Abstract. Moral Judgment Purposivism. Consider a traditional version of motivational judgment internalism: necessarily, A s

Similar documents
Moral Judgment Purposivism: Saving Internalism from Amoralism. Forthcoming in Philosophical Studies

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

WHY DO PEOPLE CARE ABOUT REPUTATION?

Rational Agency and Normative Concepts by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord UNC/Chapel Hill [for discussion at the Research Triangle Ethics Circle] Introduction

The Embedding Problem for Non-Cognitivism; Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism

Boyd, Robert and Richerson, Peter J., The Origin and Evolution of Cultures, Oxford University Press, 2005, 456pp, $35.00 (pbk), ISBN X.

But, if I understood well, Michael Ruse doesn t agree with you. Why?

Moral Judgment and Emotions

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

The Neosentimentalist Argument Against Moral Rationalism: Some Critical Observations

PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Ridgeview Publishing Company

LeBar s Flaccidity: Is there Cause for Concern?

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Science and Values: Holism and Radical Environmental Activism

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

The Psychology of Justice

Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008

Draft Date 10/20/10 Draft submitted for publication: Please do not cite without permission

ALIGNING WITH THE GOOD

Recent Work on Motivational Internalism

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

The Moral Animal. By Robert Wright. Vintage Books, Reviewed by Geoff Gilpin

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

The Doctrine of the Mean

Twentieth Excursus: Reference Magnets and the Grounds of Intentionality

How Selfish Genes Shape Moral Passions. Randolph M. Nesse The University of Michigan

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Colonnade Program Course Proposal: Explorations Category

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Nicomachean Ethics. p. 1. Aristotle. Translated by W. D. Ross. Book II. Moral Virtue (excerpts)

THE EVOLUTION OF RELIGION AND THE EVOLUTION OF CULTURE TAYLOR THIEL DAVIS. B.Sc., The University of Georgia, 2000 M.A., Tufts University, 2011

The Culpable Inability Problem for Synchronic and Diachronic Ought Implies Can

Exploring the Monty Hall Problem. of mistakes, primarily because they have fewer experiences to draw from and therefore

Types of perceptual content

Formalizing Irony with Doxastic Logic

Image and Imagination

Beatty on Chance and Natural Selection

Darwinian populations and natural selection, by Peter Godfrey-Smith, New York, Oxford University Press, Pp. viii+207.

The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

THE ROLE OF THE PATHE IN ARISTOTLE S CONCEPTION OF VIRTUE

4 Embodied Phenomenology and Narratives

Moral Relativism in Context

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Emotions from the Perspective of Analytic Aesthetics

In his essay "Of the Standard of Taste," Hume describes an apparent conflict between two

Categories and Schemata

An Alternative to Kitcher s Theory of Conceptual Progress and His Account of the Change of the Gene Concept

THE PROPOSITIONAL CHALLENGE TO AESTHETICS

WHY STUDY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY? 1

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

Review of "The Unexplained Intellect: Complexity, Time, and the Metaphysics of Embodied Thought"

Harris Wiseman, The Myth of the Moral Brain: The Limits of Moral Enhancement (Cambridge, MA and London: The MIT Press, 2016), 340 pp.

Simulated killing. Michael Lacewing

Chudnoff on the Awareness of Abstract Objects 1

The Bowerbirds and the Bees: Miller on Art, Altruism and Sexual Selection. Catherine Driscoll* Dept. of Philosophy. North Carolina State University

The Meaning of Abstract and Concrete in Hegel and Marx

In The Meaning of Ought, Matthew Chrisman draws on tools from formal semantics,

Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2d ed. transl. by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (London : Sheed & Ward, 1989), pp [1960].

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

1/9. The B-Deduction

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Is Architecture Beautiful? Nikos A. Salingaros University of Texas at San Antonio May 2016

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver

Student Performance Q&A:

Aesthetic Judgements and Motivation

Aristotle on the Human Good

The Senses at first let in particular Ideas. (Essay Concerning Human Understanding I.II.15)

Art and Morality. Sebastian Nye LECTURE 2. Autonomism and Ethicism

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

Habit, Semeiotic Naturalism, and Unity among the Sciences Aaron Wilson

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

Objectives: Performance Objective: By the end of this session, the participants will be able to discuss the weaknesses of various theories that suppor

1/10. The A-Deduction

Moral Geography and Exploration of the Moral Possibility Space

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

The Teaching Method of Creative Education

TYPE-SELECTION VERSUS TOKEN-SELECTION 1

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

Comparing Neo-Aristotelian, Close Textual Analysis, and Genre Criticism

Perceptions and Hallucinations

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

Situated actions. Plans are represetitntiom of nction. Plans are representations of action

Sentimentalism, Affective Response, and the Justification of Normative Moral Judgments

Transcription:

Matthew S. Bedke Writing Sample Abstract Moral Judgment Purposivism Consider a traditional version of motivational judgment internalism: necessarily, A s sincere moral judgment that he or she ought to ϕ motivates A to ϕ (at least a little). Such principles fail because they cannot accommodate the amoralist, or one who renders moral judgments without any corresponding motivation. Based on the possibility of amoralists, the received view is externalism roughly, the view that the connection between moral judgments and motivation is not conceptually grounded, but is instead discovered to be statistical or nomological. I revive conceptual internalism by offering some modifications of the amoralist case to show that certain motivational failures are not conceptually possible. I also suggest that empirical investigation of moral judgments can reveal a motivational link that is more robust that the statistical and nomological links allowed by externalists. I introduce and defend moral judgment purposivism (MJP): the purpose of moral judgments is to motivate prototypically moral behaviors. I argue that moral judgments evolved as a proximate mechanism to elicit prototypically moral behaviors, which would be evolutionarily advantageous under a variety of adaptationist models that incorporate assortive interactions. MJP is consistent with conceptual desiderata and it offers a more illuminating analysis of amoralist cases.

