Chapter 3 Sluicing. 3.1 Introduction to wh-fragments. Chapter 3 Sluicing in An Automodular View of Ellipsis

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Chapter 3 Sluicing. 3.1 Introduction to wh-fragments. Chapter 3 Sluicing in An Automodular View of Ellipsis"

Transcription

1 1 Chapter 3 Sluicing 3.1 Introduction to wh-fragments (1a, b) below are examples of sluicing, which was first discussed in Ross (1969). In these examples, a wh-phrase (XP[WH[Q]]) is interpreted as a full wh-question (CP[WH[Q]]). See AMEG 6.1 for the details on wh-questions. We will henceforth call sluiced wh-phrases such as those in (1a, b) wh-fragments in view of striking similarities between wh-phrases in sluicing and fragments such as (1c, d). Fragments will be discussed in Chapter 5. (1) a. John is drinking something, but I don t know what. (wh-fragment) b. John is drinking something. What, I wonder. (wh-fragment) c. John is drinking something. Beer, I guess. (fragment) d. A: What is John drinking? B: Beer, I guess. (answer fragment) e. Mary said John was drinking something, but I don t remember what. (wh-fragment) In (1a), the wh-fragment what is interpreted in two ways, as either (but I don t know) what he is drinking (what we call direct interpretation) or (but I don t know) what it is, where it refers to something in the first conjunct (what we call short-circuited interpretation). This is exactly the same as how the fragment Beer in (1c, d) is interpreted: either as He is drinking beer (direct interpretation) or It is beer (short-circuited interpretation). Direct interpretation of a wh-fragment is obtained from the preceding utterance, which we will call the antecedent of the wh-fragment, by replacing the relevant phrase in it by the wh-fragment in question. For example, in (1a), the direct interpretation is obtained by replacing something in the preceding utterance by what. On the other hand, short-circuited interpretation of a wh-fragment is to interpret it as if it is in a wh-question consisting of wh-phrase + pronoun (it/they) + be, in which the pronoun refers to the most salient NP (topic) in the prior context. In (1e), the wh-fragment can be interpreted in three ways: (but I don t remember) what Mary said John was drinking (direct interpretation), (but I don t remember) what it was (short-circuited interpretation), and (but I don t remember) what he was drinking (localized interpretation). The third way of wh-fragment interpretation, what we call localized interpretation, is to interpret a wh-fragment relative to the local domain of its antecedent (e.g., within the innermost clause of the antecedent or within its own conjunct ignoring other conjuncts). Note that Mary said John was drinking something entails that I (= speaker) remember John was drinking something if the speaker believes what Mary said about John. The localized interpretation obtains based on this entailment. It is not true that the three interpretations are always available to every instance of wh-fragment. In (2a), the direct interpretation is impossible while in (2b, c), it is semantically odd. (2) a. Bill wondered how many papers Sandy had read, but he didn t care which ones. (Chung et al. 1995:257) direct interpretation: *(but he didn t care which ones) [he wondered (how many papers) she had read] localized interpretation: (but he didn t care which ones) [she had read] short-circuited interpretation: (but he didn t care which ones) [they were]

2 2 (they refers to a certain number of papers Sandy had read in the presupposition of how many papers Sandy had read) b. Joan said she talked to the students. Fred couldn t figure out which ones. (Chung et al. 1995:266) direct interpretation: #(Fred couldn t figure out which ones) [she said she talked to] localized interpretation: (Fred couldn t figure out which ones) [she talked to] short-circuited interpretation: (Fred couldn t figure out which ones) [they were] c. He announced he would marry the woman he loved most. None of his relatives could figure out who. (ibid.) direct interpretation: #(None of his relatives could figure out who) [he announced he would marry] localized interpretation: (None of his relatives could figure out who) [he would marry] short-circuited interpretation: (None of his relatives could figure out who) [she was] The examples in (3) are extreme cases in which all the three interpretations are not available. Chung et al. (1995:253) observed that a universally quantified NP (e.g., everybody in (3a) and each of the performers in (3b)) cannot serve as part of the antecedent of wh-fragment. (3) Chung et al. 1995:253 (30) a. *She said she had spoken to everybody, but he wasn t sure who. direct interpretation: #(but he wasn t sure who) [she said she had spoken to] localized interpretation: #(but he wasn t sure who) [she had spoken to] short-circuited interpretation: *(but he wasn t sure who) [he was] (he is an unbound variable, not c-commanded by the quantified NP) b. *Each of the performers came in. We were sitting so far back that we couldn t see who. direct interpretation: #(we couldn t see who) [came in] short-circuited interpretation: *(we couldn t see who) [he was] (he is an unbound variable, not c-commanded by the QNP) In the direct and localized interpretations of (3a, b), who presupposes the existentially quantified propositions (she said) she had spoken to somebody in (3a) and some performers came in in (3b). These existential presuppositions conflict with the universally quantified NP in each antecedent. Interpreting a wh-fragment is very similar to interpreting fragments, which we will discuss in Chapter 5. To interpret an answer fragment such as (1dB), we need to find a propositional function P(x) such that the answer fragment a is interpreted as P(a). The propositional function P(x) is provided by the immediately preceding wh-question. In the same way, in order to interpret a wh-fragment, we need to find a propositional function P(x) with which the wh-fragment is interpreted as [ QPx [ Q WH] x = ] [ PROP P(x)] (in F/A terms). For example, the wh-fragment in (1a, b) is interpreted as For which thing x, [ P(x) John is drinking x] (direct interpretation) or For which thing x, [ P(x) it is x] (short-circuited interpretation), and the propositional function of the former (direct)

