NOTES ON THE METHODS OF INQUIRY OF PLATO AND ARISTOTLE 373

Similar documents
Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

The Value of Mathematics within the 'Republic'

Aristotle on the Human Good

Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates Republic Symposium Republic Phaedrus Phaedrus), Theaetetus

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Reframing the Knowledge Debate, with a little help from the Greeks

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

A Happy Ending: Happiness in the Nicomachean Ethics and Consolation of Philosophy. Wesley Spears

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

Corcoran, J George Boole. Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2nd edition. Detroit: Macmillan Reference USA, 2006

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Care of the self: An Interview with Alexander Nehamas

Credibility and the Continuing Struggle to Find Truth. We consume a great amount of information in our day-to-day lives, whether it is

PHIL 260. ANCIENT GREEK PHILOSOPHY. Fall 2017 Tuesday & Thursday: (Oddfellows 106)

Special Issue on Ideas of Plato in the Philosophy of the 21st Century : An Introduction

VIRTUE ETHICS-ARISTOTLE

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Ed. Carroll Moulton. Vol. 1. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, p COPYRIGHT 1998 Charles Scribner's Sons, COPYRIGHT 2007 Gale

124 Philosophy of Mathematics

PRACTICE Midterm Examination SWU 252: Aesthetics for Life

Pierre Hadot on Philosophy as a Way of Life. Pierre Hadot ( ) was a French philosopher and historian of ancient philosophy,

Aristotle. Aristotle. Aristotle and Plato. Background. Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle and Plato

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

In order to enrich our experience of great works of philosophy and literature we will include, whenever feasible, speakers, films and music.

Greek Intellectual History: Tradition, Challenge, and Response Spring HIST & RELS 4350

Plato s. Analogy of the Divided Line. From the Republic Book 6

Objective vs. Subjective

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

observation and conceptual interpretation

Chapter 2: The Early Greek Philosophers MULTIPLE CHOICE

Fall 2018 TR 8:00-9:15 PETR 106

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Misc Fiction Irony Point of view Plot time place social environment

1/10. The A-Deduction

None DEREE COLLEGE SYLLABUS FOR: PH 4028 KANT AND GERMAN IDEALISM UK LEVEL 6 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3. (Updated SPRING 2016) PREREQUISITES:

Always More Than One Art: Jean-Luc Nancy's <em>the Muses</em>

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document

Types of Literature. Short Story Notes. TERM Definition Example Way to remember A literary type or

Nicomachean Ethics. p. 1. Aristotle. Translated by W. D. Ross. Book II. Moral Virtue (excerpts)

Aristotle The Master of those who know The Philosopher The Foal

Valuable Particulars

13th International Scientific and Practical Conference «Science and Society» London, February 2018 PHILOSOPHY

ARISTOTLE. PHILO 381(W) Sec. 051[4810] Fall 2009 Professor Adluri Monday/Wednesday, 7:00-8:15pm

Architecture is epistemologically

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

0:24 Arthur Holmes (AH): Aristotle s ethics 2:18 AH: 2:43 AH: 4:14 AH: 5:34 AH: capacity 7:05 AH:

PHILOSOPHY PLATO ( BC) VVR CHAPTER: 1 PLATO ( BC) PHILOSOPHY by Dr. Ambuj Srivastava / (1)

Republic Of Plato By Out Of Print READ ONLINE

Criterion A: Understanding knowledge issues

a story or visual image with a second distinct meaning partially hidden behind it literal or visible meaning Allegory

The Academic Animal is Just an Analogy: Against the Restrictive Account of Hegel s Spiritual Animal Kingdom Miguel D. Guerrero

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

Comparing Neo-Aristotelian, Close Textual Analysis, and Genre Criticism

Aristotle. By Sarah, Lina, & Sufana

2 nd Grade Visual Arts Curriculum Essentials Document

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Plato s Forms. Feb. 3, 2016

Colonnade Program Course Proposal: Explorations Category

CONRAD AND IMPRESSIONISM JOHN G. PETERS

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

7AAN2026 Greek Philosophy I: Plato Syllabus Academic year 2015/16

LANGUAGE THROUGH THE LENS OF HERACLITUS'S LOGOS

1. Physically, because they are all dressed up to look their best, as beautiful as they can.

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Why Pleasure Gains Fifth Rank: Against the Anti-Hedonist Interpretation of the Philebus 1

