FOUR QUESTIONS ABOUT ACQUIRED PERCEPTION. through three steps that may be characterized schematically as follows: (i) On the

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "FOUR QUESTIONS ABOUT ACQUIRED PERCEPTION. through three steps that may be characterized schematically as follows: (i) On the"

Transcription

1 1 FOUR QUESTIONS ABOUT ACQUIRED PERCEPTION Acquired perception is the name Reid gives to a cognitive phenomenon that arises through three steps that may be characterized schematically as follows: (i) On the occasion of sensation S, I form (in accordance with my native constitution) a conception of and a belief in the presence of some external object or quality A. This much is original perception. (ii) As time goes by, I find that my perceptions of A are always or nearly always accompanied by perceptions (perhaps belonging to another sense) of some other object or quality, B. I develop the habit of thinking that B is present on occasions when I perceive A even if I have not yet perceived B. (iii) Eventually, the association between A and B becomes so strong that on the occasion of perceiving A, I automatically conceive of and believe in B without making any inference. I now have acquired perception of the quality B. 1 Reid s favorite examples of acquired perception are the perception of distance and three-dimensional figure by sight. Reid agrees with Berkeley that what is given originally to sight is only a two-dimensional array in which objects are displayed as having locations along the left-right and up-down axes, but not along the near-far axis. Outness and three-dimensional shapes (such as being cubical or spherical) are given originally only to touch. 2 By experience, however, we come to learn that certain sensations connected with adjusting the trim of the eye and certain patterns of light and 1 Reid s views on acquired perception are concentrated in Chapter 6, Sections 20-24, of An Inquiry into the Human Mind, cited henceforth in the text as IHM , and in Essay 2, Chapters 21and 22, of the Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, cited henceforth in the text as EIP I think Reid and Berkeley are wrong about this. Outness is originally given to sight, owing partly to stereopsis, a mechanism not known in their time. In this paper, though, I will go along with them for the sake of being able to work with their examples.

2 2 shadow are signs of distance and three-dimensional convexity. Eventually, we automatically conceive of and believe in a globe when we see an appropriately shaded disk. It is almost as though we see the convexity of the globe: It is experience that teaches me that the variation of colour is an effect of spherical convexity, and of the distribution of light and shade. But so rapid is the progress of the thought, from the effect to the cause, that we attend only to the last, and can hardly be persuaded that we do not immediately see the three dimensions of the sphere. (EIP 2.12, p. 236) Other examples of acquired perception are hearing the size of a bell (EIP 2.14, p. 182) and seeing the weight of a sheep (IHM 6.20, p. 172). In this essay, I take up the following four questions. (1) Is acquired perception really perception? (2) Are secondary qualities objects of original perception, or of acquired perception only? (3) Does acquired perception involve any alteration in the content of our original perceptions? Finally, (4) are there any limits in principle to what might one day become an object of acquired perception for us? Before we get to these questions, however, it is necessary to say a little more about the mechanics of acquired perception. 0. The mechanics of acquired perception Reid first draws the distinction between original and acquired perception in the Inquiry in the following passage: Our perceptions are of two kinds: some are natural and original, others acquired, and the fruit of experience. When I perceive that this is the taste of cyder, that of brandy; that this is the smell of an apple, that of an orange; that this is the noise of thunder, that the ringing of bells; this the sound of a coach passing, that the voice of such a friend; these perceptions and others of the same kind, are not original, they are acquired. But the perception which I have by touch, of the hardness and softness of bodies, of their extension, figure, and motion, is not acquired, it is original. (IHM 6.20, p. 171) The distinction is further elaborated in the chapter of the Intellectual Powers entitled Of the improvement of the senses (2.21), where it is illustrated by Reid s favorite example

3 3 of it the acquired visual perception of three-dimensional figure on the basis of originally perceived two-dimensional signs. In what way are acquired perceptions the fruit of experience? There are two models to consider, an inference model and an association model. In the inference model, after being exposed to many cases of B conjoined with A (for instance, spherical shape with a certain pattern of shading), we form in accordance with induction the general belief Anything that looks like this is a sphere. On subsequent occasions of something s looking that way, we draw the inference It looks like this, and things that look like this are spheres; therefore, it is a sphere. After several such occasions, the inference becomes fully automated: when we see something that looks the right way, we believe forthwith that it is a sphere, no longer passing through a major premise of the form All As are Bs or combining it with a minor premise of the form o is an A to conclude o is a B. We simply leap to the belief that o is a B. We now have an acquired perception that the thing we are perceiving is a B. In the association model, we go through the same history of experiencing As in conjunction with Bs as above, but we never form the explicit general belief that As are Bs (or if we do, we never use it as a premise in an inference). We simply form an association between As and Bs, which eventually becomes strong enough that on the occasion of perceiving an A, we instantly believe that it is a B. We now have an acquired perception that the thing we are perceiving is a B. In either model, we have acquired perception only when the transition from A- perceptions to B-beliefs has become fully automatic and no longer (if it ever was) a matter of inference. The difference is that in the association model, we do not go through

4 4 an inferential phase on our way to acquiring the acquired perception; in the inference model, we do. We might put the matter thus: the inference model posits a phase in which the subject has a belief in a constant conjunction, symbolizable as S believes (x)(ax Bx) ; the association model need posit no more than a constant conjunction of beliefs, symbolizable as (x)(s believes Ax S believes Bx). Which model did Reid intend? I do not think he cared; so long as the product is right, the process does not matter. His indifference is shown in his indiscriminate use of two different formulations of the inductive principle that underlies our ability to form acquired perceptions: When we have found two things to have been constantly conjoined in the course of nature, the appearance of one of them is immediately followed by the conception and belief of the other. (IHM 6.24, p. 196, lines 1-3; see also p. 197, lines 9-11.) Thus, if a certain degree of cold freezes water to-day, and has been known to do so in all time past, we have no doubt but the same degree of cold will freeze water tomorrow, or a year hence. (IHM 6.24, p. 196, lines 10-12; see also p. 197, lines 6-8.) In the first formulation, the inductive principle is said to produce in our minds a constant conjunction of beliefs; in the second, it is said to produce belief in a constant conjunction. Here and elsewhere, Reid uses the two formulations interchangeably. I end this section by commenting on the relation of Reid s account of acquired perception to ideas in three other writers, Berkeley, Helmholtz, and Ryan Nichols. Berkeley. Reid is indebted to Berkeley for many examples of acquired perception, which Berkeley often describes using the term suggestion. Suggestion is the automatic triggering of conception and belief in one thing by the sensation or perception of another, as when a blush suggests shame or a word suggests its denotatum. In the following passage, Berkeley explicitly distinguishes suggestion from inference:

5 5 To perceive is one thing; to judge is another. So likewise to be suggested is one thing, and to be inferred another. Things are suggested and perceived by sense. We make judgments and inferences by the understanding. (Sec. 42 of the Theory of Vision Vindicated; 1975, p. 293) Reid s notion of acquired perception and Berkeley s notion of suggestion could be said to be related as follows: A suggests B to person S iff whenever S experiences A, S has an acquired perception of B for which A serves as the sign. Helmholtz. Whereas Berkeley says that certain of our perceptions are based on suggestion, not inference, Helmholtz says that they are based on unconscious inference. Is there a disagreement between them? Robert Schwartz (1994) notes that the psychological reality of the major premise All As are Bs in what Helmholtz calls inference may simply consist in the disposition of A ideas to trigger B ideas what I have called a constant conjunction of beliefs. In that case, the difference between Helmholtz and Berkeley would be merely verbal. Nichols. Ryan Nichols distinguishes two types of acquired perception in Reid: inferential perception (really an oxymoron, given that there is no reasoning in perception), in which one makes a conscious inductive inference from some perceived quality A to a further quality B, and habituated perception, in which the perception of a thing as being A makes one automatically believe it to be B, owing to the subject s previous history of inferential perceptions that a thing is B based on its being A (2007, pp ). If these two types are exhaustive, it follows that all acquired perception is built on previous inference. However, despite this implication, I do not believe Nichols intends to force an inferential model on Reid. On p. 235, he seems to want to keep the possibility of an associationist model open. 1. Is acquired perception really perception?