Matthew S. Bedke Writing Sample Moral Judgment Purposivism: Saving Internalism from Amoralism If John Doe sincerely judges that he ought to visit his grandmother in the hospital, we expect him to be so motivated, at least a little bit. If Jane Doe sincerely judges that she ought to help someone in dire need (at no inconvenience to herself), we expect her to be so motivated, again, at least a little bit. And our expectations in these and similar cases are usually met, for first-person moral judgments 1 are usually motivationally efficacious, though the motivation can be outweighed by other considerations. That much seems uncontroversial, but there are different ways of clarifying and articulating the connection between moral judgment and motivation. The orthodox 2 internalist position, motivational judgment internalism, is that there is an a priori conceptually necessity between sincere moral judgments and motivation along the following lines: MJI: necessarily, individual A s sincere moral judgment that he or she ought to ϕ provides A with at least some motivation to ϕ. Given that A has a mental state M that bears all other markings of a moral judgment but lacks motivational oomph, MJI holds that M cannot be a genuine moral judgment. This view strains Acknowledgments. 1 Throughout I will be concerned with first person moral ought judgments. The literature on this kind of internalism is large, but sadly lacking in recent advances. For excellent discussions see Darwall (1983); Schaffer-Landau (2003), chapter 6; Mele (2003). 2 Some with internalists leanings could retreat to weaker and less orthodox claims, like Necessarily, the virtuous are motivated by their moral judgments or Anyone who judges that he ought to X (morally or otherwise) is either motivated accordingly or practically irrational. But such theses are more about virtuous or rational people than they are about moral judgments. These theses require the motivational connection to be mediated by something external to the judgments themselves. I want to argue that there is a less mediated motivational role for moral judgments such that denies the robustly externalist view that moral judgments of themselves have no necessary connection to motivation. 1

the thought that amoralists isolated individuals who acknowledge moral obligations but remain unmoved by them are at least conceptually possible. The orthodox externalist alternative says there is no a priori conceptual connection between moral judgments and motivation. Any observed regularities are merely contingent. It follows that there are possible states of affairs where genuine moral judgments have no motivational efficacy whatsoever. In response to this debate I want to, first, open some middle ground between these extremes by reflecting on different kinds of amoralist cases. I present a case of community-wide amoralism that underwrites a conceptually grounded connection between moral judgments and motivation while respecting the conceptual possibility of isolated amoralists. The case requires us to consider more nuanced views of the connection between moral judgments and motivation than those presented in orthodox internalism and externalism. This brings me to my second project, where I argue that we can only appropriately understand the connection between moral judgments and motivation by situating these psychological states in wider moral practices. I introduce and defend moral judgment purposivism, which can be provisionally stated as follows: MJP: the purpose of a moral judgment is to motivate individuals to act accordingly. If this is right, there is a sense in which moral judgments are supposed to motivate, and so judgments are otherwise similar but lack this purpose are not really genuine moral judgments. MJP explains our reaction to community-wide amoralist cases, avoids the pitfalls of the orthodox views, and articulates morality s essential action-guiding role. I. The Isolated Amoralist An amoralist is one who makes sincere moral judgments about his or her moral obligations, but utterly fails to be moved by them. Brink (1989, 45-50) forcefully argues for the 2

conceptual possibility of amoralists and it is perhaps the greatest flaw of MJI that it classifies the amoralist as conceptually impossible. Not only does MJI rule out amoralists, but what is worse, it rules out the possibility that a normally virtuous person on one occasion issues a moral judgment that fails to motivate. Though MJI holds that the virtuous person does not issue a moral judgment in such a case, it is clearly more natural to chalk up the deficiency to a one-time glitch. Why not call this a motivationally defective moral judgment rather than deny it the status of moral judgment altogether? 3 Indeed, most individuals side with Brink on this issue. Shaun Nichols (2003) has gathered evidence that the widely-held concept of a moral judgment does not require that it motivate. He provided subjects with a description of a psychopath who acknowledges that hurting others is morally wrong, but who claims not to care and who in fact hurts others. Nichols discusses the results as follows: Most subjects maintained that the psychopath did really understand that hurting others is morally wrong, despite the absence of motivation.... Prima facie, this counts as evidence against the conceptual rationalist s inverted-commas gambit. For it seems to be a platitude that psychopaths really make moral judgments. And if it is a platitude that psychopaths really make moral judgments, it will be difficult to prove that conceptual rationalism captures the folk platitudes surrounding moral judgment. (74-5) 4 3 Proponents of MJI try to avoid the natural thing to say. They might say that the amoralist only makes a moral judgment in the inverted commas sense; that the moral judgment is not sincere; or that the moral judgment does not concern a moral obligation. These moves might suffice for the amoralist, but they seem quite desperate explanations of the single-shot glitch in the otherwise virtuous person. 4 This study bears on the concept of moral judgment if one thinks that pre-theoretic (and particularly pre-philosophical) intuitions employ or otherwise allow access to the contents of our 3

