Giving Reasons, A Contribution to Argumentation Theory

Similar documents
Argumentation and persuasion

Marya Dzisko-Schumann THE PROBLEM OF VALUES IN THE ARGUMETATION THEORY: FROM ARISTOTLE S RHETORICS TO PERELMAN S NEW RHETORIC

DISSOCIATION IN ARGUMENTATIVE DISCUSSIONS

On the Concepts of Logical Fallacy and Logical Error

THE ANALYSIS AND EVALUATION OF LEGAL ARGUMENTATION: APPROACHES FROM LEGAL THEORY AND ARGUMENTATION THEORY

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Електронно научно списание Реторика и комуникации, бр. 22, април 2016 г.

Chaïm Perelman s New Rhetoric. Chaïm Perelman was a prominent rhetorician of the twentieth century. He was born in

PREFACE: THE VARIETY OF RESEARCH PERSPECTIVES IN THE STUDY OF ARGUMENTATION

This page intentionally left blank

Argumentation in Students Academic Discourse

Logic and argumentation techniques. Dialogue types, rules

Revisiting the Logical/Dialectical/Rhetorical Triumvirate

Logic, Truth and Inquiry (Book Review)

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

ISSA Proceedings 2002 Formal Logic s Contribution To The Study Of Fallacies

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

Argumentation Theory in Formal and Computational Perspective

Pragmatism, Pragma-Dialectics, and Methodology: Toward a More Ethical Notion of Argument Criticism

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

Argumentation Theory in Formal and Computational Perspective

Peterborough, ON, Canada: Broadview Press, Pp ISBN: / CDN$19.95

Developing the Universal Audience

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Principal version published in the University of Innsbruck Bulletin of 4 June 2012, Issue 31, No. 314

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

Claim: refers to an arguable proposition or a conclusion whose merit must be established.

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

Université Libre de Bruxelles

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Arguing or reasoning? Argumentation in rhetorical context

Humanities Learning Outcomes

Formalizing Irony with Doxastic Logic

Introduction: The Importance of Rhetoric for Argumentation

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

COMPUTER ENGINEERING SERIES

Partial and Paraconsistent Approaches to Future Contingents in Tense Logic

Pragmatics and Rhetoric for Discourse Analysis: Some conceptual remarks

Revista Iberoamericanade Argumentación

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Cultural Studies Prof. Dr. Liza Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati

TEST BANK. Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues

Fallacies and the concept of an argument

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Idealism and Pragmatism: "Transcendent" Validity Claims in Habermas's Democratic Theory

The Semantic Significance of Frege s Puzzle

Análisis Filosófico ISSN: Sociedad Argentina de Análisis Filosófico Argentina

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

MODULE 4. Is Philosophy Research? Music Education Philosophy Journals and Symposia

One Question, Two Answers

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1

The Normative Structure of Case Study Argumentation, Metaphilosophy, 24(3), 1993,

Common Ground, Argument Form and Analogical Reductio ad Absurdum

Law as Rhetoric, Rhetoric as Argument *

Introduction and Overview

Rhetoric, dialectic and logic: The triad decompartmentalized

Regression Model for Politeness Estimation Trained on Examples

French theories in IS research : An exploratory study on ICIS, AMCIS and MISQ

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

Leverhulme Research Project Grant Narrating Complexity: Communication, Culture, Conceptualization and Cognition

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

12th Grade Language Arts Pacing Guide SLEs in red are the 2007 ELA Framework Revisions.

A Rhetorical Turn for Argumentation

13th International Scientific and Practical Conference «Science and Society» London, February 2018 PHILOSOPHY

The Rhetorical Structure of Editorials in English, Swedish and Finnish Business Newspapers

Semiotics of culture. Some general considerations

Research Topic Analysis. Arts Academic Language and Learning Unit 2013

2 nd Grade Visual Arts Curriculum Essentials Document

More about Fallacies as Derailments of Strategic Maneuvering: The Case of Tu Quoque

AXIOLOGY OF HOMELAND AND PATRIOTISM, IN THE CONTEXT OF DIDACTIC MATERIALS FOR THE PRIMARY SCHOOL

CCCC 2006, Chicago Confucian Rhetoric 1

HEGEL S CONCEPT OF ACTION

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

Theories of linguistics

Ed. Carroll Moulton. Vol. 1. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, p COPYRIGHT 1998 Charles Scribner's Sons, COPYRIGHT 2007 Gale