6 6 Acquired perception is a powerful means of gaining information through the senses, but is it really perception? We cannot let the issue be decided by Reid s name for the phenomenon. A toy gun is not a gun, and artificial teeth are not teeth. By contrast, a toy block is a block, and artificial illumination is illumination. 3 My question is whether acquired perception is like artificial illumination or artificial teeth. Berkeley s answer to this question is clear and explicit: In short, those things alone are actually and strictly perceived by any sense, which would have been perceived, in case that same sense had then been first conferred on us. (1975, p. 194; 1948, p. 204) By this criterion, what we perceive only with the help of learning we do not strictly perceive at all. Had we just now been given sight without any opportunity to learn correlations between the visible and the tangible, sight would afford us no clue of distance or three-dimensional shape. Berkeley unhesitatingly concludes that these properties are not strictly perceived by sight. 4 Reid s answer to our question is more equivocal. After describing several apparent instances of acquired perception for example, a farmer s apprehension that his neighbor s cattle have broken loose, based on the down-trodden state of his corn he remarks, These are instances of common understanding, which dwells so near to perception, that it is difficult to trace the line which divides the one from the other. (IHM 6.20, p. 173) 5 3 Thanks to Roy Sorensen (personal communication) for these examples. 4 To be sure, Berkeley has a broad sense of perceive in which we may be said to perceive anything that is suggested to our imagination by a sensible cue, including the shame in another s soul when it is suggested by a blush and even God when we are made to think of him by the word God. But things perceived in this broad sense are not immediately perceived, and Berkeley insists that only things immediately perceived are sensible things, or things perceived by the senses. By sensible things I mean those only which are perceived by sense, and that in truth the senses perceive nothing which they do not perceive immediately (1975, p.164; 1948, p. 174). 5 In Reid s examples in this paragraph, the various facts perceived are all facts about the recent past. Elsewhere, he says perception always has a present object. (See EIP 1.1, p. 23, lines 1-9.) For this reason,

7 7 In another passage, he describes a case in which he at first mistook a nearby seagull on a foggy beach for a man on horseback half a mile off. (Fog throws off our acquired perceptions of distance). He observes, The mistake made on this occasion, and the correction of it, are both so sudden, that we are at a loss whether to call them by the name of judgment, or by that of simple perception. (IHM 6.22, p. 183) In yet another passage, he calls the whole question I am raising a verbal one: [When a kind of judgment becomes habitual] it very much resembles the original perceptions of our sense, and may not improperly be called acquired perception. Whether we call it judgment or acquired perception is a verbal difference. (EIP 2.14, p. 182) Even if Reid refused to answer to my question, is there an answer he ought to have given in light of his other commitments? Rebecca Copenhaver has forcefully argued that Reidian acquired perception in no way falls short of genuine perception (2010). In the rest of this section, I offer five arguments to the contrary. First argument: acquired perception is not immediate. One of the hallmarks of perception for Reid is that it is immediate. Here is his official threefold account of perception: If, therefore, we attend to that act of our mind which we call the perception of an external object of sense, we shall find in it these three things. First, Some conception or notion of the object perceived. Secondly, A strong and irresistible conviction and belief of its present existence. And, thirdly, That this conviction and belief are immediate, and not the effect of reasoning. (EIP 2.5, p. 96, and repeated elsewhere) If it turns out that acquired perception is not immediate in the requisite sense, we will have the materials for the following syllogism: 1. All genuine perception is immediate perception. I am not sure whether he would regard these instances of quasi-perceptual common understanding as cases of acquired perception.

8 8 2. No acquired perception is immediate perception. 3. Therefore, no acquired perception is genuine perception. What, then, is the requisite sense? What all does Reid mean by calling perception (or the belief involved therein) immediate? Much of the time, Reid simply means that no reasoning or inference is involved, psychologically speaking. There is no marshalling of premises and drawing of conclusions. If this is all he ever means by immediacy, the syllogism above would have a false minor premise. As discussed in the preceding section, even if inference is part of the process by which acquired perception is developed, once the habit is fully acquired, the inference is no longer there. The transition from sensory sign to perceptual belief in the thing signified has become fully automated, and no vestiges of reasoning remain. Nonetheless, there is another sense in which it is arguable that genuine perception is immediate for Reid and acquired perception not. Genuine perception is immediate in an epistemic sense: deliverances of perception are immediately justified, that is, justified without deriving their justification from any other beliefs. In Reid s favored terminology, deliverances of perception are first principles. But acquired perceptions do not seem to be like that. Even though my perceptual belief that the bell I am hearing is large is psychologically noninferential, it is justified only because on many past occasions when I heard similar sounds, I knew by sight or touch that they came from a large bell. 6 Had I not been justified on those sundry occasions in what I believed about the source of the sound, I would not be justified now. Thus my current belief is not epistemically immediate. 6 What I mean by perceptual belief in this sentence is the belief that is ingredient in perception in Reid s threefold account. I am departing from the terminology of Copenhaver, who uses perceptual belief for a further belief based on the perception.

9 9 On this point, I agree with Nichols: [H]abituated perceptual beliefs... depend for their justification upon other perceptual beliefs upstream in the belief-forming and habit-forming processes. In this sense, habituated perceptual beliefs could not serve as basic beliefs in a foundationalist theory of the structure of empirical knowledge (p. 237). 7 However, Nichols and I do not agree on the other premise in the argument from immediacy that all genuine perception is epistemically immediate. He maintains that Reid is an epistemic direct realist one who holds that the deliverances of perception are epistemically basic or immediately justified only as regards the deliverances of original perception. In the inconsistent triad {all perception is immediate perception, acquired perception is not immediate perception, acquired perception is perception}, we both accept the second proposition, but he chooses to deny the first and I the third. Since the matter is controversial, I shall not rest my case entirely on the argument from immediacy. Second argument: I do not perceive my upstairs wife. In previous work (Van Cleve 2004), I advanced the following example as a conundrum for Reid s theory of perception: I return home and see my wife s car keys on the counter, whereupon I automatically conceive of her and believe that she is home. Since she is upstairs, I do not perceive her, but it seems that I fulfill all the conditions for [acquired] perception (p. 127). This example can be made the basis of the following argument: 1. I have an acquired perception of my wife on the occasion of seeing her keys. 2. In fact, I do not perceive her on that occasion. 3. Therefore, not all cases of acquired perception are cases of perception. 7 For further reinforcement of this point, see Pollock s discussion (1974, pp ) of the principle of implicit reasons, according to which our justification for believing things may derive from general propositions that we may never have articulated and the supporting instances for which we no longer specifically recall, provided our past observation of the instances played a causal role in generating our present belief.

10 10 Some friends and interpreters of Reid have taken exception to the first premise. Nichols opposes it on the ground that the example is out of character with Reid s other examples of acquired perception (2007, p. 232), 8 and Copenhaver opposes it on the ground that my wife does not enter into the content of my car-key perception in the way she thinks required for bona fide acquired perception (2010, p. XX). 9 Yet it seems to me that my critics must concede that the example contains all the ingredients that Reid ever lists as necessary for acquired perception. I do have a conception of my wife, I do believe in her present (and nearby) existence, this conception and belief have been produced in me by the past association between seeing her keys and subsequently seeing her in the flesh, and this conception and belief now arise in me as automatically as the conception and belief in any other case of acquired perception. 10 If this is not a case of acquired perception, it must be because there are conditions of acquired perception that are yet to be articulated. One additional condition to propose on Reid s behalf might be this: in acquired perception, the signifying item and the signified item must be qualities of the same object. This would rule out perceiving my wife by perceiving her keys, since my wife is 8 See Reid s examples at IHM, p. 173, however, for examples not far removed from my own. 9 Copenhaver develops a three-fold distinction among beliefs ingredient in perception, beliefs formed on the basis of perception, and beliefs inferred from perception. She regards the belief that one s spouse is home as a belief belonging to the middle category a belief formed on the basis of perceiving the keys. However, she also explicitly argues that beliefs that initially belong to categories two or three may migrate (in the development of acquired perception) into category one they may become perceptual contents or beliefs ingredient in perception, as happens when someone becomes expert at spotting counterfeit coins. I should like to know from Copenhaver what, if anything, keeps belief in my upstairs wife from becoming a perceptual content. 10 What of Reid s requirement that the belief that is an ingredient in perception be irresistible? If that rules out acquired perception of my upstairs wife, it also rules out many of Reid s own examples of acquired perception for instance, that this is the handwriting of such-and-such a friend (IHM 6.20, p. 172). Perhaps I can resist believing that my wife is home by supposing she has been kidnapped, but so likewise can I resist believing that this is her handwriting by supposing it to be a clever forgery.