3 3 interpretation is provided by the prior utterance John is drinking something. Because of the similarities between (answer) fragments and wh-fragments, we would like to explore the explanation of sluicing by treating wh-fragments essentially as the same as fragments and relying as much as possible on what is needed to interpret fragments. In addition to interrogative wh-fragments, exclamative wh-fragments are also observed. They are interpreted with the understood null subject/topic and be (i.e., short-circuited interpretation). (4) Huddleston and Pullum 2002:921 a. What nonsense! b. What a strange thing for him to say! c. How fantastic! d. How incredibly unlikely! 3.2 The syntax of wh-fragments The internal syntax of wh-fragment is the same as that of an interrogative wh-phrase XP[WH[Q]] (AMEG (3) and 6.1.7). As for its external syntax, Ross (1969), Merchant (2001:40ff.), and Culicover and Jackendoff (2005: ) showed that a wh-fragment behaves syntactically as a wh-interrogative clause (CP[WH[Q]]). The first piece of evidence is about subject-verb agreement (1a). Although the subject wh-phrase is in the plural, the agreeing verb is in the singular, just like a subject wh-clause. The second piece of evidence is about the possibility of extraposition of a wh-fragment (1b). The wh-phrase is extraposed, again just like a subject wh-clause. (1) Culicover and Jackendoff 2005: 268 (52) We were supposed to do some problems for tomorrow, a. but [which problems] {isn t *aren t} clear. (agreement) cf. but [which problems we were supposed to do for tomorrow] {isn t *aren t} clear. (direct interpretation) cf. but [which problems they were] {isn t *aren t} clear (short-circuited interpretation) b. but it isn t clear [which problems]. (extraposition) cf. but it isn t clear [which problems we were supposed to do for tomorrow] (direct interpretation) cf. but it isn t clear [which problems they were] (short-circuited interpretation) The third piece of evidence is about its distribution with respect to a verb-particle construction. In (2a) below, the wh-phrase what, which is apparently an NP, cannot occur between the verb and the particle, as is expected of NPs. (2) a. He was doing something illegal, but I never {found out [what] *found [what] out}. (Culicover and Jackendoff 2005: 269 (54a)) cf. I never {found out [what he was doing] *found [what he was doing] out} (direct interpretation) cf. I never {found out [what it was] *found [what it was] out} (short-circuited interpretation) b. He was doing something illegal, and I discovered {yesterday immediately} what. cf. He was doing something illegal, and I discovered yesterday {*the thing *that *it}.

4 4 The fourth piece of evidence is based on the distribution of NPs: that in English, a light NP object must immediately follow a transitive verb, and that an adverb cannot intervene between a transitive verb and its light NP object, as in I discovered {the thing yesterday *yesterday the thing}. In (2b), although the light NP object cannot occur after yesterday, the interrogative what can, just like a wh-clause. This shows again that the wh-fragment what functions not as an NP but as a clause. The fifth way to show that a wh-fragment is a CP[WH[Q]] is to use a verb that can take a CP[WH[Q]] complement but cannot take an NP object. The best example of such a verb is wonder. (3) He was doing something illegal, but I wonder [what]. cf. but I wonder [{what he was doing what it was}] The sixth way is coordination. A wh-fragment can be coordinated with a full wh-question. (4) a. There are guidelines in the company dress code for [ CP[WH[Q]] when women can use perfume] and [ CP[WH[Q]] how much]. b. Languages differ widely on [ and [ CP[WH[Q]] CP[WH[Q]] what sort of material can appear in the COMP field] under what circumstances]. (Merchant 2001:61) c. Mary invited someone, but I don t know [ CP[WH[Q]] who] or [ CP[WH[Q]] when she invited them]. The seventh piece of evidence is case-marking (Ross 1969, Merchant 2001:42-43). In (5), the German verb schmeicheln ( flatter ) takes a dative NP as its complement and wissen ( know ) either an accusative NP or a clause. (5) Er will jemandem schmeicheln, aber sie wissen nicht, {wem *wen}. In (5), the dative wem is grammatical but the accusative wen is not, which shows that the wh-fragment is interpreted as the dative object of schmeicheln as in Sie wissen nicht, wem er schmeicheln will. Because of these pieces of evidence, we conclude that a wh-fragment (syntactically XP[WH[Q]]) is dominated by a CP[WH[Q]] node in syntax. 3.3 Interpreting wh-fragments The modular representations of a wh-fragment are given in (1) below. As was shown in the previous section, the wh-fragment XP[WH[Q]] is dominated by a CP[WH[Q]] in syntax. It corresponds to a QP x headed by the quantifier [ Q WH] in F/A (AMEG (1)) and a certain ROLE in RS if the wh-fragment is interpreted as an argument. Note that the speech act (SA) superstructure with the illocutionary force (IF) #inquire# (cf. AMEG (1), 7.1 (6b)) is only present when the wh-fragment is not embedded.

5 5 (1) modular representations for sluicing (wh-phrase may or may not be embedded) syntax F/A RS CP[WH[Q]] PROP SA XP[WH[Q]] (S?) QP x (PROP?) IF [AG, SO] [PT, GO] TH inquire SP AD (EV?) ROLE In the syntax of (1), the interrogative clause (CP[WH[Q]]) only consists of a single daughter, a wh-fragment (XP[WH[Q]]). Therefore, there is no possibility for a cliticized element or complementizer agreement to appear on a wh-fragment (Merchant 2001:66-69). This explains Merchant s Sluicing-COMP generalization (2001:62 (71)), which says that in sluicing, no non-operator may appear in COMP. In order to properly interpret a wh-fragment, we need to find a propositional function with which the wh-fragment is interpreted, namely, in (1) above, the S that goes with the wh-fragment, the PROP that goes with the QP x, and the EV in which the wh-fragment carries a ROLE. We claim that this is achieved by the extragrammatical process of inference, in the same way as the interpretation of VP ellipsis (2.2) and fragments (5.2 (4)), that is, the same three steps of extragrammatical inference that is involved in interpreting VP ellipsis and fragments are also involved in interpreting wh-fragments. Extragrammatical inference treats incoming information successively and accumulatively. Note that step (iii) is pure grammatical computation. (2) extragrammatical inference for fragment interpretation (i) Find from linguistic or nonlinguistic context the information that can serve as a potential antecedent. (ii) Infer the contextually appropriate S based on the wh-phrase and the potential antecedent found in step (i). (iii) Based on the syntactic structures of the inferred S obtained in step (ii) and hence the CP[WH[Q]], compute the corresponding structures in the other modules F/A and RS. In (2), inferring the contextually appropriate S in syntax that goes with the wh-fragment in question (step ii) must precede the computation of the corresponding F/A and RS (step iii). For example, to properly interpret C s wh-fragment in (3) below, B s inferred S Jane pulled his/someone s leg too must be determined first. Without this inferred S, the idiom interpretation of whose cannot be recovered. (3) (cf. 5.4 (1)) A: Mary pulled someone s leg. B: Yeah. Jane did too. (ambiguous) Yeah. Jane pulled his leg too. or Yeah. Jane pulled someone s leg too.