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

The Debate on Research in the Arts

On The Search for a Perfect Language

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

Kant, Peirce, Dewey: on the Supremacy of Practice over Theory

Chapter 1. The Power of Names NAMING IS NOT LIKE COUNTING

REVIEW ARTICLE BOOK TITLE: ORAL TRADITION AS HISTORY

THE RELATIONS BETWEEN ETHICS AND ECONOMICS: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS BETWEEN AYRES AND WEBER S PERSPECTIVES. By Nuria Toledano and Crispen Karanda

APHRA BEHN STAGE THE SOCIAL SCENE

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

Aesthetics Mid-Term Exam Review Guide:

Diotima s Speech as Apophasis

Julie K. Ward. Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) Mathesis Publications

II. Aristotle or Nietzsche? III. MacIntyre s History, In Brief. IV. MacIntyre s Three-Stage Account of Virtue

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Sidestepping the holes of holism

The Doctrine of the Mean

POLSC201 Unit 1 (Subunit 1.1.3) Quiz Plato s The Republic

A Process of the Fusion of Horizons in the Text Interpretation

HEGEL S CONCEPT OF ACTION

Humanities 116: Philosophical Perspectives on the Humanities

Do Universals Exist? Realism

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

Overcoming Attempts to Dichotomize the Republic

Integration, Ambivalence, and Mental Conflict

Transcription:

NOTES ON THE METHODS OF INQUIRY OF PLATO AND ARISTOTLE 373 Aristotle differs from Plato in more ways than he resembles him. NOTES ON THE METHODS OF INQUIRY OF PLATO AND ARISTOTLE PHILIP VASSALLO, ED.D. HAT DO WE MEAN by Platonic and Aristotelian thinking? Plato s dia- and Aristotle s treatises are sharply contrasting methods of in- Wlogues quiry because the two philosophers differed in at least three significant ways: their attitude toward inquiry, their notion of the nature of the inquiry, and the objective of their dialectic. This essay examines these three important elements as they relate to the philosophies of both men, whose legacy pervades not only how we think but what we think. Plato s Attitude Toward Inquiry It is unlikely that Plato wished to create a finite system to which the dialectic of all philosophers would be restricted. He abhorred rigid language and preferred a wide and familiar range of language and images to explain his ideas. (1) * Writing teacher, playwright, author of many articles and books, Philip Vassallo also writes ETC s Words on the Line feature. Reprinted with the author s permission from Inwardness of the Outward Gaze: Learning and Teaching Through Philosophy, available from PublishAmerica.com. Vassallo s book The Art of On-the-Job Writing is available from IGS. He accepts e-mail at Vassallo@aol.com. The author is especially grateful to Nora Miller for her help in editing this article. 373

374 ETC OCTOBER 2004 His system, if he had one, suggested that no one system could exist to provide desired outcomes; rather, his writings imply that the pursuit of truth while engaged in worthwhile endeavors was paramount. In fact, his aversion to a formulaic, inflexible treatment and explanation of philosophical foundations is made plain by the simple fact that he never described a method of inquiry. This absence of a clearly definable system is especially true in three dialogues: Protagoras, Meno, and Gorgias. In each, Plato poses the questions What is virtue? Can virtue be taught? and What end does oratory wish to achieve? But Socrates, the main character of each dialogue, never dictates to the reader what position to take. Plato s dialogues, like most philosophical conversations between two people, are not intended to provide a definitive answer to a universal question. And although Plato recorded his master Socrates remarkable dialogues, his intentions have been questioned by some scholars, who believe that he did not expect them to be historical documents. (2) Indeed, Plato believed that philosophy was not a literary device, and that it was best conveyed in the public arena. Gross (1968) suggests that Plato made a clear distinction between the written and spoken word: Plato appeared to distrust the written word as an adequate way of transmitting philosophic ideas. He claimed that only live speech, where the speaker could be cross-questioned, was the proper vehicle of philosophic thought. (3) Perhaps Plato cultivated his dialogic method because he found it to be the only way in which to examine questions about virtue, justice, and beauty; present the viewpoints of the dominant thinkers of his time; and demonstrate the manner in which the debates were conducted. Plato s Notion of the Nature of Inquiry In establishing his dialogic method, Plato wanted to mirror as closely as possible the actual process through which he, his teachers, and his students contemplated philosophy. J.J. Chambliss (1965) points out that the ideal educator has an affinity for the dialectic, which is so prominent in Plato s works: It is by a method akin to dialectic that a teacher uses words so that students may remind themselves of what is in them to be thought, and, for some, to be known. (4) Plato also had to consider the reason for committing the dialogues to paper. In concurring with the suggestion that Plato did not write the dialogues for