11 11 not a quality of the keys. 11 It would also rule out kindred cases such as seeing the fire over the ridge by seeing the smoke produced by it. Even with that condition in play, however, it will be possible to generate examples of acquired perception that we may well hesitate to classify as perception. A colorblind motorist can see that a traffic light is red by seeing that the illuminated light is the one in the top position. Here the signifying quality (place) and the signified quality (color) are qualities of the same object, so our motorist satisfies our latest condition for having an acquired perception of the color of the light. But does he perceive the redness of the light? No, for he is colorblind. 12 The car-key example in my 2004 was not actually meant in the first instance to be a counterexample to all acquired perception is perception as a Reidian thesis. It could not be a counterexample to that, since the reasons for thinking that the example satisfies all the conditions for my having an acquired perception of my wife that I conceive of her, etc. are also reasons for thinking that the example satisfies all the conditions for my having a perception of her simpliciter. The example is really a counterexample to Reid s account of perception at large, indicating that his standard threefold account either leaves out some crucial ingredient in perception or else fails to make explicit some way in which one of the included ingredients is to be understood. My suggestion in 2004 was that Reid should be understood thus: the conception that is involved in perception must be conception of the acquaintance variety. It must not merely be conception of something 11 Someone could try to surmount the proposed restriction by saying my keys have a wife-is-home-y quality about them. Being such that my wife is home is a property of the keys a Cambridge property, to be sure signified by their being on the counter. If the requirement that signifying qualities and signified qualities must belong to the same object is to do the work desired of it, then, we will have to require as well that Cambridge properties not be among the signified qualities. 12 If you doubt that the colorblind person can conceive of redness, assume that he once had normal vision and acquired the ability to conceive of redness at that time. Not all colorblindness is congenital.

12 12 by means of some description it satisfies. That is why I do not perceive my wife on the occasion of seeing her keys: though I may conceive of her under some description, I am not acquainted with her in any way, shape, or form. Instead of acquaintance, why not appeal to the epistemic immediacy discussed above, saying that genuine perception must be epistemically immediate and my acquired perception of my wife is not? That seems right to me, but it cannot be the full story. Epistemic properties supervene on nonepistemic properties, and we would have to say what the relevant nonepistemic properties are. Perhaps genuine perception is epistemically immediate precisely because it incorporates acquaintance. I went on to suggest in 2004 (and I urge again now) that by the acquaintance standard, few cases of acquired perception qualify as perception. Thus even if the carkey example does not underwrite the simple argument above, it does serve in the end to motivate the claim that not all acquired perception is perception. Third argument: I do not perceive by sight the heat of the poker. One of the remarkable features of acquired perception is that it enables us to jump across sensory modalities, perceiving by one sense qualities that were originally given only to another. As Reid tells us, We learn to perceive, by one sense, what originally could have been perceived only by another, by finding a connection between the objects of the different senses. (EIP 2.21, p. 236) [By means of acquired perception] we often discover by one sense things which are properly and naturally the objects of another. Thus I can say without impropriety, I hear a drum, I hear a great bell, or I hear a small bell; though it is certain that the figure or size of the sounding body is not originally an object of hearing. (EIP 2.14, p. 182)

13 13 Berkeley gives another example of the same phenomenon seeing the heat of a red-hot bar of iron when the heat of the iron is suggested to the imagination by the colour and figure, which are properly perceived by that sense (1975, p.194; 1948, p. 204). 13 Using this example to explicate what Berkeley means by immediate when he says we do not perceive distance immediately, George Pitcher writes as follows: A person, when he views a red, glowing poker that has just been taken from a roaring furnace... sees that the poker is very hot, but he does not really see the heat itself.... Just so, Berkeley tells us, a person can see that something is located at such-and-such a distance from him; but he cannot see the distance.... To say that we do not literally see the heat of the poker... is to say that the visual manifold of which we are aware when we see a hot poker does not contain any heat in it. Similarly, to say that we do not literally see the distance of objects is to say that the visual manifold of which we are aware when we see them does not contain distance. (1977, pp. 7-8) Pitcher is endorsing Berkeley s own view as quoted earlier that we actually and strictly perceive by any sense only those things we would perceive if that same sense had then been first conferred on us. Drawing on examples of this sort, we may now construct another argument for the thesis that not all acquired perception is perception: 1. There are some properties that are proper to a given sense, as heat to touch: they cannot be strictly perceived by any other sense. 2. We sometimes have acquired perceptions through one sense of qualities proper to another. 3. Therefore, we sometimes have acquired perceptions that are not perceptions. This argument seems intuitively compelling to me, and I shall let it stand without further comment on its merits. 13 Berkeley actually speaks of being said to see a red-hot iron bar, but it is clear from the context that he means to discuss the sense in which one sees the heat of the bar, not just the sense in which one sees a bar that is hot.

14 14 I do, however, wish to take this occasion to discuss another issue prompted by Pitcher the relationship between the original/acquired distinction and a further distinction invoked in Pitcher s remarks. Pitcher is willing to allow that we see that the poker is hot, but not that we see the heat itself. Implicit here is a distinction between propositional perception and objectual perception. Propositional perception is perception that p, for example, perception that O is F. Objectual perception is perception simply of O (an object) or of the Fness of O (a quality of an object), where these do not resolve into propositional perception. 14 With this distinction in mind, let s look again at a passage from Reid: Our perceptions are of two kinds: some are natural and original, others acquired, and the fruit of experience. When I perceive that this is the taste of cyder, that of brandy; that this is the smell of an apple, that of an orange; that this is the noise of thunder, that the ringing of bells; this the sound of a coach passing, that the voice of such a friend; these perceptions and others of the same kind, are not original, they are acquired. But the perception which I have by touch, of the hardness and softness of bodies, of their extension, figure, and motion, is not acquired, it is original. (IHM 6.20, p. 171) It is striking that every one of Reid s examples of acquired perception in this passage is a case of propositional perception, while each of his examples of original perception is a case of objectual perception. Are the two distinctions aligned in Reid s thought is every case of original perception a case of objectual perception and every case of acquired perception a case of propositional perception? Ordinary people sometimes use S sees the Fness of O simply as a stylistic variant of S sees that O is F (as in Tom saw the hopelessness of his situation.). Some philosophers allow that S sees O is a permissible locution, but only if it is unpackable into EF(S sees that O is F). What I mean by objectual perception is perception of O (or the Fness of O) that is not in either of these ways equivalent to anything propositional. 15 Reid probably meant the distinction between original and acquired perception to be exhaustive, but he overlooked an intermediate case. Suppose that some years after my birth, someone programs my brain so that upon smelling a certain scent, I automatically believe that there are oranges nearby. The resulting perception would be neither original (because it does not arise in me by my native constitution) nor acquired (because it is not acquired by experience).

15 15 The answer to the first question is no. Reid s language indicates that there may be propositional perception in regard to the objects of original perception for example, we perceive visible objects to have extension in two dimensions (EIP 6.21, p. 236), and I may perceive that there is in my hand a hard smooth body of a spherical figure (EIP 6.21, p. 237). Of course, we may also have objectual perceptions of the objects and qualities that are constituents of those propositions. The answer to the second question is harder to determine. There are passages in which Reid does use objectual locutions to refer to acquired perceptions for example, hearing the size of a bell (EIP 2.14, p. 182) and seeing the weight of a sheep (IHM 6.20, p.172). 16 But insofar as people sometimes use objectual locutions as stylistic variants of propositional ones, these passages do not settle the question. Reid might speak of the butcher s seeing the weight of the sheep even if he thinks that strictly speaking, the butcher only sees that the sheep weighs so much. So the answer to the second question is not clear. It is a thesis worthy of consideration that whereas genuine perception may take either an objectual or a propositional form, acquired perception may take a propositional form only. If the thesis were true, it would give us one more reason for thinking that acquired perception is not genuine perception. Fourth argument: errors in acquired perception are not errors of the senses. Perhaps the best case for thinking acquired perception is not perception in Reid s book is to be found in EIP 2.22, Of the fallacy of the senses. The purpose of this chapter is to refute the opinion of those philosophers who maintain that the senses are systematically 16 He actually says knows by sight the weight of his sheep, but in the other examples in the same paragraph, he uses perceives by his eye and sees as though all three were equivalent.