GV958: Theory and Explanation in Political Science, Part I: Philosophy of Science (Han Dorussen)

How Coaches Maintain the Status Quo: An Application of Chaim Perelman s Values and Universal Audience to NPDA

What is Rhetoric? Grade 10: Rhetoric

Valuable Particulars

Tamar Sovran Scientific work 1. The study of meaning My work focuses on the study of meaning and meaning relations. I am interested in the duality of

Christopher W. Tindale, Fallacies and Argument Appraisal

A Computational Approach to Identifying Formal Fallacy

The Reason of Rhetoric

An essay on Alasdair MacIntyre s Relativism. Power and Philosophy

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document

The Cognitive Nature of Metonymy and Its Implications for English Vocabulary Teaching

BOOK REVIEW. 1 Evaluating arguments

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

Colonnade Program Course Proposal: Explorations Category

Cyclic vs. circular argumentation in the Conceptual Metaphor Theory ANDRÁS KERTÉSZ CSILLA RÁKOSI* In: Cognitive Linguistics 20-4 (2009),

REFERENCE GUIDES TO RHETORIC AND COMPOSITION. Series Editor, Charles Bazerman

Page109. Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions

PHILOSOPHY. Grade: E D C B A. Mark range: The range and suitability of the work submitted

Representation and Discourse Analysis

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Transcription:

BIBLID [0495-4548 (2011) 26: 72; pp. 273-277] ABSTRACT: In Giving Reasons: A Linguistic-pragmatic-approach to Argumentation Theory (Springer, 2011), I provide a new model for the semantic and pragmatic appraisal of argumentation. This model is based on a characterization of argumentation as a second order speech-act complex. I explain the advantages of this model respecting other proposals within Argumentation Theory, such as Pragma-dialectics, Informal Logic, the New Rhetoric or the Epistemic Approach. Keywords: argumentation theory; argumentation studies; linguistic-pragmatic approach; argumentation studies in Spain and Latin-America. RESUMEN: En Giving Reasons: A Linguistic-pragmatic-approach to Argumentation Theory (Springer, 2011), propongo un nuevo modelo para la evaluación semántica y pragmática de la argumentación. Este modelo se basa en una caracterización de la argumentación como un acto de habla compuesto de segundo orden. Explico las ventajas de este modelo respecto de otras propuestas dentro de la Teoría de la Argumentación, tales como la Pragma-dialéctica, la Lógica Informal, la Nueva Retórica o el Enfoque Epistémico. Palabras clave: teoría de la argumentación; estudios sobre argumentación; enfoque lingüístico-pragmático; estudios sobre argumentación en España y Latinoamérica. On the occasion of the publication of my book Giving Reasons: A Linguistic-pragmatic- Approach to Argumentation Theory (Springer, 2011), the journal THEORIA has invited some of the most outstanding scholars in the field to discuss the proposals advanced in the book. I wish to thank John Biro, James Freeman, David Hitchcock, Robert Pinto, Harvey Siegel and Luis Vega for their willingness to participate in this volume of THEORIA. Indeed, because I have followed or discussed many of their ideas all throughout this book, there is no better way to assess its strength and weaknesses than having their reactions and being offered the opportunity to respond. I can hardly express my gratitude for their generosity and for their insightful comments and criticisms. Within the realm of Argumentation Studies, Argumentation Theory is devoted to the normative study of natural language argumentation. The philosophical interest of such discipline can hardly be exaggerated. By arguing, we do not only coordinate beliefs and actions with others, but also acquire and transmit knowledge: after all, argumentation is a means to justify our claims and beliefs and to persuade others of them. For this reason, this discipline can be seen as a certain form of methodological inquiry particularly related to those areas of philosophy concerned with the conditions that turn mere beliefs into knowledge and with the conditions of legitimacy that sanction certain communicative interactions among individuals. Besides, philosophical practice itself is conducted, mostly, by arguments and, because of this, suitable normative mod- THEORIA 72 (2011): 273-277