6 C: Tell me whose? (ambiguous) Tell me whose leg you SG/PL pulled Wh-fragments and inference Just as is the case with fragments in general, it is true that the propositional function that goes with a wh-fragment is not always available from the immediately preceding utterance, but rather it must be inferred from pieces of information spread across the preceding discourse. (1) is such an example (cf. 5.2 (1)). (1) The participants A, B, and C share the knowledge that John used to have a drinking problem. A: Have you heard about a friend of yours? B: (About) which friend of mine? Which friend of mine are you asking about? A: (About) John. I m asking you about John. He has started again. He has started drinking too much again B: Which alcohol this time? Which alcohol has he stared drinking too much of this time? Whisky? Has he started drinking too much of whisky this time? A: No, beer. No, he has started drinking too much of beer this time B: When? When did he start drinking too much of beer? A: Two weeks ago. He started drinking too much of beer two weeks ago. C: {I didn t know that That s true That s false}. C s that refers to the message John started drinking too much of beer two weeks ago. Note that the verb drink in the message does not appear in the discourse and only exists in the shared knowledge that John used to drink too much. In each utterance in (1), its intended message is shown next to the symbol. (2) is another example, in which the intended interpretation of Guess who at the end is Guess who has not both read the textbook and finished the assignment. (The other possibility is that Guess who is interpreted as Guess who he is, in which he refers to someone who hasn t (short-circuited interpretation).) The inferences taking place as dialogue (2) progresses are shown next to the symbol. (2) A: Have you read the textbook for today? B: Yes, I have. [VP ellipsis] I have read the textbook for today. And I have finished the assignment too. How about you? Have you read the textbook and finished the assignment? C: Of course, I have. [VP ellipsis] Of course, I have read the textbook and finished the assignment. I m sure everyone has. [VP ellipsis] I m sure everyone has read the textbook and finished the assignment. D: That s not true.

7 7 I know someone who hasn t. [VP ellipsis] I know someone who hasn t both read the textbook and finished the assignment. Guess who. [wh-fragment] Guess who hasn t both read the textbook and finished the assignment. (3) is another example in which the interpretation of a wh-fragment cannot be recovered from the immediately preceding utterance. (3) A: I m sure John isn t seeing any girl. B: But I hear Tom is. [VP ellipsis] A: Yeah. B: But do you know where? [wh-fragment] A: In his apartment, I guess. [answer fragment] C: Tell me which girl. [wh-fragment] The intended interpretation of (3C) is Tell me which girl Tom is seeing in his apartment. Note that which girl in C asks about a girl in the antecedent of the VP ellipsis in B s Tom is, namely, Tom is seeing a girl (cf. missing antecedent phenomenon (2.5)). (4) is an example similar to (3). (4) A: John isn t seeing any girl but Tom is. [VP ellipsis] B: Do you know how often? [wh-fragment] A: I suppose twice a day. [answer fragment] C: Do you know where? [wh-fragment] The intended interpretation of C is Do you know where Tom is seeing {the girl her *a girl} twice a day? In (5) below, just like 5.2 (3), real world knowledge is needed to infer what the bartender meant, which is Which beer would you like this time? or something like it. The discourse-initial, non-embedded wh-fragment in (5) receives its interpretation directly from nonlinguistic context, just like the examples in (6). (5) [A regular customer enjoys various kinds of beer at the bar every night. He holds out his empty glass to the bartender without saying anything. The bartender says to the customer:] Which one? (6) Chung et al. 1995:264 (cited from Ginzburg 1992) a. [said by a taxi driver] Where to, lady? b. [said by a distraught homeowner staring at the ashes of his house] Why? In examples (5) and (6), there is no prior utterance in the discourse that provides the information needed to infer an

8 8 intended message. The relevant information comes only from nonlinguistic context. Therefore, this shows again that we need to assume the extragrammatical process of inference, which is at work in constructing an inferred message. What inference needs to do is to arrive at a propositional function that goes with the wh-fragment, namely, to arrive at the S?, the PROP? and the EV? in 3.3 (1) from the relevant linguistic and nonlinguistic discourse context. 3.5 Need for short-circuited interpretation Short-circuited interpretation of wh-fragments was defined and illustrated in 3.1. In this section, we will present various pieces of evidence that we need to posit this type of interpretation. First, there are cases of fragments whose interpretation requires short-circuited interpretation. For example, in (1a, b), short-circuited interpretation of fragments is required. (For more discussion on short-circuited interpretation, see ) (1) a. A: What did John buy? B: A book? direct interpretation: #Did John buy a book? short-circuited interpretation: Was it a book? (it refers to something in the presupposition of the wh-question Pat bought something ) b. A: John bought something. B: A book? direct interpretation: #Did John buy a book? short-circuited interpretation: Was it a book? (it refers to something) c. A: John bought a book written by a famous scientist. B: By whom? direct interpretation: *By whom did John buy a book written? localized interpretation: By whom was it written? (it refers to a book written by a famous scientist) In (1a, b), B s fragment must be interpreted as short-circuited interpretation. The direct interpretation in (1a, b) is pragmatically odd. Incidentally, (1c) shows the need to posit localized interpretation of wh-fragments. Here, the direct interpretation is impossible. Here is a German example. (2) receptionist: Ach, Moment. Sie sind Herr Aoki? Hier wurde etwas für Sie abgegeben. Aoki: Für mich? [fragment] Von wem? [wh-fragment] receptionist: Von Frau Professor Schütz. [fragment] Eine Geige, glaube ich. [fragment] (from Ota, Tatsuya and Marco Raindl Das Geheimnis der Geige. NHK. p.154)