Our verdicts in these cases shed light on the concept of a moral judgment. According to our concept, it is possible to have an amoralist, or to have a normally virtuous person, issue a sincere moral judgment despite any lack of motivational import. From these isolated amoralist cases, it is too easy to conclude that externalism is right and so motivation is no part of the concept of moral judgment. 5 However, there are ways to press back against orthodox externalism and establish a more robust connection between moral judgment and motivation. One way to do so is to concentrate on particular amoral individuals and ask whether the motivational failings of their putative moral judgments can be systematic, or whether they must be understood against a background of motivational efficacy within that particular agent. Consider the views of Mark Timmons and James Dreier that push us in this direction. Timmons (1999), for instance, claims that a moral judgment typically has certain (defeasible) causal tendencies, including, especially, certain first-person choice guiding tendencies.... Its typically having these tendencies is part of the very concept of moral judgment. (140, emphasis added). Similarly, James Drier (1990) says let us call modest internalism the principle that in normal contexts a person has some motivation to promote what he believes to be good. (14). On the most natural reading of these views, and the view I want to consider, if we know that an agent, A s, tokenings of mental state M do not typically (in the case concepts. Though I am sympathetic to the view, those who have misgivings about this kind of conceptual analysis in this kind of case can rely on the more traditional arguments given by Brink and noted above. In any event, my purpose is not to argue for the conceptual possibility of amoralists, but to investigate whether any brand of internalism can accommodate them. 5 Nichols (2003) seems to embrace this kind of approach, or what he calls empirical internalism about core moral judgment. (111). In Nichols s words, core moral judgment is nomologically connected with motivation. (Id.) Though he uses the label internalism, this appears to be the standard externalist view advocated by Brink, for any connection between moral judgment and motivation would be contingent. 4

of Timmons) or normally (in the case of Drier) have the tendency to motivate A, then we know the tokens of M are not genuine moral judgments. I see two worries about these positions as responses to orthodox externalism. First, lifelong amoralists seem conceptually possible. That is, a particular agent A might render genuine moral judgments that never have motivational force for A, so the typicality and normalcy requirements, as restricted to the mental tokens of a particular agent, are simply not required for A to render genuine moral judgments. Second, even if it were true that A s putative moral judgments must typically or normally motivate A to be genuine moral judgments, it is not clear how much this view departs from externalism. Externalists can and often do acknowledge statistical and nomological connections between moral judgments and motivational states, and Timmons and Dreier s references to typicality and normalcy are most straightforwardly read as statistical claims. As Timmons view makes clear, he is claiming that typical motivational purport is part of the concept of a moral judgment, and that might signal some departure from orthodox externalism, but that bit of the view relies on the conceptual impossibility of died in the wool amoralists. As I have indicated, that is the most vulnerable part of the claim. In any event, there is a more effective way to push back against the externalist if we focus on communities of agents instead of the mental tokenings of isolated amoralists. To that end, I want to develop a line of thought introduced by Simon Blackburn (1998) that emphasizes the intelligibility of amoralist cases only when they are isolated against a background of motivational efficacy. He remarks: My own judgment on this debate is that externalists can win individual battles. They can certainly point to possible psychologies about which the right thing to say is that the agent knows what it is good or right to do, and then deliberately and 5

knowingly does something else. And they can point to psychologies like that of Satan, in which it can become a reason for doing something precisely that it is known to be evil. But internalists win the war for all that, in the sense that these cases are necessarily parasitic, and what they are parasitic upon is a background connection between ethics and motivation. They are cases in which things are out of joint, but the fact of a joint being out presupposes a normal or typical state in which it is not out. (61). Blackburn thinks that there is a background connection between ethics and motivation, without which we would not understand the exceptional cases as instances of moral judgments. In what follows I will try to substantiate and clarify Blackburn s view by suggesting that the background connection that is essential to moral judgments is community-wide motivational tendencies (section II-A). I will then raise an objection to the view (section II-B), and develop my own more detailed account of moral judgments that answers the objection while providing the best overall theory of moral judgments qua motivational state (section III). II. From Amorality to Amoralsville What seems to animate internalists is a sense that moral judgments are essentially actionguiding, or, as Hare put it, Moral judgments, in their central use, have it as their function to guide conduct. (70). Given the possibility of various kinds of isolated amoralists, and Blackburn s helpful suggestion, I suggest that the best place to locate this essential actionguiding character is in community-wide connections between moral judgment and motivation. So let us now consider whether isolated amoralist should indeed be treated differently from communities of amoralists, and whether we can thereby ground some kind of conceptual connection between moral judgments and systematic motivational tendencies. Let me begin by 6

addressing the shortcomings of some other proposals before introducing my own view in the following section. James Lenman (1999) offers a starting point for thinking about wide-spread amoralism. He asks us to consider an entire planet of amoralists, Amorality, where scientists ascertain and record moral facts, but where no one is ever practically motivated by their moral judgments. (445-46). According to Lenman, externalists must acknowledge Amorality as conceptually possible, but because he finds this hypothetical preposterous, he concludes that externalism quite generally cannot be true. Though he does not discuss the isolated amoralist in any detail, he seems to think that if an entire planet of amoralists is not possible, then neither are isolated amoralists, even against a background of motivational efficacy. While I find Lenman s case to be a nice starting point, there are problems with his conclusion that planets of amoralists are not possible, and the broader implication of his view that externalism is false. Oddly enough, what seems to bother Lenman about the putative moral judgments on planet Amorality is their lack of any propositional content. Indeed, given the bare assertion that the amoralists on Amorality study the moral facts, one can wonder exactly what it is that is under study, particularly when there would appear to be little by way of moral behavior on Amorality. But more importantly, the point of disagreement between internalists and externalists is not supposed to be about content and whether amoralist moral judgments are meaningless, but rather whether moral judgments with agreed upon contents must have motivational import. 6 To really test externalism as applied at the level of global motivational failure, we would do better to think of a case where the semantic content of the amoralists is not at issue. 6 Gert and Mele (2005) press a similar objection against Lenman. 7

