He wrote a short overview of the whole of the Organon. After him more and more substantial works were produced. Abû Nasr Alfarabi (d. 950) makes the first more original contributions. He wrote a series of commentaries on the Organon. Avicenna held his work in very high esteem. Unfortunately, most of his commentaries are lost. By far the most important logician in the Arabic tradition was, however, Avicenna (d. 1037). 176 Avicenna s Logic Avicenna had a different attitude to Aristotle s logic than logicians before him. He didn t think that Aristotle was necessarily right. Aristotle had a lot of intuitions about logic that didn t all go together into a coherent whole. They had to be worked out and then it would become clear, Avicenna thought, that Aristotle s logic was only a fragment of a much larger system. Up until Avicenna, logic was in the Arabic tradition dominated by Aristotle s influence, but after him logic was Avicennean. This isn t to say that logic wasn t Aristotelian after Avicenna. It was, but the texts drawn upon by most logicians weren t Aristotle s they were Avicenna s (a formidable exception was, of course, Averroes). One work in particular became especially important for subsequent logicians. It was what is known as Al-Ishârât wa l Tanbîhat in Arabic and Pointers and Reminders in English. In some of his works on Avicenna s logic, Tony Street has outlined three things that make logic Avicennean as opposed to Aristotelian. (1) The truth-conditions of absolute (or assertoric, that is, non-modal) sentences are expressed in modal terms. (2) The logical properties of so-called descriptional (wasfi) sentences, like Every B is A while B, are studied. (3) Syllogisms are divided into connective and repetitive.

If a logician adopts these three, he is following Avicenna, according to Street (see Street 2002 and Street 2004). 177 In pointer two of path four, Avicenna introduces the distinctions between different kinds of sentences. The first distinction is between absolute and modal sentences. Although absolute sentences are distinguished from modal sentences they turn out to be modal as well. The basic division is one between absolute sentences that are taken to be definite and indefinite with respect to time. Avicenna talks about three kinds of absolute sentences, and they are all explicated with the help of time. First there are absolute sentences that refer to a definite time. They play no role in his discussion. The other two are more important and they are the general and the special absolute sentences. The general absolute sentences are sentences taken without limitation with respect to time, which means that they have to take in all individuals past, present and future. Furthermore, the copula is is taken to mean that the B s are A s at least sometime. An example would thus be Every human being is sometimes moving. A special absolute sentence is hence a sentence with limitations with respect to time. The subject term hence refer to individuals at a specific moment in time although it is not explicated what moment in time that is. The copula is also understood as a conjunction meaning sometimes B and sometimes not B. An example would be Everything running is sometimes walking and sometimes not walking. Avicenna is quick to point out that neither general nor special absolute sentences behave as expected. They for example don t fit in to the traditional square of opposition. Every B is A on the general reading doesn t contradict Some B is not A. He therefore brings in one other kind of absolute sentence, namely a perpetual absolute sentence. In the perpetual sentence the copula is simply read as is always. The contradictory of the general absolute is going to be a perpetual absolute, and similar with the special although it will contradict a disjunction of two perpetual sentences (see Street 2002 and Lagerlund 2009 for a more detailed discussion about this).

The second distinctive Avicennan thesis is the introduction of descriptional sentences. This is again done in the context of modal logic, although, such sentences don t need to be modal at all and Avicenna can be seen to have introduced a logic for descriptional sentences (Street 2002). The example he gives in Pointers and Reminders is: 178 (D) Everything walking is necessarily moving while walking The addition of while walking restricts all moving things to those actually walking, which makes the sentence true. Avicenna distinguishes descriptional sentences from substantial sentences. The example he gives of a substantial sentence is: (S) Every human is necessarily an animal The logic for substantial sentences is different from the logic for descriptional sentences. A sentences like (S) converts according to the standard Aristotelian conversion rules, like: Every human is necessarily and animal into: Some animal is necessarily a human. These kind of sentences are characterized by being kath hauto (per se) as described by Aristotle in Posterior Analytics I.4 (see Lagerlund 2000, 30-1). Part of what Artistotle said about modal logic is valid for such sentences. Another group of sentences, like: Every grammarian is necessarily a human aren t substantial and hence don t convert, since this converted sentence is false: Some human is necessarily a grammarian. However, if these are read as descriptional sentences, then they do convert, like: Every grammarian is necessarily a human while a grammarian,