9 9 The first fragment Für mich? and the following wh-fragment Von wem? are interpreted not as Hier wurde etwas für mich abgegeben? or Von wem wurde etwas für mich hier abgegeben? (direct interpretation) but simply as Ist das für mich? and Von wem ist das? (short-circuited interpretation). The last two fragments in (2) Von Frau Professor Schütz and Eine Geige, glaube ich are interpreted not as Hier wurde für Sie eine Geige von Frau Professor Schütz abgegeben or Hier wurde für Sie eine Geige abgegeben, glaube ich (direct interpretation) but simply as Das ist von Frau Professor Schütz and Das ist eine Geige, glaube ich (short-circuited interpretation). These fragments are of the most frequent type, in which a fragment carries new information (focus) about an understood topic that is phonologically null. This is short-circuited interpretation. In (2), the understood topic is etwas ( something that was handed in for Aoki ). Second, Chung et al. (1995:273) pointed out that some PPs that do not allow preposition stranding in wh-question (e.g., (3a, b)) allow it in sluicing as in (3c, d). This was first observed by Rosen (1976). (3) Chung et al. 1995:273 a. *What circumstances will we use force under? cf. Under what circumstances will we use force? b. *What sense is this theory right in? cf. In what sense is this theory right? c. We are willing to use force under certain circumstances, but we will not say in advance which ones. short-circuited interpretation: (but we will not say in advance which ones) [they are] (they refers to certain circumstances) d. This theory is surely right in some sense; it s just not clear which exactly. short-circuited interpretation: (it s just not clear exactly which) [it is] (it refers to some sense) The direct interpretation of (3c, d) would have involved preposition stranding. The short-circuited interpretation is available which does not depend on preposition stranding. Third, in wh-question such as (4a), the variable of the Wh-QP who, whose F/A is [ QPx [ Q WH] [ PROP x = PERSON]] (AMEG (2)), ranges over its own domain, namely, [ PROP x = PERSON]. (4) inheritance of content (Chung et al. 1995: ) a. Joan said she talked to some students, but I don t know who she talked to. b. Joan said she talked to some students, but I don t know who. localized interpretation: (but I don t know who) [she talked to] short-circuited interpretation: (but I don t know who) [they were] (they refers to some students) c. A: Joan talked to some students. B: Who? short-circuited interpretation: (Who) [were they]? (they refers to some students)

10 10 Chung et al. (1995: ) observed that in wh-fragments such as (4b), the variable ranges over (i.e., the answer space of the variable is) the intersection of its own domain and the domain defined by the expression in the antecedent that corresponds to the wh-fragment (their inner antecedent (p.241)), some students in (4b). They said (p.260) that restrictions on the range of the variable are determined jointly by the content of the inner antecedent (some students in (4b)) and that of the wh-fragment (who in (4b)). This is due to the fact that in the case of wh-fragments such as (4b), as opposed to full wh-questions, the speaker s intention in uttering a wh-fragment is to ask about the inner antecedent, as in (4c). Therefore, the answer space for the wh-fragment in question is jointly determined by both the wh-fragment and the inner antecedent. This inheritance of content is captured in our approach by the short-circuited interpretation. For example, in (5a, b), the answer space for the wh-fragment is the set of male guests (at the party). (5) a. A: Mary talked to some men at the party. B: Which guests? short-circuited interpretation: Which guests were they? (they refers to some men in A) b. I know Mary talked to some men at the party, but I don t know which guests. c. I know Mary talked to some men at the party, but I don t know which guests she talked to. Chung et al. (1995:261) observed that this inheritance of content is particular to sluicing, and full wh-questions do not show similar effects. In (5c), the wh-phrase which guests is not necessarily intended to identify the preceding NP some men. On the other hand, this intention is clear with the wh-fragment in (5a, b). Fourth, we need short-circuited interpretation when the adjective in question is only used attributively such as drunken. (6) I saw a drunken man, but I don t remember how {*drunken drunk}. short-circuited interpretation: (but I don t remember how {*drunken drunk}) [he was] (he refers to a drunken man in the antecedent) Fifth, short-circuited interpretation is required when the meaning of the adjective in question is different in attributive and predicative uses. (The symbol # indicates semantic/pragmatic anomaly.) (7) a. *I saw a hard worker, but I don t remember how hard. short-circuited interpretation: #(but I don t remember how hard) [he was] (he refers to a hard worker in the antecedent) b. I saw a hard worker, but I don t remember how hard a worker. direct interpretation: (but I don t remember how hard a worker) [I saw] short-circuited interpretation: (but I don t remember how hard a worker) [he was]

11 11 (8) a. *I met a big fan of Andy Griffith, but I don t know how big. short-circuited interpretation: #(but I don t know how big) [he was] (he refers to a big fan of Andy Griffith in the antecedent) b. I met a big fan of Andy Griffith, but I don t know how big a fan. direct interpretation: (but I don t know how big a fan) [I met] short-circuited interpretation: (but I don t know how big a fan) [she was] To account of the unacceptability of (7a) and (8a), short-circuited interpretation is needed. Sixth, when a wh-fragment takes its own complement, we need short-circuited interpretation. (9) a.?i saw many proud parents in the graduation ceremony, and I know how proud of their children. short-circuited interpretation: (and I know how proud of their children) [they were] b.?i saw a proud winner in the ceremony, and I know how proud of himself. short-circuited interpretation: (and I know how proud of himself) [he was] Seventh, when the adjective in question modifies a plural count noun or a mass noun. (10) a. She writes thorough reports, and wait till you see how thorough! (Merchant 2001:167) short-circuited interpretation: (and wait till you see how thorough) [they are]! (they refers to thorough reports in the antecedent) cf. *How thorough reports does she write? (Merchant 2001:165) b. He bought expensive jewelry, but he wouldn t say how expensive. (Merchant 2001:167) short-circuited interpretation: (but he wouldn t say how expensive) [it was] (it refers to expensive jewelry in the antecedent) cf. *How expensive jewelry did he buy? (Merchant 2001:165) We conclude that because of these pieces of evidence, short-circuited interpretation is independently motivated. 3.6 Ambiguity in wh-fragment interpretation Just like fragments in general (5.4 (9)), wh-fragments can be ambiguous, when there are multiple potential antecedents available in the prior discourse. (1) a. Mary said she has five cats, but I don t know how many dogs. (ambiguous) direct interpretation: but I don t know how many dogs Mary said she has (step i) antecedent = Mary said she has five cats (step ii) inferred S = (but I don t know how many dogs) [Mary said she has] localized interpretation: but I don t know how many dogs she has (step i) antecedent = she has five cats