16 16 fallacious, or at any rate, that they often deceive us. Reid admits that the senses sometimes deceive us, his leading example being the case of phantom pain felt in a limb no longer possessed (EIP 2.18, p. 214 and 2.22, p. 251). But he maintains that most socalled fallacies of the senses are not fallacies of the senses at all; they are errors, but not errors of the senses proper. Reid distinguishes four classes of alleged errors of the senses, of which only the fourth class contains errors of the senses properly so called (such as pain felt in a phantom limb). The first class is described (and dismissed) in the following paragraph: Many things called deceptions of the senses are only conclusions rashly drawn from the testimony of the senses....thus, when a man has taken a counterfeit guinea for a true one, he says his senses deceived him; but he lays the blame where it ought not to be laid: For we may ask him, Did your sense give a false testimony of the colour, or of the figure, or of the impression? No. But this is all that they testified, and this they testified truly: From these premises you concluded that it was a true guinea, but this conclusion does not follow. (EIP 2.22, p. 244) What I want to call special attention to in this passage is that the only qualities Reid mentions as being testified to by the senses are color, figure, and impression. These are all on the list of original objects of perception. 17 In other nearby places, he uses interchangeably the expressions what our senses testify and what we perceive. 18 So it is tempting to generalize from the guinea example to the following claim: the only objects we strictly perceive are the objects of original perception. Putting it the other way around, acquired perception is not perception strictly speaking. 17 Color and figure are objects of original perception by sight. I am not sure what he means by impression. Perhaps he means the pattern impressed on the coin, which would be an original object of sight in two dimensions and of touch in three, or perhaps he means its heft, which would be an original object of touch. 18 For example, at EIP 6.22, p. 246, he says Our senses testify only the change of situation of one body in relation to other bodies and restates this one sentence later as It is only the relative motions of bodies that we perceive.

17 17 The second class of alleged errors of the senses are errors we make in our acquired perceptions. Reid tells us that if acquired perception could be resolved into some form of reasoning, this class would reduce to the first class along with the false guinea, but since he thinks acquired perception results from some part of our constitution distinct from reason, he makes it a class of its own (EIP 2.22, p. 247). In any case, Reid maintains that the errors of acquired perception are not properly fallacies of our senses (ibid.). For example, if I am deceived by a clever painter into believing that a flat patch on canvas is really a sphere, I am in error, but my error lies not in original but in acquired perception. The objects of original perception the light and colors are distributed just as my senses say they are. What Reid unequivocally affirms here is that errors in acquired perception are not errors of the senses. This provides the take-off point for the following argument: 1. No error in acquired perception is an error of the senses (premise). 2. If every acquired perception is an exercise of the senses, then every error in acquired perception is an error (in an exercise) of the senses. (This is a logical truth; compare DeMorgan s If every horse is an animal, then every head of a horse is a head of an animal.) 3. Therefore, not every acquired perception is an exercise of the senses (from 1 and 2). 4. Every genuine perception is an exercise of the senses (premise). 5. Therefore, not every acquired perception is a genuine perception (from 3 and 4). That argument seems to me decisive. However, as noted above, Copenhaver stands on the opposite side of the issue, holding that acquired perception is in all cases perception. She has sought to defuse the textual argument based on premise 1 above by proposing that error of sense is a technical term for Reid. She takes it to refer specifically to errors in original perception. This proposal apparently keeps the door

18 18 open for saying that errors in acquired perception, though not errors of sense in the technical sense, can nonetheless be cases of misperception, as required by her view. However, her proposal does nothing to block the argument as I have stated it. The premises are 1, 2 and 4, and her proposal leaves all of them standing. 19 The question whether acquired perception is genuine perception has been reincarnated in contemporary philosophy of mind as the question whether so-called higher-level properties (properties such as being a pine tree or being an apple, which are not on Reid s list of objects of original perception) can be represented in perception. That is, can such properties belong to the contents of perception proper and not just to the contents of beliefs formed on the basis of perception? Susanna Siegel (2006) offers the following test question as a diagnostic for determining one s stand: if you are taken in by a bowl of wax fruit, is your error an error in perception or an error in accompanying belief? If your visual experience represents only colors and shapes, you have made an error in belief; if it represents apples and pears, you have made an error in perception. 20 It seems to me that in his discussion of the fake apple made of turf, Reid has given as explicit an answer as one could like to Siegel s question: your error is an error in belief, not in perception (EIP 2.22, p. 245). Fifth argument: speak with the vulgar, but think with the learned. For my final argument, I let Reid speak for himself: 19 Perhaps one could maintain that if error of sense has a technical meaning in Reid, one cannot drop the parenthetical expression in my premise 2, shortening error in an exercise of the senses to error of the senses. I need take no stand on that. I can stay with the longer formulation of premise 2, under which it is a logical truth. And I can rewrite premise 1 as No error in acquired perception is an error in an exercise of the senses to make it engage with premise 2. It is clear that Reid would assert 1 in either the longer or the shorter version. 20 In this context, Copenhaver remarks, It is precisely because we are perceptually sensitive to such features as being a tomato and being a quarter that we may be misled by wax vegetables and counterfeits. I do not see why that is so. Even if the content of my perception were limited to colors and shapes, could it not still mislead me into believing falsely that there is a tomato in the bowl?

19 19 Acquired perception is not properly the testimony of those senses which God hath given us, but a conclusion drawn from what the senses testify.... The appearance of the sign immediately produces the belief of its usual attendant, and we think we perceive the one as well as the other. [emphasis mine] That such conclusions are formed even in infancy, no man can doubt; nor is it less certain that they are confounded with the natural and immediate perceptions of sense, and in all languages are called by the same name. We are therefore authorized by language to call them perception, and must often do so, or speak unintelligibly. But philosophy teaches us in this, as in many other instances, to distinguish things which the vulgar confound. I have therefore given the name of acquired perception to such conclusions, to distinguish them from what is naturally, originally, and immediately testified by our senses. (EIP 2.22, p. 247) In this telling passage, the equivocation of the earlier passages is gone. Reid all but says that in calling acquired perception perception, we are speaking with the vulgar. When we think with the learned, we acknowledge that acquired perception is not perception proper. 2. Are secondary qualities objects of acquired perception only? Reid is an upholder of the distinction between primary and secondary qualities, though he rejects some ways of drawing it. Pace Locke, it is not true that primary qualities resemble our sensations and secondaries do not; pace Berkeley s Hylas, it is not true that primary qualities are mind-independent and secondaries not. Both sets of qualities are mind-independent, and neither set resembles anything in our minds. But in Reid s view, there is a basis for drawing the distinction nonetheless: Our senses give us a direct and a distinct notion of the primary qualities, and inform us what they are in themselves: But of the secondary qualities, our senses give us only a relative and obscure notion. They inform us only, that they are qualities that produce in us a certain sensation. (EIP 2.17, p. 201) 21 Some commentators, including Lehrer and Smith (1985), Nichols (2007, p. 224), and Buras (2009, pp. 348ff.), attribute to Reid the thesis that all perception of secondary 21 For further discussion, see Van Cleve 2011.

20 20 qualities is acquired perception. One possible piece of evidence for their attribution is the following passage: Three of our senses, to wit, smell, taste, and hearing, originally give us only certain sensations, and a conviction that these sensations are occasioned by some some external object. We give a name to that quality of the object by which it is fitted to produce such a sensation, and connect that quality with the object, and with its other qualities. Thus we learn, that a certain sensation of smell is produced by a rose; and that quality in the rose, by which it is fitted to produce this sensation, we call the smell of the rose. Here it is evident that the sensation is original. The perception, that the rose has that quality, which we call its smell, is acquired. In like manner, we learn all those qualities in bodies, which we call their smell, their taste, their sound. (EIP 2.21, p. 235) Reid does indeed seem to say here that at least three classes of secondary qualities smells, tastes, and sounds are perceived only via acquired perception. But are we entitled to generalize this claim to all secondary qualities? I think not. The outstanding exception is color, which Reid certainly regards as a secondary quality (EIP 2.17, p. 201) and which he lists among the original objects of sight in the Inquiry: By [sight] we perceive originally the visible figure and colour of bodies only, and their visible place (IHM 6.20, p. 171). Confounding the issue, however, is a fact noted by Nichols (p. 224) Reid apparently omits color when he comes to list the original objects of sight in the Intellectual Powers: By [sight] we perceive visible objects to have extension in two dimensions, to have visible figure and magnitude, and a certain angular distance from one another. These I conceive are the original perceptions of sight. (EIP 2.21, p. 236) Does this signal any change of view on his part? Again, I think not. For one thing, it is quite possible that Reid s pronoun these in the sentence quoted is meant to refer back not just to the qualities mentioned in the previous

21 21 sentence, but to color, which was mentioned in the sentence just before that. 22 For another and more decisive thing, Reid clearly implies later on the same page that color is originally perceived. Speaking of a sphere that we now know (by acquired perception) to be three-dimensional, he says The eye originally could only perceive two dimensions, and a gradual variation of colour on the different sides of the object (EIP 2.21, p. 236, lines 26-28; see also lines on the same page.). So there is at least one secondary quality, color, that we perceive originally. Are there others? I would like to advance the following conjecture: if our senses enable us to localize a secondary quality (as they do in the case of colors, textures, and temperatures), we may have original perceptions regarding it. To see what lies behind the conjecture, look back at the quotation about the rose. By our original constitution, when we smell a rose, we know that some quality of some external object is causing our sensation we just do not know what object or where. It takes repeated experience and induction before we know that the quality (i.e., the cause of the fragrant sensations we are getting) resides in a rose. At that point, we have acquired perception: we can perceive by smell that a rose is in the room, even if we have not yet seen it. With color, we do not need to go through any such process to learn where the external cause of our sensation lies. That is because the same retinal excitations that give us sensations of color also induce us to believe that the cause of them lies in a certain direction. As Reid says, we always see any point of an object along the line passing from the retinal point stimulated by it back through the center of the eye and into ambient space. (See IHM 6.12, pp , for 22 Here is the sentence: By sight, we learn to distinguish objects by their colour, in the same manner as by their sound, taste, and smell. What makes the matter ambiguous is that sound, taste, and smell are also mentioned in the same breath.