which converts into: Some human is necessarily a grammarian while a grammarian. 179 Descriptional sentences hence have a logic like substantial sentences and Avicenna thinks part of Aristotle s modal logic can be worked out using descriptional sentences. I have compared this to some similar logics found in thirteenth century Latin logic (see Lagerlund 2009). Even though Avicenna sketches a logic for descriptional sentences in Pointers and Reminders, he is mostly concerned with substantial sentences and their logic. The third distinctive mark of Avicenna s logic is the distinction between so-called connective and repetitive syllogisms. It corresponds roughly to Aristotle s distinction between categorical and hypothetical syllogisms. In his newly published history of Arabic logic, Khaled El-Rouayheb divides Arabic logic after 1200 into several distinctive periods (see El-Rouyaheb 2011). The immediate following period outlined in the book starts in the early thirteenth century with Fakhr al- Din al-razi. He divides the logical tradition into an early and a later tradition. After Razi the Arabic logical tradition became disassociated from Aristotle and more narrowly focused on the predicables, definitions, propositions and syllogisms. Most thirteenth century logic can also be described as post-avicennan in the sense that they all took their departure from Avicenna and not from Aristotle himself. In the fourteenth century another transformation takes place and lengthy summaries found in the earlier traditions became very rare. Instead of writing commentaries on the works of Aristotle, Arabic logicians were content with writing glosses. The interest also shifted from formal logic (syllogisms) to semantical concerns. After this period Arabic logic fragments in the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries and several centers develops. In the book, El-Rouyaheb identifies an Ottoman Turkish, an Iranian, an Indo-Muslim, a North African and a Christina Arabic tradition. These developed independently of each other, and, according to El-Rouyaheb, it is the Ottoman Turkish tradition that is the most important. This fragmentation continues up to

the twentieth century. It is mostly the themes outlined by Avicenna that dominates the tradition, however. 180 The Influence of Arabic Logic Arabic logic had very little influence on the Western logical tradition after the Middle Ages. In fact it was largely forgotten until rediscovered by Nicholas Rescher in 1964 (see Rescher 1964). Carl Prantl argued in the mid-nineteenth century that the part of Western logic nowadays called logica modernorum, the so-called theories of the properties of terms, that is, supposition theory etc. from the twelfth century, entered into the Latin world from translations of Byzantine and Arabic logical works (see Prantl 1867). This was, as M.L. de Rijk showed in the 1960 s, completely wrong (see de Rijk 1962 and 1967). He argued convincingly that this part of medieval logic was partly due to Aristotle s Sophistici Elenchi but foremost it was due to the creative minds of late twelfth century logicians. His judgment of earlier views was so harsh, however, that Arabic logic in the Latin tradition has hardly been studied at all. Most scholars are of the opinion that Arabic logic had very little if any influence on Western logic, but, although Arabic logic didn t revolutionize Western logic as was once thought, it certainly had an influence on the Western logical tradition; although not in the way previously thought. The Latin logicians of the thirteenth century had quite a good grasp of Arabic logic. The major source for this knowledge was the Maqâsid al-falâsifa (The Meaning of the Philosophers) by Abû Hâmid Muhammad al-ghazâlî (1058-1111). It was supposed to be a preparatory work for his later and for contemporary readers much more known Tahâfut al-falâsifa (The Incoherence of the Philosophers). The whole of the Maqâsid contains a presentation of logic, physics, metaphysics and theology, and has been claimed to be an intelligent reworking of foremost Avicenna s Dânesh-name (Book of Science), which is a compendium of his doctrines written in Persian. Al-Ghazâlî s work was translated in full into Latin early in the second half of the twelfth century, which isn t more than 50 or 75 years after it was written. In one of the manuscripts the title is Liber Algazelis de summa theoricae philosophiae, but it was also printed in Venice in 1506 under the title Logica et philosophia Algazelis arabis.