12 12 (step ii) inferred S = (but I don t know how many dogs) [she has] b. The newspaper has reported that they are about to appoint someone, but I don t remember who. (Chung et al. 1995:256) direct interpretation: (but I don t remember who) [the newspaper has reported that they are about to appoint] localized interpretation: (but I don t remember who) [they are about to appoint] short-circuited interpretation: (but I don t remember who) [he is] Note that localized interpretation such as the one in (1a) is obtained based on an entailment from the antecedent. For example, the first part of (1a) Mary said she has five cats entails that I know she has five cats, if the speaker believes what Mary said. The localized interpretation but I don t know how many dogs she has obtains based on this entailment. This entailment is real, which is shown by the fact that Mary said she has five cats, but I don t know how many cats she has is felt to be contradictory. Here is another example of ambiguous wh-fragment. (2) A: Mary said she is learning a new foreign language. (cf. 5.4 (9)) B: Which language? direct interpretation: (Which language) [did she say she is learning]? localized interpretation: (Which language) [is she learning]? In the direct interpretation of (2B), B asks A what Mary said about her new foreign language. On the other hand, in the localized interpretation, B asks A what A knows about Mary s new foreign language. Note that A s Mary said she is learning a new foreign language entails A s knowledge that I know she is learning a new foreign language. In (3), the first conjunct is ambiguous between the scope relations of MOST > A and A > MOST. (3) Chung et al. 1995:256 a. Most columnists claim that a senior White House official has been briefing them, and the newspaper today reveals which one. direct interpretation: (and the newspaper today reveals which one) [most columnists claim has been briefing them] localized interpretation: (and the newspaper today reveals which one) [has been briefing them] short-circuited interpretation: (and the newspaper today reveals which one) [he is] (he refers to a senior White House official based on its wide scope) b. Most columnists claim that a senior White House official has been briefing them, but none of them will reveal which one. (under the scope relation MOST > A) direct interpretation: (but none of them will reveal which one) [they claim has been briefing them]

13 13 localized interpretation: (but none of them will reveal which one) [has been briefing them] (= Chung et al. 1995:257 (44)) short-circuited interpretation: *(but none of them will reveal which one) [he is] The most likely interpretation of (3a) is the one in which the first and second conjuncts are interpreted as A > MOST and WHICH > MOST, respectively, namely, there is a certain senior White House official who most columnists claim has been briefing them, and the newspaper reveals which one it is that most columnists claim has been briefing them. This interpretation is compatible with any of the direct, localized, and short-circuited interpretations. On the other hand, in (3b), the first conjunct is interpreted as either A > MOST or MOST > A. When it is interpreted as A > MOST, the interpretation of the second conjunct is compatible of any of the direct, localized, and shot-circuited interpretations, just like (3a). However, when it is interpreted as MOST > A, namely, different unidentified White House officials are claimed to have been briefing different columnists, the interpretation of the second conjunct is compatible only with the direct and localized interpretations. The short-circuited interpretation is not possible, because he is nothing but an unbound variable of the narrower scope a senior White House official. 3.7 Multiple wh-fragments Although English is not a multiple wh-fronting language (AMEG (1)), it allows multiple wh-fragments when the antecedent of the multiple wh-fragments has an appropriate pair-list reading (Merchant 2001:112). Just as multiple wh-questions (AMEG (3), (4)), the first wh-fragment has scope over the second wh-fragment and serves as the generator of pair-list reading. As shown in (1e), multiple fragments are also possible. (1) a. Everyone brought something (different) to the potluck, but I couldn t tell you {(?)who what *what who}. (Merchant 2001:112, 113) direct interpretation: (but I couldn t tell you) who brought what to the potluck b. Everybody said he d bring something different to the potluck. But I can t remember who what. (Merchant 2001:113) direct interpretation: (But I can t remember) who said he d bring what to the potluck localized interpretation: (But I can t remember) who would bring what to the potluck c. In French, we have noticed that some intransitive V permit Extraposition of Indefinite, while others permit Impersonal Passive. Which which? (Merchant 2001:112, attributed to Paul Postal) direct interpretation: Which (intransitive verbs) permit which? d. Someone said that once, but I don t remember who, what, when, or where. (from the web) e. A: Everyone brought their favorite food to the potluck, didn t they? B: Yes. John sandwiches, Tom sushi, and Mary an apple pie. We simply assume the syntactic structure for these multiple wh-fragments in which a single CP[WH[Q]] node directly dominates multiple XP[WH[Q]] nodes and the scope relations are indicated by left-to-right order.

14 Aggressively non-d-linked the hell An aggressively non-d-linked wh-phrase (e.g., who the hell) generally cannot occur in sluicing (Merchant 2001:121), which is shown in (1a, b, c).. (1) a. I wish I knew who (*the hell)! (Merchant 2001:122) b. A: Someone bought a car yesterday. B: Who (*the hell)? cf. Who the hell bought it? c. Mary bought something yesterday, but I don t know what (*the hell). direct interpretation: (but I don t know what) [she bought] short-circuited interpretation: (but I don t know what) [it was] (it refers to something) There seem to be two reasons why the aggressively non-d linked wh-phrases who/what the hell are unacceptable in (1). First, the interpretation of wh-fragment is entirely dependent on the antecedent, and in this respect, wh-fragments are D-linked and the aggressively non-d-linked the hell is not appropriate to them. This is similar to the fact that the hell is not appropriate to a wh-phrase with D-linked which. (2) (Pesetsky 1987, cited in Lasnik and Saito 1992:173) a. [ NP[WH[Q]] What the hell book] did you read that in? b. *[ NP[WH[Q]] Which the hell book] did you read that in? Secondly, an aggressively non-d-linked wh-phrase must c-command a gap (XP[G]) (i.e., its extraction site). This explains why an in-situ wh-phrase cannot occur with the aggressively non-d-linked the hell (AMEG (4)). (3) a. Who read what? b. *Who read what the hell? (Lasnik and Saito 1992:173) c. [ NP[WH[Q]] Who the hell] [ S[PAST] NP[G] read what]? However, Merchant (2001) observed that the hell is acceptable if it is adjoined to a wh-phrase that undergoes sluiced wh-phrase inversion with preposition swiping. (4) a. He was talking, but God knows who (the hell) to. (Merchant 2001:65 note 14) b. A: I m getting married. B: Who the hell to? A: Who do you think? Rita. (from the web) c. I m battling that on top of sleep deprivation. I m almost on my knees now. What is this? Am I meant to surrender? If so, who the hell to? And what then? (from the web) d. CP[WH[Q]