NOTES ON THE METHODS OF INQUIRY OF PLATO AND ARISTOTLE 375 posterity, Stokes (1986) theorizes that Plato probably wrote them for presentation purposes, much like a modern dramatist would create dialogue. Writing may often have been for purposes of check or reminder for oral recitation, rather than for wholly independent use. Plato s dialogues could very possibly rely on a substantial proportion of Athenians retaining powers of memory superior to our modern norm. Such a public would not need the explicitness of reference for a constantly and fluently reading, and hence less freely memorizing, one. (5) Thus, to Plato the dialogue could well have been intended as a fusion of philosophic commentary (in which the problems of man could be considered) and dramatic entertainment (in which such problems are considered before live audiences in a manner resembling live action as it was perceived at that time). Plato s Dialectical Objective A sound approach to understanding Plato s intentions is through Sallis s insightful study (1975) which describes three salient features in each of Plato s dialogues: dramatic character, soul, and playfulness. (6) By dramatic character, Sallis means the dimensionality between what is being said and the context in which it is said. Tejera (1984) calls this Plato s conceptual experiment:... a variable but visible format that underlies all the dialogues different as they are in their individual designs and that frees the author from the burden of overall doctrinal consistency (from dialogue to dialogue) by holding in a state of dramatic or conversational suspension and putting them in the mouths of likely speakers other than Plato himself. It is a format that exempts attempted solutions to philosophic problems from sounding or having to claim to be definitive. (7) The dramatic character of the dialogues gives us more to consider than merely the problem discussed or the author s viewpoint about it. We must also scrutinize each character s motivation, relationship to each other, and attitude about the issue at hand. Taylor (1926) stresses the importance of being aware of Plato s self-omission from the dialogues, especially when comparing Plato to his most famous student: Unlike Aristotle, (Plato) does not introduce himself and his opinions into his dialogues. He is, in fact, at great pains, with the instinct of the great dramatists, to keep his own personality in the background. (8)

376 ETC OCTOBER 2004 By soul is meant what the dialogues provoke the listener or reader to recollect. In Plato s case this is Truth. What distinguishes Plato from the other philosophers of his time is his rejection of opinion. Because of this, Solmsen (in Owen, 1968) reports that Plato places the dialectic as the highest form of communication, in a class of its own and of greater import than other branches of study such as mathematics and science: The dialectician must be able to render and receive account of what he knows. He must find his way or fight his way to the end through all scrutiny and must proceed in accordance with reality, not in accordance with opinion. (9) By playfulness is meant the engaging spirit in which philosophy is to be undertaken a spirit conducive to the interpretation of doctrine. As Guthrie (1956) says, we not only read a philosophical text, but we see it acted. (10) For Plato, this engaging spirit or dramatic quality affects not only the artistic setting and the personages, but the ideas which he brings upon the stage. The Platonic Socrates, under cover of an ironical profession of ignorance, employs a method to expose showy pretenders to universal knowledge, to produce a salutary conviction of ignorance, or to stimulate youthful thought, and prepare the way for a more serious analysis by an exposition of the antinomies latent in conventional opinion. (11) It is this same engaging spirit, however, that creates problems in interpreting Plato s objectives. Tejera insists that students of philosophy cannot distinguish between Plato s Socrates and the historical Socrates. (12) Gross suggests that different Platonic dialogues examining similar questions present answers in conflict with one another. (13) Plato s method, however, is more about what question is to be asked and how it is to be asked. Plato s Socrates spends a great deal of time in Gorgias trying to lay the groundwork for the deceptively simple question, what end does the orator seek? And this process is itself at the heart of Plato s method. One cannot choose to arbitrarily assign universals to situations occurring in the dialogues. At best we can look at the dialogues as attempts to formulate ways of asking philosophic questions, in the course of which certain hypotheses are put forth which are then subjected to incisive scrutiny. (14) In a sense, Plato s dialogues defy traditional explication because we cannot subject them to a literal interpretation as we can treatises. Tejera insists that a reader seeking to answer philosophic questions through Plato s characters must prove, among other matters, that the character speaks for Plato, that Plato meant the words literally, and that another character opposed to the proposed answer did not