The Latin translation of the Maqâsid was very much read and became together with Maimonides Guide, at least in the thirteenth century, the basic text from which the Latin authors gained their knowledge of Arabic philosophy. The reason it became so much read was because it mentions some of the 'hot' topics of the period, for example the divisions of the sciences, the distinction between essence and existence, the eternity of the world, the number of souls etc. The logic became very well known as well. Albert the Great used it quite extensively and it was used or copied by Ramón Lull. 181 Al-Ghazâlî begins the Maqâsid with a distinction between imagination (imaginatio) and belief (credulitas). An imagination is an apprehension of a thing, he writes, which is signified by a single mental utterance (dictio) in the intellect. Names like stone or tree etc. signify these apprehensions or imaginations. A belief is on the other hand a sentence or a complex utterance, that is, that which says or expresses something, like the world begins. A belief is always a composition of at least two imaginations. The kind of knowledge, which is mediated by imagination, is arrived at through definitions and descriptions, and the kind of knowledge, which is mediated by belief, is arrived at through arguments. It is logic that gives the rules by which we are able to give good and true definitions and arguments. Hence logic is the very foundation of knowledge and all science, argues Al-Ghazâlî. The major thing to note about this division is the close connection between mind and logic. The view of logic as being about intentions is derived from Avicenna and it was very influential. It gave rise to a major controversy in the thirteenth century between those that argued that logic was a science of discourse (scientia sermocinalis) and those that argued that is was a science of reason (scientia rationalis). Albert the Great argues, for example, that logic is a science of mental intentions. The Arabic discussion of the matter of the syllogism found in Al-Ghazâlî s logic is of particular interest. His division of the matter had an influence on several Latin logicians and among them Thomas Aquinas. The matter of a syllogism is it s premises while the form is the syllogistic form.

He gives the following division of the matter: Demonstrative premises, 182 Topical premises, Rhetorical and legal premises, Sophistical premises, Poetical premises. Logic is hence subdivided into these five kinds of matter. Althought the Maqâsid was a summary of Al-Farabi s and Avicenna s doctrines, the Latin medieval logicians also had some knowledge of Al-Farabi s and Avicenna s logics directly. A twelfth century translation of the beginning, namely the part on Porphyry s Isagoge, of Avicenna s encyclopedic worked called in Arabic Kitab al-shifa (The Book of Healing) was circulating, and also a fragment of the part on the Posterior Analytics from the same book existed in Latin. Small fragments of some of Al-Farabi's logic works have also been discovered in Latin. In the early thirteenth century, some of Averroes commentaries on the Organon were translated in to Latin. William of Luna translated the middle commentary on Porphyry s Isagoge and the middle commentaries on Aristotle s Categories, De interpretatione, Prior Analytics, and Posterior Analytics between the 1220 s and 30 s. In many commentaries on Aristotle s logical works in the thirteenth century a heavily metaphysical interpretation of logic is defended. There has been some discussion in the secondary literature about the source of this interpretation and one suggestion is that it has its source in Averroes commentaries. His view of differentia can be found in Robert Kilwardby s commentaries on the Isagoge and the Categories. It can also be read into Aquinas De ente et essentia. Averroes treatment of modal syllogistics is also very interesting and strengthens his general metaphysical interpretation of Aristotle s logic. It seems also to have had some influence in the thirteenth century, particularly on

Kilwardby s commentary on Aristotle s Prior Analytics. A detailed study of the logical theories in Arabic logic works accessible to Latin logicians has not been written yet. It is clear, however, that these doctrines never were as influential as Prantl assumed, but neither did they exert no influence what so ever (See Lagerlund 2000, Chapter 2, Lagerlund 2007 and Lagerlund 2011). 183 References El-Rouayheb, K. (2010) Relational Syllogisms & the History of Arabic Logic, 900-1900, Leiden: Brill. Lagerlund, H. (2000) Modal Syllogistics in the Middle Ages, Leiden: Brill. Lagerlund, H. (2007) The Assimilation of Aristotelian and Arabic Logic up to the Later Thirteenth Century, in D.M. Gabbay and J. Woods (eds.) Handbook of the History of Logic, vol. 2, Amsterdam: Elsevier. Lagerlund, H. (2009) Avicenna and Tusi on Modal Logic, History and Philosophy of Logic, 30:3, 227-239. Lagerlund, H. (2011) Arabic Logic in the Latin Middle Ages, in H. Lagerlund (ed.) Encyclopedia of Medieval Philosophy, Heidelberg: Springer. Prantl, C. (1867) Geschichte der Logic im Abendlande, 3 vols., Leipzig. Rescher, N. (1964) The Development of Arabic Logic, Pittsburgh. de Rijk, L.M. (1962) Logica Modernorum. A Contribution to the History of Early Terminist Logic: vol. I; On the Twelfth Century Theories of Fallacy, (Wijsgerige teksten en studies 6), Assen: Van Gorcum. de Rijk, L.M. (1967) Logica Modernorum. A Contribution to the History of Early Terminist Logic: vol. II, 1-2, The Origin and Early Development of the Theory of Supposition, (Wijsgerige teksten en studies 16), Assen: Van Gorcum. Tony Street (2002). An Outline of Avicenna s Syllogistic. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 84:2,129-160. Street, T. (2004) 'Arabic Logic', in D. M. Gabbay and J. Woods (eds.), Handbook of the History of Logic, vol. 1, Amsterdam: Elsevier.