15 15 NP[WH[Q]] PP[to] NP[WH[Q]] NP? P[to] NP[G] who the hell to We assume the syntactic structure (4d), in which the wh-phrase who the hell c-commands the corresponding NP gap. 3.9 Access to lexical entries The extragrammatical process of inference involves accessing the lexical entries of the words uttered and at the same time accessing the lexical entries of the closely related words. The following example, just like the similar example of fragment in 5.3 (1), leads us to assume that when the lexical entry for intransitive verb drink is accessed, the lexical entry for transitive drink is also activated and becomes available for the construction of the inferred message but I don t know what Harriet is drinking again. (1) Culicover and Jackendoff 2005: 266 (48b) Harriet is drinking again, but I don t know what. [sprouting sluicing] Here is another example. When the lexical entry for intransitive flirt in (2A) is accessed (syntax: V in [ ]), the related entry with PP[with] complement is also activated (syntax: V in [, PP[with]]). Therefore, in (2B), the presence of the preposition with is obligatory (cf. 5.3 (4a)) and no other preposition is possible. (2) Culicover and Jackendoff 2005: 271 (58b) A: Harriet s been flirting again. B: Who *(with)? Note that if B had simply said Who? without with, it would have been interpreted as Who is Harriet?, which is not B s intention. However, there seems to be a restriction between different lexical entries of the same verb on the way which lexical entry can activate which one. As shown in (3a, b), matching sluicing (i.e., the type of sluicing in which the wh-fragment can be matched with an overt phrase in the antecedent (Culicover and Jackendoff 2005:257)) presents no problem, because there is an antecedent in the preceding context about which the wh-phrase asks and also because the same lexical entry of the same verb ([V, NP, NP] in (3a) and [V, NP, PP[to]] in (3b)) is used both in the clause that contains the antecedent of the wh-fragment and in the inferred message of the wh-fragment. In contrast, sprouting sluicing (i.e., the type of sluicing in which the wh-fragment has no matching constituent in the antecedent but functions as a suppressed/unassociable role (i.e., an implicit argument) or an adjunct in the antecedent (Culicover and Jackendoff 2005:257)) is restricted, as shown in (3c, d, e).

16 16 (3) Chung at al. 1995:248, Merchant 2001:33, and Culicover and Jackendoff 2005: 258, note 17 a. They served someone fish, but I don t know who. [matching] direct interpretation:??(but I don t know who) [they served fish] short-circuited interpretation: (but I don t know who) [he was] b. They served something to the students, but I don t know what. [matching] c. She served the soup, but I don t know to whom. [sprouting] d. She served the students, but I don t know what. [sprouting] e. *She served the soup, but I don t know who. [sprouting] short-circuited interpretation: *(but I don t know who) [he was] Note in passing that the restriction on the extraction of the first object in a double-object construction (e.g.,??who did she serve the meal? (Merchant 2001:34 note 16)) is absent in sluicing as in (3a). This is because the interpretation of the wh-fragment in (3a) is obtained not from its direct interpretation but from its short-circuited interpretation, which does not involve the wh-movement of the first object of the ditransitive verb. This is supported by the fact that the short-circuited interpretation of wh-fragment in (3e) is impossible. (4) four partial lexical entries for serve a. syntax: V in [, NP] RS: TYPE serve in [ [AG, SO; SERVER] [PT, GO; DINER] <[TH; FOOD]>] b. syntax: V in [, NP, NP] RS: TYPE serve in [ [AG, SO; SERVER] [PT, GO; DINER] [TH; FOOD]] c. syntax: V in [, NP] RS: TYPE serve in [ [AG, SO; SEVER] [PT, TH; FOOD] <[GO; DINER]>] d. syntax: V in [, NP, PP[to]] RS: TYPE serve in [ [AG, SO; SERVER] [PT, TH; FOOD] [GO; DINER]] When an addressee hears the first conjunct of (3c), she accesses the lexical entry (4c), which in turn activates (4d), which is used to infer the intended message of the second conjunct ( but I don t know to whom she served the soup ). Lexical entry (4d) is a natural extension of (4c) in the sense that the suppressed/unassociable role in (4c), namely, <[GO; DINER]>, becomes overt/associable in (4d) and the outrank relations of the roles ([AG, SO] > [PT, TH] > GO) are kept intact between the two lexical entries (cf. Chung et al. 1995:248, 262). The situation about (3d) is quite similar. Again, lexical entry (4b), which is used for the second conjunct of (3d), is a natural extension of (4a), which is used for the first conjunct of (3d), in exactly the same sense. Generally, when a verb has two lexical entries L 1 and L 2, we define the binary relation, L 2 is a natural extension of L 1, iff (i) the RS of L 1 and that of L 2 have the same set of roles (and, therefore, the same outrank relations), and (ii) the lowest role in outranking is suppressed/unassociable in the RS of L 1 but overt/associable in the RS of L 2. For example, if a verb has two lexical entries L 1 and L 2 with three roles R 1, R 2, and R 3, and the