NOTES ON THE METHODS OF INQUIRY OF PLATO AND ARISTOTLE 377 speak for Plato. (15) To do anything less would be to commit serious interpretive violence to the text. Aristotle s Attitude Toward Inquiry The perspective from which we may view Plato cannot provide focus when we examine the works of Aristotle. They are similar, however, in that neither philosopher sought to present a comprehensive system of philosophy. Moravcsik (1967) compares this characteristic of the two philosophers: Aristotle is one of those rare philosophers who wrote about an enormous range of topics within the fields of logic, ethics, philosophy of education, philosophy of science, philosophy of art, philosophy of language, epistemology, and metaphysics. But it is a mistake to think that his philosophy adds up either to a system or to a world view within which all answers within all these fields are organized and interrelated. In his philosophizing Aristotle seems to have kept in mind the ideal of the self-sufficient man, an ideal that both Plato and he espoused in their ethical writings; a self-sufficient man ought to be able to deal with any problem that he encounters even though he may not organize his answers into an axiomatic pattern, and even though he may come to the conclusion that different types of question require different types of answers. (16) But Aristotle differs from Plato in more ways than he resembles him. During the prime of his career, Aristotle saw a more book-oriented society and, therefore, had greater motivation to preserve his work than did his teacher. (17) While it is widely accepted that Aristotle s treatises are his lecture notes which have been edited and re-edited and translated and re-translated over the past two millennia which in part accounts for what Barnes (1976) calls a stark and abrupt style that is crammed with uncouth and technical terms (18) the massive scope of his written work suggests that he intended to lay the groundwork of a dialectical method which consistently aims to reach conclusions, even if these conclusions do not resolutely answer a posed question and cannot be reached the same way for all questions. Thus, with Aristotle we see a more systematic approach to inquiry than we do with Plato. As Hamlyn (1987) muses: Plato could never have written the mature works of Aristotle. If nothing else they were treatises, and Plato did not believe in such things. Aristotle clearly did, and what he wrote is a never-ending source of interest and fascination. (19)

378 ETC OCTOBER 2004 Aristotle s Notion of the Nature of Inquiry The study of Aristotle s philosophy necessarily begins with his criticism of Plato. Solmsen (1968) notes that the nucleus of Aristotle s paradigm is an attack on Plato s conception of philosophy: Aristotle draws a sharp line of separation between the dialecticians and those who impart technical or scientific instruction. It is the latter who start from first, albeit indemonstrable, principles of true quality and whose concern is with teaching and education. The men whom Aristotle here has in mind are primarily the mathematicians. Their procedure is clearly more solid and more scientific; by comparison with them the dialecticians begin to look rather dilettantish. (20) Evans (1977) sees this distinction by Aristotle as one of his greatest achievements and as an entrée into other fields of study: One of Aristotle s most important contributions to human thought was the idea that demarcation lines can be drawn between the different departments of expertise and that nothing is thereby lessened in the expertise of each distinct expert. In this his opposition to Plato is fundamental. For Plato believed that to know anything in the fullest sense it is necessary to know everything; he thought that any science or skill which is partial in its scope has only a limited claim to the title not simply of universal science but of science. (21) Aristotle, therefore, believes that the degree of certainty we reach in our inquiry of different subject matters is a function of the depths and limitations of those subject matters, not of some supreme dialectical method possessed only by the dialectician. This notion considerably influences the adaptive manner in which Aristotle approaches each discipline. Furthermore, it explains why he would prefer a non-dialogic method in his writings, for under investigation are the subject matter and his opinion of it, not the dramatic context or personal conflicts emanating from it. Aristotle s Dialectical Objective Aristotle s Ethics offers a fine example of his constant effort at classification of all types of knowledge, an effort that does not appear with as much frequency or structure in Plato s dialogues. Where Plato contemplates ceaselessly on virtue, Aristotle bypasses such agonizing determinations by classifying virtue into two types: moral and intellectual. He then further categorizes the intellect, or the rational part of the soul, into two parts: the contemplative, which