22 22 Reid s formulation of this law of vision.) 23 Owing to this law, we have an innate ability to localize the distal causes of our color sensations. We have no such innate ability to localize the causes of our olfactory sensations. Are there any other secondary-quality sensations that should be grouped with color rather than smell in this regard? Yes: heat and cold. When we feel a surface to be warm or cold, we do not merely have a certain sensation and believe it to have an external quality somewhere as its cause; we know that the cause is right here, at the ends of our fingertips. The same is true of rough and smooth, if they count as secondary qualities. 24 Apart from the matter of localization, there is another way in which I think Lehrer, Smith, and Nichols may be too hasty in declaring secondary qualities to be objects of acquired perception only. What Reid gives as an example of acquired perception in regard to smell is the perception, that the rose has that quality, which we call its smell. That leaves open the possibility that we have an original perception to the effect that some quality exists that is causing our sensation or, more colloquially, that a certain scent is in the air. Perhaps (though it seems a stretch) one could even be said to have an objectual perception of the scent or quality itself, without knowing where it resides. In one or both of these latter two ways, there could be original perceptions of all secondary qualities, including those that are not innately localized. 23 For further discussion of this law, see Van Cleve 2003, especially section IX. 24 I am not sure whether they do. They supervene, of course, on primary qualities the hardness of an object and its figure at a fine level of resolution. But I do not think our senses give us any very determinate notion of the configuration responsible for the roughness or smoothness we feel, and that fact would make textures secondary qualities in Reid s scheme. One more example of a localized secondary quality may be mentioned: pain. In its primary sense, pain is a sensation, but there is also a sense in which we perceive pain as some unknown disorder in our toe causing the sensation (IHM 6.21, p. 175).

23 23 That is a welcome result for me, since it provides a way out of an inconsistency in Reid that would threaten to arise on my interpretation otherwise. According to Lehrer, Smith, and Nichols, (1) secondary qualities are objects of acquired perception only. According to me, (2) acquired perception is not perception. Yet according to Reid himself, (3) secondary qualities are objects of perception. 25 (1)-(3) form an inconsistent triad. If Reid does not embrace (1), the inconsistency does not arise. A deeper potential contradiction about secondary qualities is addressed in my final section. 3. Does acquired perception alter the content of our original perceptions? Originally, I perceive a sphere only as a variegated disk and a certain type of bird only as a slow flutter of gray and white. Subsequently, I have the acquired perception of the disk as a sphere and the moving patches of color as a mockingbird. Do my original perceptions survive as ingredients in the enriched perception? Or are they transformed into or superseded by something else? As a preliminary to determining Reid s answer to this question, let us consider Locke s answer, which he presents under the heading Ideas of Sensation often changed by the Judgment in of the Essay (1690): The Ideas we receive by sensation, are often in grown People alter d by the Judgment, without our taking notice of it. When we set before our Eyes a round Globe, of any uniform colour... tis certain, that the Idea thereby imprinted in our Mind, is of a flat Circle variously shadow d, with several degrees of Light and Brightness coming to our Eyes. But we having by use been accustomed to perceive, what kind of appearance convex Bodies are wont to make in us;... the Judgment presently, by an habitual custom, alters the Appearances into their Causes: So that from that, which truly is variety of shadow or colour, collecting the Figure, it makes it pass for a mark of Figure, and frames to its self the perception of a convex Figure, and an uniform Colour; when 25 EIP 2.17 is entitled Of the Objects of Perception; and first, of primary and secondary Qualities.

24 24 the Idea we receive from thence, is only a Plain variously colour d, as is evident in Painting. (p. 145) 26 That seems to be an unequivocal answer to our question sensation is altered by learning and judgment. But does Locke really mean it? I think not. In the first place, there can hardly be any question of a two-dimensional object somehow morphing into a threedimensional object. Dimension is a topological invariant; if the original cue does not survive, that must because it is replaced, not altered. In the second place, not even the talk of replacement accurately expresses Locke s view if such talk is taken literally. Scrolling ahead to Locke s more careful statement of what he is getting at, we read: [The judging of shape from shadow] is performed so constantly, and so quick, that we take that for the Perception of our Sensation, which is an Idea formed by our Judgment; so that one, viz. that of Sensation, serves only to excite the other, and is scarce taken notice of it self; as a Man who reads or hears with attention and understanding, takes little notice of the Characters, or Sounds, but of the Ideas, that are excited in him by them. (p. 146) And therefore tis not so strange, that our Mind should often change the Idea of its Sensation into that of its Judgment, and make one serve only to excite the other, without our taking notice of it. (p. 147) Although Locke uses the language of changing one more time, the surrounding commentary makes clear that it is not to be taken literally. The original cues are scarce taken notice of, but like the characters on a page, they are still there. Turning now to Reid, we find that his view of the matter is substantially the same as Locke s: It is experience that teaches me that the variation of colour is an effect of spherical convexity, and of the distribution of light and shade. So rapid is the progress of the thought, from the effect to the cause, that we attend only to the last, and can hardly be 26 Interestingly, Locke s discussion of this issue serves as the context in which he raises and answers Molyneux s question. Locke s answer is no the newly sighted person would not recognize what he saw as a globe or a cube because he would not yet have connected the two-dimensional objects he sees with the three-dimensional objects he knows by touch.

Perceiving Bodies Immediately: Thomas Reid s Insight

Perceiving Bodies Immediately: Thomas Reid s Insight 1 Perceiving Bodies Immediately: Thomas Reid s Insight Marina Folescu THIS IS THE PENULTIMATE DRAFT. PLEASE CITE THE PUBLISHED VERSION, FROM THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY 32(1) (2015): 19-36. 1 Introduction

More information

1/10. Berkeley on Abstraction

1/10. Berkeley on Abstraction 1/10 Berkeley on Abstraction In order to assess the account George Berkeley gives of abstraction we need to distinguish first, the types of abstraction he distinguishes, second, the ways distinct abstract

More information

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by Conclusion One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by saying that he seeks to articulate a plausible conception of what it is to be a finite rational subject

More information

In his essay "Of the Standard of Taste," Hume describes an apparent conflict between two

In his essay Of the Standard of Taste, Hume describes an apparent conflict between two Aesthetic Judgment and Perceptual Normativity HANNAH GINSBORG University of California, Berkeley, U.S.A. Abstract: I draw a connection between the question, raised by Hume and Kant, of how aesthetic judgments

More information

SYMPOSIUM: REID ON VISIBLE FIGURE REID ON THE PERCEPTION OF VISIBLE FIGURE. GIDEON YAFFE University of Southern California

SYMPOSIUM: REID ON VISIBLE FIGURE REID ON THE PERCEPTION OF VISIBLE FIGURE. GIDEON YAFFE University of Southern California SYMPOSIUM: REID ON VISIBLE FIGURE REID ON THE PERCEPTION OF VISIBLE FIGURE GIDEON YAFFE University of Southern California Thomas Reid s theory of sensory perception has been widely examined in recent years.

More information

Berkeley s idealism. Jeff Speaks phil October 30, 2018

Berkeley s idealism. Jeff Speaks phil October 30, 2018 Berkeley s idealism Jeff Speaks phil 30304 October 30, 2018 1 Idealism: the basic idea............................. 1 2 Berkeley s argument from perceptual relativity................ 1 2.1 The structure

More information

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment First Moment: The Judgement of Taste is Disinterested. The Aesthetic Aspect Kant begins the first moment 1 of the Analytic of Aesthetic Judgment with the claim that

More information

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception 1/6 The Anticipations of Perception The Anticipations of Perception treats the schematization of the category of quality and is the second of Kant s mathematical principles. As with the Axioms of Intuition,

More information

Early Modern Philosophy Locke and Berkeley. Lecture 2: Primary and Secondary Qualities

Early Modern Philosophy Locke and Berkeley. Lecture 2: Primary and Secondary Qualities Early Modern Philosophy Locke and Berkeley Lecture 2: Primary and Secondary Qualities The plan for today 1. Locke s thesis 2. Two common mistakes 3. Berkeley s objections 4. Subjectivism and dispositionalism

More information

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5 PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5 We officially started the class by discussing the fact/opinion distinction and reviewing some important philosophical tools. A critical look at the fact/opinion

More information

1/9. Descartes on Simple Ideas (2)

1/9. Descartes on Simple Ideas (2) 1/9 Descartes on Simple Ideas (2) Last time we began looking at Descartes Rules for the Direction of the Mind and found in the first set of rules a description of a key contrast between intuition and deduction.