17 17 outranking relations R 1 > R 2 > R 3 between them and their RSs are: the RS of L1 [ EV TYPE R 1 R 2 <R 3 > ] and the RS of L2 [ EV TYPE R 1 R 2 R 3 ], then the lexical entry L2 is a natural extension of the lexical entry of L 1. Note that of the four lexical entries of the verb serve in (4), (4b) and (4d) are natural extensions of (4a) and (4c), respectively. If a verb has two lexical entries L1 and L 2, and L 2 is a natural extension of L 1, access to L 1 can activate L 2. For example, access to (4a) and (4c) can activate (4b) and (4d), respectively. The intended message of but I don t know who in (3e) is??but I don t know who she served the soup, which needs lexical entry (4b). However, in the first conjunct of (3e), lexical entry (4c) is accessed, but access to (4c) in the first conjunct of (3e) cannot activate (4b) for the second conjunct, because (4b) is not a natural extension of (4c). This explains the ungrammaticality of (3e). The verb read offers another example of natural extension of lexical entry and how it is activated. This verb has at least two lexical entries (5a, b) and (5b) is a natural extension of (5a). Therefore, access to (5a) in the first conjunct of (6a) can activate (5b) for the second conjunct, which makes sprouting sluicing possible in (6a). On the other hand, sprouting sluicing is impossible with the verb bathe, which is shown in (6b). (5) a. syntax: V in [ ] RS: TYPE read in [ [AG; PERSON] <[PT, TH; INFORMATION]>] b. syntax: V in [, NP] RS: TYPE read in [ [AG; PERSON] [PT, TH; INFORMATION]] (6) a. She was reading, but I couldn t make out what. [sprouting] (Chung et al. 1995:249) b. *She was bathing, but I couldn t make out who. [sprouting] (ibid.) b. *They were marching, but I couldn t make out who. c. Someone was bathing, but I couldn t make out who. [matching] c. Some prisoners were marching, but I couldn t make out who. d. She was bathing someone, but I couldn t make out who. [matching] d. The guard was marching some prisoners, but I couldn t make out who. Although bathe has both intransitive and transitive usage, the transitive bathe (8b) is not a natural extension of the intransitive bathe (8a). The former is a causativization of the latter, just like the intransitive and transitive march, as in The prisoners marched and The guard marched the prisoners. Compare bathe with wash, whose intransitive usage is a (semantic) reflexive use of the corresponding transitive verb (7). Also, John bathed Mary entails Mary bathed but John washed Mary does not entail Mary washed. (7) a. John bathed. / John bathed him. /??John bathed himself. b. John washed. / John washed him. / John washed himself.

18 18 In (6b), the intended message of the second conjunct is I couldn t make out who she was bathing with the transitive bathe. When an addressee hears the first conjunct of (6b), she accesses the lexical entry of intransitive bathe (8a), which does not activate the transitive bath (8b), because the latter is not a natural extension of the former. Note that there is no unassociable role (i.e., implicit argument) in (8a) that becomes associable in the corresponding transitive (8b) and that successful sprouting depends on. (8) partial lexical entries for bathe a. intransitive bathe syntax: V in [ ] RS: [ TYPE bathe ] in [ [AG, TH]] b. transitive bathe syntax: V in [, NP ] RS: [ TYPE cause 2 -bathe ] in [ VA [ TYPE cause 2 ] AG [ PT [ SITU [ TYPE bathe ] [AG, TH]]]] cf. cause is a two-place predicate that takes an agent (as causer) and a caused 2 situation and denotes a volitional action (VA). See AMEG 4.7 (3). The same restriction on activation of lexical entries (i.e., that access to a lexical entry can only activate the lexical entry of the same verb that is a natural extensions of the former) applies to fragments. This shows a strong similarity between sluicing interpretation and fragment interpretation. (9) restriction on lexical entry activation in fragments a. A: They served John fish. B: No, Mary. [matching; cf. (3a)] b. A: They served fish to the students. B: No, chicken. [matching; cf. (3b)] c. A: She served the soup. B: Yes, to John. [sprouting; cf. (3c)] d. A: She served the students. B: Yes, fish. [sprouting; cf. (3d)] e. A: She served the soup. B: *Yes, John. [sprouting; cf. (3e)] f. A: She was bathing. B: *Yes, her baby. [sprouting; cf. (6b)] Chung et al. (1995: ) observed that implicit arguments can serve as the antecedent for a wh-fragment.

19 19 According to Fillmore (1986), some verbs such as eat and read allow novel implicit arguments whereas others such as apply and contribute allow familiar implicit arguments. In (10a), the implicit argument (PP[for]) of apply is familiar to the speaker, and, therefore, his asking about it by what conflicts with this presupposition. On the other hand, in (10b), the implicit argument of eat is novel to the speaker, and, therefore, he can ask about it by what. (10) a. *They applied yesterday. I wonder what for. (Chung et al. 1995:267) a. *He has already contributed $100. I wonder to what organization. (ibid.) b. They were eating. I wonder what. (ibid.) c.?they claimed to us that they had applied, but they refused to say for which jobs. (Chung et al. 1995:268) d.?he revealed that he had already contributed $100, bu t he would not reveal to what organization. (ibid.) In (10c, d), the verbs with a familiar implicit argument is embedded in a context that neutralizes the familiar/novel distinction of presupposition, the sentences become more acceptable Island-insensitivity Chung et al (1995:273), Merchant (2001:87), and Culicover and Jackendoff (2005:258, note 17 and ) showed that wh-phrases in sluicing are not sensitive to strong islands by giving examples that would violate island constraints if a purely syntactic account such as wh-movement followed by deletion were resorted to. Ross already observed the weakening of island violation effects in sluicing in his seminal paper (1969: (71)-(73)). (See 5.5 (1)-(3) and 5.8 (7), where fragments will be shown to be island-insensitive.) These examples show that purely syntactic accounts do not fare well in accounting for sluicing. (1) a. Bob found a plumber who fixed the sink, but I m not sure with what. [CNPC] (Culicover and Jackendoff 2005:258) direct interpretation: *(but I m not sure with what) [Bob found a plumber who fixed the sink] localized interpretation: (but I m not sure with what) [he fixed it] b. That Tony is eating right now is conceivable, but I m having a hard time imagining what. [Sentential subject] (Culicover and Jackendoff 2005:258) direct interpretation: *(but I m having a hard time imagining what) [that Tony is eating right now is conceivable] localized interpretation: (but I m having a hard time imagining what) [he is eating right now] c. A: Harriet drinks scotch that comes from a very special part of Scotland. B: Where? [CNPC] (Culicover and Jackendoff 2005:267) direct interpretation: *(Where) [does Harriet drink scotch that comes from]? localized interpretation: (Where) [does it come from]? d. A: John met a guy who speaks a very unusual language.