In addition, even if Lenman s scenario is impossible, the move from the impossibility of global amoralism to the impossibility of isolated amoralism is an unwarranted leap, as others have pointed out (see Gert and Mele 2005 for a nice discussion). Perhaps some background motivation is necessary to either breath semantic content into the judgments of amoralists, or to simply understand the judgments they make as moral judgments at all, but it would not follow that isolated amoralists in our society render judgments with no semantic content, or judgments which cannot be understood as moral judgments at all. To see whether community-wide amoralism really is conceptually impossible on motivational grounds we should construct a case that is as similar to our moral situation, save some community-wide lack of motivation. We should do our best to table issues of semantic content. Gert and Mele (2005) have offered a case to further guide the way. They ask us to consider planet Alpha, where beings emerge with a strong genetic predisposition to acquire generic desires to do whatever they morally ought. (278). They imagine that one day a worldwide catastrophe strikes that sinks all residents into a deep listlessness. Though the residents of Alpha continue to make genuine first-person moral ought judgments, these judgments no longer carry motivational oomph, for everyone is caught in the grip of a depressive funk. After reflection, Gert and Mele suggest that this kind of scenario is possible. If so, perhaps we are wrong to think that there must be some kind of community-wide background connection between moral judgment and motivation. Still, in the Gert and Mele scenario there is a sense in which the moral judgment affected by global listlessness is understood against a background of efficacious moral motivation. As the evolutionary tale emphasizes, the moral judgments on Alpha still have conduct guidance as part of their function, and we can understand the listlessness as widespread malfunctions of 8

genuinely moral judgments. That is, it is not clear that the background connection of normal motivational efficacy that Blackburn wants is missing in the case of Alpha. And if the listlessness persists, one wonders whether we would be less and less inclined to consider those judgments genuinely moral as the background motivational purpose fades from view. A. The Amoralsville Case I think we can generate another case to show that some community-wide purpose or function is indeed necessary to understand certain judgments as genuinely moral. Consider a distant community very much like our own, but unrelated to our own (perhaps they are on another planet) that developed a very stringent, heavy-handed system of punishment and coercion to keep its citizens in line. The residents of this community are ruled by single dictator that metes out sever punishments, but only for moral violations. As a result, individuals in this community generally keep their contracts, respect each others property, and even help those in need simply because they fear punishment and coercion should they fail to do so. As external observers we would say that their behaviors by and large conform to our ethical norms, though we realize that they are never motivated by anything other than their own interests and fear of harm to their interests. Let us call this place Amoralsville. So far, there are not even putative moral judgments in Amoralsville. But imagine that the residents receive radio frequencies from our society and thereby observe our use of moral language and discourse. With the introduced moral vocabulary, the residents of Amoralsville learn to apply moral concepts correctly. As a result, Amoralsville residents correctly pick out what is right and wrong, acknowledge obligations, and can correctly categorize that which they (morally) ought to do. In fact, forming first personal moral judgments and speaking in ethical terms becomes kind of a fad in Amoralsville, though 9

importantly the judgments never garner any motivational force, and moral demands simply do not weigh with them. Residents of Amoralsville are at all times solely motivated by their own interests. Because this community learns at least the descriptive meaning of our moral language, and uses it correctly, there is no objection that their judgments lack content. The society is in most respects relevantly like our own, including the kinds of behaviors they typically engage in, except moral judgments do not now, nor did they ever, perform any kind of social function. The question is: Do Amoralsville residents render genuine moral judgments? This is quite a different case than those involving isolated amoralists. It looks like the citizens of Amoralsville do not really engage in genuine ethical discourse, for an essential ingredient of ethical discourse has gone missing, viz., its action-guiding character. Amoralsville is also quite different from the Alphas case raised by Gert and Mele, for in our case first person moral judgments perform no social function and historically never did. This suggests that the best way to understand Blackburn s requisit background connection in the following terms: isolated amorlalists only make sense against a background of moral judgments that are supposed to perform some kind of social function. That purpose is present in the case of Alpha evolution programmed it in but it is missing in the Amoralsville case and it seems to account for our divergent intuitions in these cases. Because the Amoralsville case strikes us as missing fundamental moral ingredients in virtue of a kind of community-wide motivational failing, it looks like orthodox externalist line is mistaken. B. A Concern Is the above conclusion a significant insight into the nature of moral judgments, or is it an odd result that should make us mistrust our intuitions? Here is one reason for suspicion. It is 10