More information

No Proposition can be said to be in the Mind, which it never yet knew, which it was never yet conscious of. (Essay I.II.5)

No Proposition can be said to be in the Mind, which it never yet knew, which it was never yet conscious of. (Essay I.II.5) Michael Lacewing Empiricism on the origin of ideas LOCKE ON TABULA RASA In An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, John Locke argues that all ideas are derived from sense experience. The mind is a tabula

More information

The red apple I am eating is sweet and juicy. LOCKE S EMPIRICAL THEORY OF COGNITION: THE THEORY OF IDEAS. Locke s way of ideas

The red apple I am eating is sweet and juicy. LOCKE S EMPIRICAL THEORY OF COGNITION: THE THEORY OF IDEAS. Locke s way of ideas LOCKE S EMPIRICAL THEORY OF COGNITION: THE THEORY OF IDEAS Let us then suppose the mind to be, as we say, white paper, void of all characters, without any ideas; how comes it to be furnished? Whence comes

More information

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima Caleb Cohoe Caleb Cohoe 2 I. Introduction What is it to truly understand something? What do the activities of understanding that we engage

More information

Exploring touch: A review of Matthew Fulkerson s The First Sense

Exploring touch: A review of Matthew Fulkerson s The First Sense Philosophical Psychology, 2015 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2015.1010197 REVIEW ESSAY Exploring touch: A review of Matthew Fulkerson s The First Sense Clare Batty The First Sense: A Philosophical

More information

From Rationalism to Empiricism

From Rationalism to Empiricism From Rationalism to Empiricism Rationalism vs. Empiricism Empiricism: All knowledge ultimately rests upon sense experience. All justification (our reasons for thinking our beliefs are true) ultimately

More information

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience Introduction Naïve realism regards the sensory experiences that subjects enjoy when perceiving (hereafter perceptual experiences) as being, in some

More information

John Locke. Ideas vs. Qualities Primary Qualities vs. Secondary Qualities

John Locke. Ideas vs. Qualities Primary Qualities vs. Secondary Qualities John Locke Ideas vs. Qualities Primary Qualities vs. Secondary Qualities Locke s Causal Theory of Perception: Idea: Whatsoever the mind perceives in itself is the immediate object of perception. Quality:

More information

Glossary alliteration allusion analogy anaphora anecdote annotation antecedent antimetabole antithesis aphorism appositive archaic diction argument

Glossary alliteration allusion analogy anaphora anecdote annotation antecedent antimetabole antithesis aphorism appositive archaic diction argument Glossary alliteration The repetition of the same sound or letter at the beginning of consecutive words or syllables. allusion An indirect reference, often to another text or an historic event. analogy

More information

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002) Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002) 168-172. Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance

More information

Locke, Judgment, and Figure: A Consistent Answer to the Molyneux Problem

Locke, Judgment, and Figure: A Consistent Answer to the Molyneux Problem Anthós Volume 7 Issue 1 Article 6 9-2015 Locke, Judgment, and Figure: A Consistent Answer to the Molyneux Problem Jamale Nagi Portland State University Let us know how access to this document benefits

More information

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)? Kant s Critique of Judgment 1 Critique of judgment Kant s Critique of Judgment (1790) generally regarded as foundational treatise in modern philosophical aesthetics no integration of aesthetic theory into

More information

An Essay towards a New Theory of Vision

An Essay towards a New Theory of Vision 3rd edition 1732 The Contents Section 1 Design 2 Distance of itself invisible 3 Remote distance perceived rather by experience than by sense 4 Near distance thought to be perceived by the angle of the

More information

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION Submitted by Jessica Murski Department of Philosophy In partial fulfillment of the requirements For the Degree of Master of Arts Colorado State University

More information

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic 1 Reply to Stalnaker Timothy Williamson In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic as Metaphysics between contingentism in modal metaphysics and the use of

More information

Image and Imagination

Image and Imagination * Budapest University of Technology and Economics Moholy-Nagy University of Art and Design, Budapest Abstract. Some argue that photographic and cinematic images are transparent ; we see objects through

More information

Table of Contents. Table of Contents. A Note to the Teacher... v. Introduction... 1

Table of Contents. Table of Contents. A Note to the Teacher... v. Introduction... 1 Table of Contents Table of Contents A Note to the Teacher... v Introduction... 1 Simple Apprehension (Term) Chapter 1: What Is Simple Apprehension?...9 Chapter 2: Comprehension and Extension...13 Chapter

More information

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography Dawn M. Phillips 1 Introduction In his 1983 article, Photography and Representation, Roger Scruton presented a powerful and provocative sceptical position. For most people interested in the aesthetics

More information

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1 Opus et Educatio Volume 4. Number 2. Hédi Virág CSORDÁS Gábor FORRAI Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1 Introduction Advertisements are a shared subject of inquiry for media theory and

More information

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes Testa, Italo email: italo.testa@unipr.it webpage: http://venus.unive.it/cortella/crtheory/bios/bio_it.html University of Parma, Dipartimento

More information

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Sidestepping the holes of holism Sidestepping the holes of holism Tadeusz Ciecierski taci@uw.edu.pl University of Warsaw Institute of Philosophy Piotr Wilkin pwl@mimuw.edu.pl University of Warsaw Institute of Philosophy / Institute of

More information

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content Book review of Schear, J. K. (ed.), Mind, Reason, and Being-in-the-World: The McDowell-Dreyfus Debate, Routledge, London-New York 2013, 350 pp. Corijn van Mazijk

More information

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception 1/8 The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception This week we are focusing only on the 3 rd of Kant s Paralogisms. Despite the fact that this Paralogism is probably the shortest of

More information

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave. Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave. The Republic is intended by Plato to answer two questions: (1) What IS justice? and (2) Is it better to

More information

Spectrum inversion as a challenge to intentionalism

Spectrum inversion as a challenge to intentionalism Spectrum inversion as a challenge to intentionalism phil 93515 Jeff Speaks April 18, 2007 1 Traditional cases of spectrum inversion Remember that minimal intentionalism is the claim that any two experiences

More information

Abstract Several accounts of the nature of fiction have been proposed that draw on speech act

Abstract Several accounts of the nature of fiction have been proposed that draw on speech act FICTION AS ACTION Sarah Hoffman University Of Saskatchewan Saskatoon, SK S7N 5A5 Canada Abstract Several accounts of the nature of fiction have been proposed that draw on speech act theory. I argue that

More information

Constant Conjunction and the Problem of Induction

Constant Conjunction and the Problem of Induction Constant Conjunction and the Problem of Induction You may recall that Hume s general empiricist epistemological project is to explain how we obtain all of our knowledge based fundamentally on the idea

More information

Locke and Berkeley. Lecture 2: Primary and Secondary Qualities

Locke and Berkeley. Lecture 2: Primary and Secondary Qualities Locke and Berkeley Dr Rob Watt Lecture 2: Primary and Secondary Qualities 1. Locke s thesis Two groups of properties Group 1: Solidity, Extension, Figure, Motion, or Rest, and Number (2.8.9 N 135). Also

More information

Early Modern Philosophy Locke and Berkeley. Lecture 6: Berkeley s Idealism II

Early Modern Philosophy Locke and Berkeley. Lecture 6: Berkeley s Idealism II Early Modern Philosophy Locke and Berkeley Lecture 6: Berkeley s Idealism II The plan for today 1. Veridical perception and hallucination 2. The sense perception argument 3. The pleasure/pain argument

More information

Selection from Jonathan Dancy, Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology, Blackwell, 1985, pp THEORIES OF PERCEPTION

Selection from Jonathan Dancy, Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology, Blackwell, 1985, pp THEORIES OF PERCEPTION Selection from Jonathan Dancy, Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology, Blackwell, 1985, pp. 144-174. 10.2 THEORIES OF PERCEPTION There are three main families of theories of perception: direct realism,