274 els for argumentation would also seem to be necessary if philosophy is to achieve selfunderstanding and self-regulation. Indeed, these three factors ground the considerable interest that Plato and, specially, Aristotle had in the study of the relationships between Dialectics, Rhetoric and Logic. As with many other philosophical concerns, the remote origins of Argumentation Theory go back to that fruitful period of ancient Greek philosophy. Paradoxically, though, since then, philosophers had paid scant attention to the study of natural language argumentation as a subject matter, neglecting its characterization as a theoretical object and the provision of specific normative models for it. Somehow, there was the assumption that Logic, understood as a formal theory of valid inference, would suffice to do the work. The idea was that good argumentation is just argumentation which is good in its premises and inferences. And other types of argumentative flaws, like incorrectly changing the burden of proof, begging the question, using biased language, etc., which are rather answerable to the pragmatic dimension of argumentation as a communicative activity, did not receive a systematic treatment for centuries. This is why the development of Argumentation Theory as a discipline is, surprisingly, quite recent. It is only since the second half of last century that authors like Perelman and Toulmin pointed to the need of developing normative models for natural language argumentation. From two very different perspectives namely, logical and rhetorical, respectively Toulmin and Perelman tried to provide a framework for the assessment of real, everyday argumentation, under the assumption that Formal Logic was, at its best, insufficient for it. Toulmin and Perelman shared a philosophical interest in argumentation as an instrument and expression of practical and theoretical rationality. They showed the scantiness of previous accounts and provided guidelines for the development of Argumentation Theory proper. Nowadays, their works still reveal themselves as fruitful and alive approaches in many ways. However, since these seminar works, the field has experienced an enormous growth. From the late 70 s, the study of argumentation has attracted the attention of scholars from Philosophy, Linguistics, Communication Studies, Law, Psychology, etc. Several journals (like Argumentation, Informal Logic, Philosophy and Rhetoric, Argumentation & Advocacy, etc.), associations (like the International Society for the Study of Argumentation (ISSA), the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), the Association for Informal Logic and Critical Thinking (AILACT), etc.) and conferences (like the fourth-annual ISSA Conference, the biennial OSSA Conference, AFA/SCA Alta Conference, etc.) have been established in order to join efforts to understand natural language argumentation and to develop models to interpret, analyze and evaluate it. The realm of Argumentation Studies has become a multi-disciplinary field, and this circumstance has mutually enhanced the variety of perspectives, also within Argumentation Theory itself. Current proposals within Argumentation Theory have adopted a pragmatic perspective that has been displayed at two levels. The first one has been articulated through a conception of argumentation as a particular form of communication. In this sense, the interest in interpreting and analyzing real argumentative discourses and conversational exchanges would manifest most authors concern with the pragmatic

275 intricacies of argumentation as a certain kind of communicative activity. This concern amounted to a shift in perspective from arguments as merely abstract objects with solely logical properties, to argumentation as an activity also having a dialectical and a rhetorical dimension. However, in many cases, this pragmatic approach also gave rise to a new conception of argumentative value, namely, a conception replacing criteria to decide on the justificatory power of arguments for criteria to decide on the value of acts of arguing as means to achieve certain goals, like persuading a universal audience (the New Rhetoric approach by Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca 1958) or resolving a difference of opinion (the Pragma-dialectical Approach by van Eemeren and Grootendorst 1984). As a consequence, most contemporary argumentation theorists have assumed that good argumentation is argumentation able to achieve certain ends that, allegedly, would be characteristic of the practice of arguing. In previous works, I have called this view the instrumentalist conception of argumentative value and I have shown that it faces severe difficulties. Instead, I have argued for a conception of good argumentation as argumentation able to justify its target claim. In order to shape this intuition, I have followed two insightful ideas: on the one hand, Toulmin s defense of the view that the normativity of inference is a substantial matter rather than a formal one; and on the other, van Eemeren and Grootendorst s characterization of argumentation as a speech-act complex. Following these ideas, my main goal in Giving Reasons was to show that argumentative normativity, i.e., the articulation of the distinction between good and bad argumentation, should be cast in terms of argumentation s linguistic-pragmatic nature. Any theory dealing with the normative conditions of argumentation in terms of its features as a certain type of linguistic practice may be said to belong to a linguisticpragmatic approach to Argumentation Theory. In this respect, the particular theory of argumentation that I offer in Giving Reasons is just one of many possible ways of dealing with the normativity of argumentation from a linguistic-pragmatic perspective. Nevertheless, I use the label linguistic-pragmatic approach in order to contrast the theory I offer there with theories belonging to other general approaches such as the logical approach, the dialectical approach, the rhetorical approach or the epistemic approach to Argumentation Theory. As I try to show, one of the main rewards of thinking of argumentation, first and foremost, as a particular type of linguistic practice instead of thinking of argumentation as a logical product, as a dialectical procedure, as a rhetorical process or as an epistemological tool is to facilitate the integration of argumentation s logical, dialectical, rhetorical and epistemic dimensions. Actually, I think that integration along these lines is a well-established desideratum within the field. As I see it, the fact that most current proposals are answerable to the label logical, dialectical, rhetorical or epistemic may be symptomatic of a certain theoretical uneasiness. This uneasiness becomes especially evident when we consider that, so far, we have lacked unitary treatment of two key aspects of argumentation, namely, its justificatory power and its persuasive power. Current approaches tend to characterize argumentation either as a justificatory device that can eventually be used for persuading this is the case with