prima facie plausible that an agent s mental states are determined by that agent s internal psychological makeup. But on the above view, it looks like two agents, A and B, that are identical with respect to their internal psychology can differ as to whether they token genuine moral judgments. Imagine that A is an amoralist member of our community who tokens a moral judgment that has no motivational force. Because A is understood against a certain background of compliance he nonetheless tokens a genuine moral judgment that is defective. B, by contrast, is a member of Amoralsville, and though he is a neurological duplicate of A he does not render a genuine moral judgment because of his external environment and its lack of a certain background connection between moral judgment and motivation. It seems strange that background societal conditions can determine whether or not an individual has a particular kind of mental state, and this oddity might move us to doubt the intuitive differences. I want to see if we can make better sense of the seeming importance of certain kinds of background connections by moving beyond conceptual analysis. As we shall see, the key is to introduce and articulate a historical dimension to moral judgments and their social functions. Only then can we fully appreciate the essential action-guiding character of moral judgments. III. A Purpose of Moral Judgments I argue that moral judgments are best understood as part of larger moral practices within communities of moral agents, and that situating moral judgments in these larger practices best illuminates their motivational character. The view I defend I call moral judgment purposivism, which can be roughly stated as follows: moral judgments are mental states whose purpose is to motivate individuals to engaged in characteristically moral behaviors (or refrain from characteristically immoral behaviors). What follows will be somewhat exploratory and suggestive. I rely on some recent thoughts in evolutionary theory, and I grant that my 11

suggestions will be subject to further study, which I take to be a virtue. But my main aim is to open up new possibilities to advance the traditional internalist-externalist debate and to show that there are interesting connections between morality and motivation that are not contingent (at least as traditionally understood by the externalist). To develop the view I will first articulate a biological theory of purposes, or proper functions. According to the view, natural objects can acquire purposes by virtue of the selection processes that occur during evolution. I will then apply this view about biological purposes to moral practices to show that moral judgments also have evolved purposes, one of which is to motivate prototypically moral behaviors. After laying down the principles of moral judgment purposivism I will show that the view respects our considered judgments about isolated amoralists and the residents of Amoralsville, conflicted as they might be. The real payoff is that purposivism offers us a way of looking at these cases that clarifies the differences between distinct cases, and further informs our concept of a moral judgment. A. Evolved Purposes The purpose of our moral judgments is just one instance of a general theory of the purposes of evolved functionings. Consider the familiar case of genetic replication. Various genes express themselves as phenotypes, and the phenotypic expression of a given kind of gene can make that gene a more or less successful replicator depending on how the phenotype functions within an environment. Given an environment where various genes express various phenotypes, those phenotypes that increase a gene s relative rate of replication will count as adaptive and so increase the proportion of the gene generation after generation. From this basic story Ruth Millikan (1984) has developed a theory of proper functions that applies to biological entities and languages, and her story will closely parallel our account of 12

the purposes of moral practices. She considers things like the human heart and asks, What makes a heart the kind of thing that it is? Millikan gives the following partial reply: hearts are things that have pumping blood as a proper function. Very roughly we can say that a function F is a proper function of an entity if F made that entity s ancestors selectively fit, and so caused the entity s ancestors to proliferate relative to its competitors. We can explain why some entities exist today by appealing to the way in which those kinds of things functioned historically, and the functions we appeal to in these explanations are proper functions. It turns out the pumping blood was and still is a useful function for biological organisms to have, and so hearts were selected for, and the genes that expressed them were more likely to replicate, precisely because they performed that function. One interesting thing about this account is that we can come to see the proper functions that explain an entity s existence as partially definitive of the kind of thing that it is. For example, the proper function of pumping blood is a definitive characteristic of hearts, and so things that do not have pumping blood as a proper function are not hearts. This is not to say that things that do not actually pump blood are not hearts. Surgically removed hearts, defective hearts, and other things that do not pump blood might still count as hearts depending on their proper functionings, which, in turn, depend on the histories of these things ancestors. 7 But water pumps do not count as hearts even if they can pump blood precisely because water pumps do not have pumping blood as a proper function, and having such a proper function is partly definite of hearts. 7 Artificial hearts might also count as a kind of heart, for pumping blood is a purpose of theirs. However, they do not belong to the same natural kind as naturally occurring hearts because they do not enjoy the right history. 13

It is natural to use purpose to capture what we mean by a selected proper function, as we might say that the purpose of a heart is to pump blood, and so we can shorthand this complicated story of selection and propagation through time by referring to an entity s purposes. B. Moral Evolution While the adaptationist story is familiar in biology, it has a very general form. We can model change through time with evolutionary dynamics if: 1) there is a population with varied phenotypes, where 2) the phenotypes are copiable, and 3) different phenotypes result in differential relative copying success. More importantly, if these three conditions obtain for any phenotype we expect some evolutionary model to explain why the phenotype was selected for. And if some phenotype was selected for, then it has a corresponding proper function or purpose. I want to suggest that moral judgments inherit a purpose by playing a role in certain wider moral practices, so let me begin by considering whether prototypical cases of moral behaviors fit these three conditions for adaptationist modeling. It does seem as though different behaviors have functional differences that can be copied by others or copied on other occasions and that the behaviors can impact one s relative fitness. Consider a classic case the prisoner s dilemma and suppose the prisoners are trying to determine whether to keep or break their prior promise to cooperate. In this case, defectors can take advantage of those who keep their promise, and dominance reasoning actually recommends that each party defect no matter what the other party does. This case presents an adaptationist puzzle that is reiterated for many moral behaviors, viz., why would a habit of keeping one s promises evolve, given its continual vulnerability to the defection strategy? Can we explain why behaviors such as refraining from theft, lying, and intentionally harming others would evolve given the seemingly obvious fitness 14