More information

KANTIAN CONCEPTUALISM

KANTIAN CONCEPTUALISM KANTIAN CONCEPTUALISM forthcoming in: G. Abel/J. Conant (eds.), Berlin Studies in Knowledge Research, vol. : Rethinking Epistemology, Berlin/New York: de Gruyter. Abstract: In the recent debate between

More information

SpringBoard Academic Vocabulary for Grades 10-11

SpringBoard Academic Vocabulary for Grades 10-11 CCSS.ELA-LITERACY.CCRA.L.6 Acquire and use accurately a range of general academic and domain-specific words and phrases sufficient for reading, writing, speaking, and listening at the college and career

More information

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason THE A PRIORI GROUNDS OF THE POSSIBILITY OF EXPERIENCE THAT a concept, although itself neither contained in the concept of possible experience nor consisting of elements

More information

McDowell, Demonstrative Concepts, and Nonconceptual Representational Content Wayne Wright

McDowell, Demonstrative Concepts, and Nonconceptual Representational Content Wayne Wright Forthcoming in Disputatio McDowell, Demonstrative Concepts, and Nonconceptual Representational Content Wayne Wright In giving an account of the content of perceptual experience, several authors, including

More information

Kant and the Problem of Experience

Kant and the Problem of Experience PHILOSOPHICAL TOPICS VOL. 34, NOS. 1 & 2, SPRING AND FALL 2006 Kant and the Problem of Experience Hannah Ginsborg University of California, Berkeley As most of its readers are aware, the Critique of Pure

More information

It is from this perspective that Aristotelian science studies the distinctive aspects of the various inhabitants of the observable,

It is from this perspective that Aristotelian science studies the distinctive aspects of the various inhabitants of the observable, ARISTOTELIAN COLORS AS CAUSES Festschrift for Julius Moravcsik, edd., D.Follesdall, J. Woods, College Publications (London:2008), pages 235-242 For Aristotle the study of living things, speaking quite

More information

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

1/8. Axioms of Intuition 1/8 Axioms of Intuition Kant now turns to working out in detail the schematization of the categories, demonstrating how this supplies us with the principles that govern experience. Prior to doing so he

More information

1/10. The A-Deduction

1/10. The A-Deduction 1/10 The A-Deduction Kant s transcendental deduction of the pure concepts of understanding exists in two different versions and this week we are going to be looking at the first edition version. After

More information

SIGNS, SYMBOLS, AND MEANING DANIEL K. STEWMT*

SIGNS, SYMBOLS, AND MEANING DANIEL K. STEWMT* SIGNS, SYMBOLS, AND MEANING DANIEL K. STEWMT* In research on communication one often encounters an attempted distinction between sign and symbol at the expense of critical attention to meaning. Somehow,

More information

The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong

The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong identity theory of truth and the realm of reference 297 The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong WILLIAM FISH AND CYNTHIA MACDONALD In On McDowell s identity conception

More information

Aristotle s Metaphysics

Aristotle s Metaphysics Aristotle s Metaphysics Book Γ: the study of being qua being First Philosophy Aristotle often describes the topic of the Metaphysics as first philosophy. In Book IV.1 (Γ.1) he calls it a science that studies

More information

A Theory of Secondary Qualities

A Theory of Secondary Qualities Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXIII, No. 3, November 2006 A Theory of Secondary Qualities ROBERT PASNAU University of Colorado at Boulder The secondary qualities are those qualities of

More information

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 7, no. 2, 2011 REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY Karin de Boer Angelica Nuzzo, Ideal Embodiment: Kant

More information

Université Libre de Bruxelles

Université Libre de Bruxelles Université Libre de Bruxelles Institut de Recherches Interdisciplinaires et de Développements en Intelligence Artificielle On the Role of Correspondence in the Similarity Approach Carlotta Piscopo and

More information

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver Truth and Tropes by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver Trope theory has been focused on the metaphysics of a theory of tropes that eliminates the need for appeal to universals or properties. This has naturally

More information

Philosophy Pathways Issue th December 2016

Philosophy Pathways Issue th December 2016 Epistemological position of G.W.F. Hegel Sujit Debnath In this paper I shall discuss Epistemological position of G.W.F Hegel (1770-1831). In his epistemology Hegel discusses four sources of knowledge.

More information

BOOK REVIEW. William W. Davis

BOOK REVIEW. William W. Davis BOOK REVIEW William W. Davis Douglas R. Hofstadter: Codel, Escher, Bach: an Eternal Golden Braid. Pp. xxl + 777. New York: Basic Books, Inc., Publishers, 1979. Hardcover, $10.50. This is, principle something

More information

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS) KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS) Both the natural and the social sciences posit taxonomies or classification schemes that divide their objects of study into various categories. Many philosophers hold

More information

Moral Judgment and Emotions

Moral Judgment and Emotions The Journal of Value Inquiry (2004) 38: 375 381 DOI: 10.1007/s10790-005-1636-z C Springer 2005 Moral Judgment and Emotions KYLE SWAN Department of Philosophy, National University of Singapore, 3 Arts Link,

More information

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki 1 The Polish Peasant in Europe and America W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki Now there are two fundamental practical problems which have constituted the center of attention of reflective social practice

More information

SECTION EIGHT THROUGH TWELVE

SECTION EIGHT THROUGH TWELVE SECTION EIGHT THROUGH TWELVE Rhetorical devices -You should have four to five sections on the most important rhetorical devices, with examples of each (three to four quotations for each device and a clear

More information

Carlo Martini 2009_07_23. Summary of: Robert Sugden - Credible Worlds: the Status of Theoretical Models in Economics 1.

Carlo Martini 2009_07_23. Summary of: Robert Sugden - Credible Worlds: the Status of Theoretical Models in Economics 1. CarloMartini 2009_07_23 1 Summary of: Robert Sugden - Credible Worlds: the Status of Theoretical Models in Economics 1. Robert Sugden s Credible Worlds: the Status of Theoretical Models in Economics is

More information

The Phenomenological Negation of the Causal Closure of the Physical

The Phenomenological Negation of the Causal Closure of the Physical The Phenomenological Negation of the Causal Closure of the Physical John Thornton The Institute for Integrated and Intelligent Systems, Griffith University, Australia j.thornton@griffith.edu.au 1 Preliminaries

More information

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality Spring Magazine on English Literature, (E-ISSN: 2455-4715), Vol. II, No. 1, 2016. Edited by Dr. KBS Krishna URL of the Issue: www.springmagazine.net/v2n1 URL of the article: http://springmagazine.net/v2/n1/02_kant_subjective_universality.pdf

More information

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS The problem of universals may be safely called one of the perennial problems of Western philosophy. As it is widely known, it was also a major theme in medieval

More information

Hume's Theory of Mental Representation David Landy Hume Studies Volume 38, Number 1 (2012), 23-54. Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of

More information

Chapter 2 Christopher Alexander s Nature of Order

Chapter 2 Christopher Alexander s Nature of Order Chapter 2 Christopher Alexander s Nature of Order Christopher Alexander is an oft-referenced icon for the concept of patterns in programming languages and design [1 3]. Alexander himself set forth his

More information

WITHOUT QUALIFICATION: AN INQUIRY INTO THE SECUNDUM QUID

WITHOUT QUALIFICATION: AN INQUIRY INTO THE SECUNDUM QUID STUDIES IN LOGIC, GRAMMAR AND RHETORIC 36(49) 2014 DOI: 10.2478/slgr-2014-0008 David Botting Universidade Nova de Lisboa WITHOUT QUALIFICATION: AN INQUIRY INTO THE SECUNDUM QUID Abstract. In this paper

More information

Claim: refers to an arguable proposition or a conclusion whose merit must be established.