276 most theories that adopt logical or epistemic approaches or as a persuasive device whose legitimacy conditions would provide a particular account of justification as happens with the rhetorical approach and with some theories within the dialectical approach. A conception of argumentation as a speech-act complex is meant to be suitable for providing a unitary treatment of justification and reasoned persuasion, since it enables us to characterize argumentation as a justificatory device at its illocutionary level, whereas its paradigmatic persuasive power, i.e. the power of persuading by reasons, results from its ability to produce certain perlocutionary effects. The linguistic-pragmatic theory developed in Giving Reasons is a proposal about argumentation evaluation comparable to other normative proposals within the field, such as Pragma-dialectics, Informal Logic, the New Rhetoric or some epistemic theories of argumentation. However, I have tried to explain why a linguistic-pragmatic theory along these lines is to be preferred. In particular, I have tried to show that, unlike its rivals including Biro and Siegel s epistemological approach this theory avoids instrumentalism in its account of what good argumentation is; and it is only by avoiding instrumentalism that a normative theory of argumentation can overcome the justification problem that normative theories, in general, are bound to face. As part of the small community of argumentation theorists, I hope Giving Reasons turns out to be a well-oriented contribution to the advancement of the field. Besides, as a member of the Hispanic philosophical community, I wish it provided a spur to the growth of Argumentation Theory in Spain and Latin America. In these countries, despite the important work of pioneers such as Luis Vega, Raymundo Morado or Carlos Pereda, Argumentation Theory is just finding its way, and the number of financed research projects is still small. Nevertheless, the field is experiencing an increasing interest from young scholars and a growing presence in the programs of many degrees and masters in Philosophy and related areas. The fact that THEORIA, one of the most prestigious Spanish philosophical journals, has decided to devote this issue to Argumentation Theory is, I think, symptomatic and very encouraging indeed. I wish to thank the editors of THEORIA for the opportunity they have offered to my book and for their sensitiveness towards this emerging interdisciplinary research field. On the one hand, the possibility of having a public discussion of one s ideas is something very valuable for any author indeed. On the other, due to THEORIA s significant impact in the philosophical Spanish-speaking community, the publication of this volume is good news for all those interested in Argumentation Studies in our Ibero-American world. REFERENCES Bermejo-Luque, Lilian. 2011. Giving Reasons: A Linguistic-Pragmatic Approach to Argumentation Theory. Argumentation Library, vol. 20. Dordrecht: Springer. Eemeren, Frans H. van, and Rob Grootendorst. 1984. Speech Acts in Argumentative Discussions: A Theoretical Model for the Analysis of Discussions Directed towards Solving Conflicts of Opinion. Dordrecht: Foris. Perelman, Chaim, and Lucie Olbrechts-Tyteca. 1969/1958. The New Rhetoric: A Treatise on Argumentation. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

277 LILIAN BERMEJO-LUQUE is a researcher at the Institute of Philosophy of the Spanish National Research Council (CSIC). She is the author of the book Giving Reasons. A linguistic-pragmatic approach to Argumentation Theory and editor of the journal Revista Iberoamericana de Argumentación. ADDRESS: Instituto de Filosofía, CCHS CSIC. c/ Albasanz, 26-28. 28037 Madrid, Spain. E-mail: lilian.bermejoluque@gmail.com