payoffs for contrary behaviors? Can we explain why honesty and helping behaviors would evolve? The answer to these questions is yes. Let me canvass some recent literature to support my point. Hamilton (1963) introduced the idea of inclusive fitness, or kin selection, which can explain why genetically related individuals might help each other out. Trivers (1971) expanded the idea by discussing reciprocal altruism, where individuals who help only those others who reciprocate can gain a fitness advantaged over non-reciprocators, who are left to fend for themselves. In both cases, genetically altruistic behavior given to a non-kin non-reciprocator puts one at a fitness disadvantage, but so long as the altruistic behavior is correlated with other altruistic behavior to a sufficient degree, genetic altruists are expected to proliferate. 8 Sober and Wilson (1998) categorize these kinds of theories as models of group selection and they survey other scenarios wherein altruistic behavior can evolve. More recently, Brian Skyrms (1996) and (2004) has produced models showing the evolutionary stability of mutual aid, respecting property, some forms of punishing behavior, and other cooperative behaviors. As with the foundational work of Hamilton and Trivers, in all of these models the crucial factor that permits prototypically moral behaviors to evolve is assortive interactions, or the ability of moral actors to interact with one another (rather than non-moral actors) a sufficiently high proportion of the time. Moral actors as a class can become fitter than non-moral actors so long as the stick to their own kind and avoid too much free riding and predation. Though I have indicated that prototypically moral behavior can be copied from one individual to the next, there are various ways for the copying to proceed. The most familiar kind of copying proceeds through genetically expressed functional units, and most models assume 8 For a review of game theory models of social behaviors see Maynard Smith (1982) and Axelrod and Hamilton (1981). 15

some kind of genetic determinism where phenotypes are directly produced by genotypes. This is almost certainly wrong for all phenotypes, for even if genes encode for all the details of phenotypic expression the processes of expression rely heavily on environment. For example, a heart will not be expressed properly if it lacks nutrients during crucial stages of development. Nonetheless, the genetic determinacy simplification is just that: it makes our explanatory task more tractable and it does not seem to significantly alter the predictive power of evolutionary models. Alternatively, some functional units might be primarily determined by culture instead of genetics. 9 Genetics might supply the basic substrates for organisms to adopt functional behaviors (e.g., the ability to adopt a language, or phobic responses to local environmental cues) without coding directly for those behaviors. In any search for the proper functions of our moral behaviors we should be sensitive to the similarities and differences between genetic and cultural versions of evolution. Both can be modeled with the same mathematical structures. 10 The crucial difference concerns the modes of copying. When functional units are primarily genetically determined, copying proceeds through the reproduction of the genes, which are passed on through progeny of the genetic host. When functional units are primarily culturally determined, copying can proceed through a number of mechanisms, including sophisticated cultural transmissions (e.g., education) and more simple mimicking mechanisms. Two points are crucial. First, biological fitness and cultural fitness can pull in opposite directions because the copying mechanisms differ. And second, different moral behaviors might have different mixtures of genetic and cultural copying. Psychologists Haidt 9 I intend culture to be understood very broadly here, where behaviors can be copied through mimicking behavior, a more sophisticated process of social education, etc. For an overview of approaches to cultural evolution see Sober and Wilson (1998), chapters 4 and 5. 10 The rate of mutation and the modes of copying might make cultural adaptations very difficult to model. See, e.g., Dennett (1995), ch. 12. 16

and Joseph (2004), for example, suggest that our moral sense is produced by a combination of genetic and cultural processes. They argue that relevant studies on human and primate moral behavior evidence four innate moral modules concerning suffering/compassion, reciprocity/fairness, hierarchy/respect, and purity/disgust. Different cultures can then emphasize different aspects of these moral sentiments, but the innate mechanisms will limit the kinds of moral practices people can adopt. This hypothesis has the virtue that it can explain the common structure and some of the common intuitions shared by moral practices and at the same time explain the variations we actually find across cultures. 11 It is not my aim to defend any particular account of the evolution of prototypical moral behaviors save this: that some such evolutionary story will provide the best explanation of (at least prototypical instances of) our moral behaviors precisely because moral behaviors fit the three conditions for applying evolutionary dynamics. 12 If I am right about this, then the historical ancestors of some of our current moral practices would have performed some function, and they were selected for, copied, and propagated precisely because they performed that function. Applying Millikan s proper functionalism, our moral behaviors have a proper function, or a purpose, that corresponds to the functions for which they were selected, and these purposes would be partially definitive of our various moral practices. The prevailing evidence from biology and psychology indicates that (at least prototypical) moral behaviors evolved through a process of assortive interactions, which we might call social interactions because they enable 11 See Haidt (2001) for more detail on his social intuitionist model. 12 I should hasten to mark the difference between proximate and distal explanations. Evolutionary dynamics seeks to explain the distal causes of things that copy over generations. Other approaches might provide workable proximate explanations of our moral behaviors so we can understand why individuals engaged in them from, say a psychological or sociological perspective. But we need something like evolutionary dynamics to explain the persistence or proliferation of moral behaviors over generations. 17