NOTES ON THE METHODS OF INQUIRY OF PLATO AND ARISTOTLE 379 considers invariable things, and the calculative, which considers variable things. To define the virtue of each, Aristotle does not seek a universal equation because each virtue is directly linked to its proper function. (22) While he does not lead us directly to a truth regarding virtue, he does tell us the five ways in which the truth can be reached through the intellect by means of affirmation or denial: via art, science, prudence, wisdom, and intuition. (23) In underscoring the difference between the two philosophers, Evans (1977) argues: Aristotle is concerned to show that (a) the activity of the dialectician does not amount to philosophy, despite the dialectician s belief to the contrary,... (b) what the dialectician is concerned with does form part of the philosopher s concern. Both (a) and (b) are necessary elements in Aristotle s defence of his conception of the universal study of Being against the main alternative contender for this title, Plato s conception of dialectic as the super-science. (a) is in effect the statement of Aristotle s opposition to the alternative position, but (b) is necessary to preclude the charge that Aristotle has ignored what is valuable in his opponents account and simply set up an alternative of his own which may have as much, but not necessarily any more, than the opposing account to recommend it. (24) While both Plato and Aristotle seek Truth, Aristotle submits that the means to Truth are through the many disciplines, each of them with a force of its own and with a significance neither subordinate nor superior to its counterpart fields of study. REFERENCES 1. Shorey, Paul. The Unity of Plato s Thought (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1903) p.4. 2. Hamlyn, D.W. A History of Western Philosophy (London: Penguin-Viking, 1987) p.45.

380 ETC OCTOBER 2004 3. Gross, Barry. The Many Meanings of Plato in The Great Thinkers on Plato, Barry Gross, Ed. (New York: G.P. Putnam s Sons, 1968) p.xii. 4. Chambliss, J.J. The Guardian: Plato in The Educated Man: Studies in the History of Educational Thought, Paul Nash, Andreas M. Kazamias, and Henry J. Perkinson, Eds. (New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1965) p.51. 5. Stokes, Michael C. Plato s Socratic Conversations: Drama and Dialectic in Three Dialogues (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1986) p.441. 6. Sallis, John. Being and Logos: The Way of Platonic Dialogue (Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1975) p.14-22. 7. Tejera, V. Plato s Dialogues One By One: A Structural Interpretation (New York: Irvington, 1984) p.90. 8. Taylor, p.24. 9. Solmsen, Friedrich. Dialectic Without Forms. In G.E.L. Owen, Aristotle on Dialectic: The Topics (London: Oxford University Press, 1968), p.49. 10. Guthrie, W.K.C., Trans. Plato: Protagoras and Meno (London: Penguin, 1956), p.7. 11. Shorey, p.6. 12. Tejera, p.29. 13. Gross, p.xii. 14. Ibid., p.xiii. 15. Tejera, p.4. 16. Moravcsik, J.M.E., Ed. Aristotle: A Collection of Critical Essays (Garden City: Anchor Doubleday, 1967) pp.7-8. 17. Stokes, p.442. 18. Barnes, Johnathan. Introduction to The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle, J.A.K. Thompson, Trans. (London: Penguin, 1976) p.14. 19. Hamlyn, p.76. 20. Solmsen, p.53. 21. Evans, J.D.G. Aristotle s Concept of the Dialectic (London: Cambridge University Press, 1977) p.7. 22. Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics, p.205. 23. Ibid., p.206. 24. Evans, p.13.