Claim: refers to an arguable proposition or a conclusion whose merit must be established. Argument mapping: refers to the ways of graphically depicting an argument s main claim, sub claims, and support. In effect, it highlights the structure of the argument. Arrangement: the canon that deals

More information

1/9. The B-Deduction

1/9. The B-Deduction 1/9 The B-Deduction The transcendental deduction is one of the sections of the Critique that is considerably altered between the two editions of the work. In a work published between the two editions of

More information

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL CONTINGENCY AND TIME Gal YEHEZKEL ABSTRACT: In this article I offer an explanation of the need for contingent propositions in language. I argue that contingent propositions are required if and only if

More information

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example Paul Schollmeier I Let us assume with the classical philosophers that we have a faculty of theoretical intuition, through which we intuit theoretical principles,

More information

Lecture 10 Popper s Propensity Theory; Hájek s Metatheory

Lecture 10 Popper s Propensity Theory; Hájek s Metatheory Lecture 10 Popper s Propensity Theory; Hájek s Metatheory Patrick Maher Philosophy 517 Spring 2007 Popper s propensity theory Introduction One of the principal challenges confronting any objectivist theory

More information

TERMS & CONCEPTS. The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the English Language A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING

TERMS & CONCEPTS. The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the English Language A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING Language shapes the way we think, and determines what we can think about. BENJAMIN LEE WHORF, American Linguist A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING TERMS & CONCEPTS The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the

More information

Kant s Negative Answer to Molyneux s Question. Richard David Creek

Kant s Negative Answer to Molyneux s Question. Richard David Creek Kant s Negative Answer to Molyneux s Question Richard David Creek Thesis submitted to the faculty of the Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for

More information

The Pure Concepts of the Understanding and Synthetic A Priori Cognition: the Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason and a Solution

The Pure Concepts of the Understanding and Synthetic A Priori Cognition: the Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason and a Solution The Pure Concepts of the Understanding and Synthetic A Priori Cognition: the Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason and a Solution Kazuhiko Yamamoto, Kyushu University, Japan The European

More information

The Rhetorical Modes Schemes and Patterns for Papers

The Rhetorical Modes Schemes and Patterns for Papers K. Hope Rhetorical Modes 1 The Rhetorical Modes Schemes and Patterns for Papers Argument In this class, the basic mode of writing is argument, meaning that your papers will rehearse or play out one idea

More information

Chudnoff on the Awareness of Abstract Objects 1

Chudnoff on the Awareness of Abstract Objects 1 Florida Philosophical Society Volume XVI, Issue 1, Winter 2016 105 Chudnoff on the Awareness of Abstract Objects 1 D. Gene Witmer, University of Florida Elijah Chudnoff s Intuition is a rich and systematic

More information

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala 1 Forms and Causality in the Phaedo Michael Wiitala Abstract: In Socrates account of his second sailing in the Phaedo, he relates how his search for the causes (αἰτίαι) of why things come to be, pass away,

More information

On Recanati s Mental Files

On Recanati s Mental Files November 18, 2013. Penultimate version. Final version forthcoming in Inquiry. On Recanati s Mental Files Dilip Ninan dilip.ninan@tufts.edu 1 Frege (1892) introduced us to the notion of a sense or a mode

More information

Twentieth Excursus: Reference Magnets and the Grounds of Intentionality

Twentieth Excursus: Reference Magnets and the Grounds of Intentionality Twentieth Excursus: Reference Magnets and the Grounds of Intentionality David J. Chalmers A recently popular idea is that especially natural properties and entites serve as reference magnets. Expressions

More information

Rhetorical Analysis. AP Seminar

Rhetorical Analysis. AP Seminar Rhetorical Analysis AP Seminar SOAPS The first step to effectively analyzing nonfiction is to know certain key background details which will give you the proper context for the analysis. An acronym to

More information

Types of perceptual content

Types of perceptual content Types of perceptual content Jeff Speaks January 29, 2006 1 Objects vs. contents of perception......................... 1 2 Three views of content in the philosophy of language............... 2 3 Perceptual

More information

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective DAVID T. LARSON University of Kansas Kant suggests that his contribution to philosophy is analogous to the contribution of Copernicus to astronomy each involves

More information

Nicomachean Ethics. p. 1. Aristotle. Translated by W. D. Ross. Book II. Moral Virtue (excerpts)

Nicomachean Ethics. p. 1. Aristotle. Translated by W. D. Ross. Book II. Moral Virtue (excerpts) Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle Translated by W. D. Ross Book II. Moral Virtue (excerpts) 1. Virtue, then, being of two kinds, intellectual and moral, intellectual virtue in the main owes both its birth and

More information

Against Metaphysical Disjunctivism

Against Metaphysical Disjunctivism 32 Against Metaphysical Disjunctivism PASCAL LUDWIG AND EMILE THALABARD We first met the core ideas of disjunctivism through the teaching and writing of Pascal Engel 1. At the time, the view seemed to

More information

Self-Consciousness and Knowledge

Self-Consciousness and Knowledge Self-Consciousness and Knowledge Kant argues that the unity of self-consciousness, that is, the unity in virtue of which representations so unified are mine, is the same as the objective unity of apperception,

More information

GUIDELINES FOR EXAMINATION OF EUROPEAN UNION TRADE MARKS EUROPEAN UNION INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY OFFICE (EUIPO) PART B EXAMINATION SECTION 4

GUIDELINES FOR EXAMINATION OF EUROPEAN UNION TRADE MARKS EUROPEAN UNION INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY OFFICE (EUIPO) PART B EXAMINATION SECTION 4 GUIDELINES FOR EXAMINATION OF EUROPEAN UNION TRADE MARKS EUROPEAN UNION INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY OFFICE (EUIPO) PART B EXAMINATION SECTION 4 ABSOLUTE GROUNDS FOR REFUSAL CHAPTER 2 EUTM definition (Article

More information

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas Rachel Singpurwalla It is well known that Plato sketches, through his similes of the sun, line and cave, an account of the good

More information

MIRA COSTA HIGH SCHOOL English Department Writing Manual TABLE OF CONTENTS. 1. Prewriting Introductions 4. 3.

MIRA COSTA HIGH SCHOOL English Department Writing Manual TABLE OF CONTENTS. 1. Prewriting Introductions 4. 3. MIRA COSTA HIGH SCHOOL English Department Writing Manual TABLE OF CONTENTS 1. Prewriting 2 2. Introductions 4 3. Body Paragraphs 7 4. Conclusion 10 5. Terms and Style Guide 12 1 1. Prewriting Reading and

More information

Perceptions and Hallucinations

Perceptions and Hallucinations Perceptions and Hallucinations The Matching View as a Plausible Theory of Perception Romi Rellum, 3673979 BA Thesis Philosophy Utrecht University April 19, 2013 Supervisor: Dr. Menno Lievers Table of contents

More information

Logic and argumentation techniques. Dialogue types, rules

Logic and argumentation techniques. Dialogue types, rules Logic and argumentation techniques Dialogue types, rules Types of debates Argumentation These theory is concerned wit the standpoints the arguers make and what linguistic devices they employ to defend

More information

Thomas Reid's Notion of Exertion

Thomas Reid's Notion of Exertion Thomas Reid's Notion of Exertion Hoffman, Paul David, 1952- Journal of the History of Philosophy, Volume 44, Number 3, July 2006, pp. 431-447 (Article) Published by The Johns Hopkins University Press DOI:

More information

A New Approach to the Paradox of Fiction Pete Faulconbridge

A New Approach to the Paradox of Fiction Pete Faulconbridge Stance Volume 4 2011 A New Approach to the Paradox of Fiction Pete Faulconbridge ABSTRACT: It seems that an intuitive characterization of our emotional engagement with fiction contains a paradox, which

More information

Formalizing Irony with Doxastic Logic

Formalizing Irony with Doxastic Logic Formalizing Irony with Doxastic Logic WANG ZHONGQUAN National University of Singapore April 22, 2015 1 Introduction Verbal irony is a fundamental rhetoric device in human communication. It is often characterized

More information

Quine s Two Dogmas of Empiricism. By Spencer Livingstone

Quine s Two Dogmas of Empiricism. By Spencer Livingstone Quine s Two Dogmas of Empiricism By Spencer Livingstone An Empiricist? Quine is actually an empiricist Goal of the paper not to refute empiricism through refuting its dogmas Rather, to cleanse empiricism

More information

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art Session 5 September 16 th, 2015 Malevich, Kasimir. (1916) Suprematist Composition. Gaut on Identifying Art Last class, we considered Noël Carroll s narrative approach to identifying

More information

My thesis is that not only the written symbols and spoken sounds are different, but also the affections of the soul (as Aristotle called them).

My thesis is that not only the written symbols and spoken sounds are different, but also the affections of the soul (as Aristotle called them). Topic number 1- Aristotle We can grasp the exterior world through our sensitivity. Even the simplest action provides countelss stimuli which affect our senses. In order to be able to understand what happens

More information

What s Really Disgusting

What s Really Disgusting What s Really Disgusting Mary Elizabeth Carman 0404113A Supervised by Dr Lucy Allais, Department of Philosophy University of the Witwatersrand February 2009 A research report submitted to the Faculty of

More information

Humanities 116: Philosophical Perspectives on the Humanities

Humanities 116: Philosophical Perspectives on the Humanities Humanities 116: Philosophical Perspectives on the Humanities 1 From Porphyry s Isagoge, on the five predicables Porphyry s Isagoge, as you can see from the first sentence, is meant as an introduction to

More information