cooperative, mutually advantageous outcomes amongst moral actors. Given the evidence we can preliminarily claim that a purpose (or proper function) of moral behaviors is to enable and further cooperative, mutually beneficial outcomes for moral individuals. 13 C. Moral Judgment Purposivism So far I have talked about the evolution of moral behavior, though it would be more appropriate to talk about the evolution of moral practices, which includes behaviors, psychologies, and language. For it is this complex of things that helps individuals obtain mutually beneficial outcomes. In particular, to elicit certain moral behaviors we would have to evolve a mental state responsible for motivating the desired behaviors. Here it is helpful to think in terms of nested proper functions. Consider again the biological domain. One of a left ventricle s proper functions is to squeeze blood out of the heart and that is its contribution to the heart s overall function of pumping blood throughout the body. Similarly, moral judgments will be those mental states that not only recognize when moral behaviors are called for, but also translate those recognitions into behavior, thereby contributing their part to the moral practices that enable social cooperation. Moral judgments with some connection to motivational states will be selected for over moral judgments that merely recognize moral situations and obligations without translating those into appropriate motivational states. Consequently, they have a corresponding nested proper function: a purpose (or proper function) of moral judgments is to motivate individuals to act in accordance with the judgment. This is not to deny the importance of other moral practices, but merely to point out the role of first person moral judgments. We are now in position to set forth moral judgment purposivism. 14 13 Our moral behaviors might fail to have these effects currently, but it is sufficient that their history bestows them with the purpose of eliciting those effects. More importantly, the mechanisms that enable our moral behaviors might have been co-opted to produce other kinds of behavior that fail to generate cooperative outcomes. I discuss this more below. 18

MJP: a purpose of an individual A s sincere moral judgment that he or she ought to ϕ is to motivate A to ϕ (at least a little bit), where a. A s sincere moral judgment is part of a social (assortive) practice whose purpose is, in part, to influence individuals to ϕ, and b. ϕing is a (prototypically) moral behavior We can think of MJP as a synthetic necessity claim, though we should take pains to avoid tempting misunderstandings. Evolutionary explanations do not claim that moral judgments of the sort we have are necessary to perform the social function they in fact perform. Indeed, that function could be served in other ways. To take an analogous case, evolutionary explanations would not claim that no other phenotypes could serve the function that our hands actually serve. That is obviously false. In both cases, evolution purports to explain why our moral judgments or hands did in fact evolve given contingent facts about available phenotypes in our evolutionary environment and the functions performed by those phenotypes. Understood as a synthetic necessity claim, then, MJP is not the view that moral judgments are necessary to perform their social function, but rather that an essential purpose of moral judgments is that they perform a particular social function. In other words, the claim is not that if a mental state M serves this 14 I have tried to show that naturally occurring moral judgments of the kind we are familiar have a purpose (via evolutionary theory). What about the possibility of swamp men who are internally identical to us, and who form societies similar to ours? What of their putative moral judgments? They do not have the right history, so they do not satisfy the synthetic necessity claim that partially defines our own moral judgments. Nonetheless, I leave open the possibility that swamp moral judgments could have a (non-evolutionary) purpose, and if such mental states otherwise meet the conceptual desiderata they, too, might count as moral judgments, just not human moral judgments. So if swamp men formed to have moral lives much like our own, swamp-moral-judgments and human-moral-judgments might be different species of moral judgment. One way to put this is to say that moral judgments can be realized by different states, and investigation of one of the realizations reveals a synthetic necessity that does not hold of the other realizations. For a more detailed defense of historical, biological kinds as natural kinds, or what Millikan calls real kinds, see Millikan s On Swampkinds (forthcoming). 19

function, then M is a moral judgment, but rather, if some mental state M does not have a certain social function as a purpose, then M is not a moral judgment. Although I have thus far identified moral judgments, as opposed to other kinds of motivating judgments, by referring to their contents (e.g., keeping promises, not thieving, not harming others, helping others), it seems that evolution would also select for some of the formal characteristics of moral judgments. For example, these judgments would have to be especially weighty to override any tendencies for self-regarding behaviors, at least in some cases. Otherwise the benefits of mutual cooperation would rest on shaky, less reliable, foundations. Moreover, we might expect moral judgments to be universal, or near universal moral actors would judge the obligations to apply to anyone in the same circumstances because the recognition of near universal obligations helps to maintain the high proportion of compliance in a social group. As we have seen, some such assortive interactions are needed to make moral actors more fit than their non-moral counterparts. One thing we need from a theory of moral motivation is to preserve the fact that different people come to very different moral convictions, and each differing moral judgment tends to carry with it some motivational import. Yet from the above it might sound like we can only explain the motivational force of moral judgments that correspond to prototypical moral behaviors, like altruistic actions. It is important to note, however, that the above comments try to explain the existence of a motivational mechanism by appealing to the kinds of behaviors it historically helped generate, and once we discover that the purpose of moral judgments is to motivate prototypical cases of moral behavior, the machinery that evolved to do this can be co- 20

opted by other practices that differ significantly from their proper function. 15 When this happens we should expect the co-opting normative judgments to motivate corresponding behaviors even if, historically, these behaviors were not the socially adaptive ones. That is, judgments that make use of the evolved machinery for making moral judgments will typically have corresponding motivations because the evolved machinery doesn t know any better, and it will still be the purpose of the machinery to motivate the corresponding behavior. IV. Back to the Amoralist MJP follows up on the conceptual difference between isolated and community-wide amoralist cases to offer a more illuminating analysis, so it is fair to say that MJP offers a theory of moral judgment inspired by some conceptual benchmarks. Let me now comment on how the MJP theory illuminates the amoralist cases and grounds the action-guiding character of moral judgments. First, MJP permits the existence of some isolated amoralists, which nonetheless render genuine moral judgments. The purposive perspective can explain how some moral judgments with the right history and so the right proper function could be nonetheless be defective and fail to perform their proper function. Individuals who make sincere moral judgments about what they ought to do, but fail to be motivated by them, issue defective moral judgments (but moral judgments nonetheless). Though they issue moral judgments, those judgments are not doing 15 I thank for reminding me of this point. Haidt and Craig (2004) say something similar. Of course, it is possible to teach children to be cruel to certain classes of people, but how would adults accomplish such training? Most likely by exploiting other moral modules. Racism, for example, can be taught by invoking the purity module and triggering flashes of disgust at the dirtiness of certain groups, or by invoking the reciprocity module and triggering flashes of anger at the cheating ways of a particular group (Hitler used both strategies against the Jews). In this way, cultures can create variable actual domains that are much broader than the universal proper domains for each module. (63). 21

what they are supposed to be doing. This is no different than the discovery of defective left ventricles that are supposed to perform a certain function but fail to do so. Externalism can also accommodate amoralists, but MJP does a better job at identifying and explaining the thought that the moral judgments of isolated amoralists are defective. It is not just that amoralists fail to follow an observed regularity; there also seems to be something wrong with their moral sensibilities. Just as the spark plug that fails to fire is defective insofar as it fails to do what it is supposed to do, moral judgments that fail to translate into appropriate motivational states are defective insofar as they fail to do what they are supposed to do. Second, MJP has a rather refined view of the Amoralsville case and how it differs from isolated amoralists in our own society. Under MJP, whether or not a particular social group has moral practices depends on whether or not bits of thought, language and behavior were selected and propagated in the past because those practices elicited moral behavior. And moral judgments play a part in that vast system of moral practices. A society like ours, with only a few, isolated amoralists, would evidence society-wide moral practices and moral judgments. Isolated amoralists render moral judgments that do not fulfill their purpose, just as we find a few individuals with left ventricles that do not fulfill their purpose. Recall that Amoralsville residents generally behave in ways that respect moral norms, but they are never motivated by putative moral judgments. In fact, they learned about moral language from our society, and in Amoralsville moral categories are merely classificatory. Though most citizens purport to make judgments about their moral obligations, no citizen is thereby motivated. What gets them going is the fear of punishment and their own self-interest. Here it looks like Amoralsville did not develop a system of thought, language and behavior that facilitated mutually beneficial social interactions. As a result, they did not inherit moral 22

judgments as part of those practices. Unlike the isolated amoralist, who has a mental state that counts as a broken moral judgment, Amoralsville residents do not even have broken moral judgments. Though the resident can descriptively pick out occasions of moral obligation, there is an essential motivational aspect of moral judgments that goes missing. In short, these mental states are not supposed to motivate in the requisite way, and so they do not count as genuine moral judgments. The purposive perspective offers an interpretation of the claim that moral judgments are a type of state that typically motivates in normal conditions. Societies will not have moral practices unless they have a mental state that typically motivates most people to behave morally. There is some threshold below which non-compliance with moral norms would lead to the dissolution of society. And the conditions of normalcy are the conditions under which the moral practices developed. If conditions change radically perhaps Hobbesian scarcity comes to pass and death hangs in the balance then moral judgments might fail to motivate, but for a time at least they might still count as moral judgments because they would motivate in the normal conditions of non-scarcity and the absence of constant threat to life and limb. And now we can see how background, external conditions might play some role in determining whether an individual has a particular mental state. If the mental state type M is essentially part of a developed social practice as I have argued is the case with moral judgments then we have to look to the history of one s internal psychology and how it relates to social practices to determine whether a particular token state m is of the type M. There probably is no bright-line level of motivation that determines whether a society is more like our own, where amoralists render moral judgments, or more like Amoralsville, where they do not. 23

What is important is the history of interaction and the development of attitudes and other practices that enable cooperative social behaviors, which can occur in stages and degrees. Third, MJP offers a theory of how moral judgments are essentially action guiding. The connection between moral judgments and motivation extends beyond contingent relationships. To be sure, there is a sense in which it was entirely contingent whether moral practices and so moral judgments evolved to do the work that they in fact do. But the claim here is that, given the way the world is, and so, if I am right, given that moral judgment did evolve to do this work, the connection between moral judgment and motivation is not entirely contingent. Given the way the world is, it is not possible to have certain community-wide failures moral motivation. In the actual world moral judgments motivate most of the time, but more than this we can say that they are supposed to motivate, or have motivation as a purpose. Mental states without this purpose are not genuine moral judgments. Now I turn to address some potential criticisms of the view. V. Objections and Clarifications to the Purposive Perspective Perhaps most concerns about the view will focus on its adaptationist underpinnings. The evidence suggests that some moral behaviors including those that biologists call altruistic or cooperative were selected because they made moral actors more fit than their competitors, and this increased fitness depended on assortive interactions. Though different social groups could have developed slightly different ways of achieving these mutually beneficial outcomes, one might wonder whether this perspective makes moral behaviors look too monolithic. If moral behavior is merely fit behavior, then how do we distinguish moral from other kinds of behaviors that also contribute to fitness? In reality, our moral lives are very complex and one might wonder whether evolutionary modeling does justice to the complexity. 24