20 20 B: Which language? [CNPC] (Culicover and Jackendoff 2005:267) direct interpretation: *(Which language) did John meet a guy who speaks? localized interpretation: (Which language) does he speak? Although the direct interpretation of each of the wh-fragments in (1) is not available due to an island violation, each localized interpretation is available, which hides the island violations of wh-fragments. Chung et al. (1995: ) claimed that sluicing involving sprouting are subject to the standard array of island effects, and gave the following examples. (2) Chung et al. (1995:279) (102) a. Wh-island *Sandy was trying to work out which students would speak, but she refused to say {who to to who(m)}. b. Wh-island *Agnes wondered how John could eat, but it s not clear what. c. Subject Condition *That Tom will win is likely, but it s not clear which race. d. CNPC *Bob found a plumber to fix the sink, but it s not clear what with. e. CNPC *Tony sent Mo a picture that he painted, but it s not clear with what. (2d, e) are in sharp contrast with (1a), in which there is no CNPC effect, although it involves sprouting sluicing. Also, (2c) is in sharp contrast with (1b), in which there is no Subject Condition effect. We tentatively conclude, following Culicover and Jackendoff (2005), that wh-fragment is not sensitive to islands, regardless of whether it involves matching sluicing or sprouting sluicing. Although wh-fragment is island-insensitive, VP ellipsis is island-sensitive (Chung et al. 1995:275, Merchant 2001:4-5, 114, Merchant 2004:705). (3a) is an example of CNPC violation. (3b) is a VP ellipsis example of CNPC violation. (3c) is a wh-fragment example of CNPC violation. (3) a. *They want to hire someone who speaks a Balkan language, but I don t remember which they want to hire someone who speaks. (Merchant 2001:5) b. *They want to hire someone who speaks a Balkan language, but I don t remember which they do. (Merchant 2001:5) c. They want to hire someone who speaks a Balkan language, but I don t remember which. (Merchant 2001:4) In our AMG approach to unbounded dependency, island facts are captured by the dominance path conditions

21 21 (AMEG (1)), which formulate licit wh-movement paths by means of dominance relations, in which the top of the dominance path is CP[WH[Q]] (i.e., an interrogative wh-cp) and the bottom of the path is XP[G] (i.e., a gap with the syntactic category XP). The simplified version of dominance path conditions are repeated here as (3). As for the full version of the dominance path conditions, see AMEG (1). (4) the dominance path conditions on XP[WH[Q]] (simplified version) a. non-subject gap: CP[WH[Q]] {S, VP, CP[that]}* VP {NP, N, PP}* XP[G] b. embedded subject gap: CP[WH[Q]] {S, VP, CP[that]}* VP S NP[G] c. matrix subject gap: CP[WH[Q]] S[FIN] NP[G] In (4a, b), {S, VP, CP[that]}* is to be interpreted as the set of dominance paths consisting of any number (including zero) of S, VP, CP[that] in any order. (The correct order of S, VP, CP[that] in each instance of wh-movement is determined separately by the relevant PS rules and lexical entries.) For example, the dominance path condition (4b) says that a licit wh-movement dominance path must be a member of the set of all the dominance paths that start with the top node CP[WH[Q]] and end with the string VP S NP[G] and in between there can be any number (including zero) of S, VP, CP[that] in any order. The dominance path conditions (3a, b) account for many of the well-known islands. For example, (5a) is an example in which the Complex NP Constraint (CNPC) (the relative clause subcase) is violated. The CNPC says in derivational terms that derivational steps in which material is extracted from the S of a complex NP are excluded (McCawley 1998:523). (5) a. Complex NP Constraint *What topics does Mary like to read books that are about? b. CP[WH[Q]] S[INV] S[BSE] VP[BSE] VP[to] VP[BSE] NP N CP[that] S[FIN] VP[FIN] PP[about] NP[G] The dominance path involved in (5a) is given in (5b). Every time wh-movement moves a wh-phrase out of a complex NP, we have as part of its dominance path the sequence NP N CP S. For instance, if a wh-phrase was extracted out of a relative clause (e.g., the man who [ S XP[G] ]), its dominance path would contain the sequence NP N CP[WH[R]] S, because the constituent structure of the relevant part is [ NP DET [ N N [ CP[WH[R]] NP[WH[R]] [ S XP[G] ]]]]. However, (3a, b) do not allow any dominance path containing the sequence NP N CP S. A wh-fragment, which is syntactically [ CP[WH[Q]] XP[WH[Q]]] (3.1 (7)), does not trigger the dominance path conditions, because the dominance path conditions are encoded in the lexical entry of moved wh-phrase whose external syntax is [ CP[WH[Q]] XP[WH[Q]], S] (AMEG (1)), which is not satisfied by a wh-fragment. On the

! Japanese: a wh-in-situ language. ! Taroo-ga [ DP. ! Taroo-ga [ CP. ! Wh-words don t move. Islands don t matter.

! Japanese: a wh-in-situ language. ! Taroo-ga [ DP. ! Taroo-ga [ CP. ! Wh-words don t move. Islands don t matter. CAS LX 522 Syntax I Episode 12b. Phases, relative clauses, and LF (ch. 10) Islands and phases, summary from last time! Sentences are chunked into phases as they are built up. Phases are CP and DP.! A feature

More information

CAS LX 522 Syntax I. Islands. Wh-islands. Phases. Complex Noun Phrase islands. Adjunct islands

CAS LX 522 Syntax I. Islands. Wh-islands. Phases. Complex Noun Phrase islands. Adjunct islands CAS LX 522 Syntax I Week 14b. Phases, relative clauses, and LF (ch. 10) Islands There seem to be certain structures out of which you cannot move a wh-word. These are islands. CNP (complex noun phrase)

More information

Lecture 7. Scope and Anaphora. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 1

Lecture 7. Scope and Anaphora. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 1 Lecture 7 Scope and Anaphora October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 1 Today We will discuss ways to express scope ambiguities related to Quantifiers Negation Wh-words (questions words like who, which, what, ) October

More information

The Syntax and Semantics of Traces Danny Fox, MIT. How are traces interpreted given the copy theory of movement?

The Syntax and Semantics of Traces Danny Fox, MIT. How are traces interpreted given the copy theory of movement? 1 University of Connecticut, November 2001 The Syntax and Semantics of Traces Danny Fox, MIT 1. The Problem How are traces interpreted given the copy theory of movement? (1) Mary likes every boy. -QR--->

More information

Possible Ramifications for Superiority

Possible Ramifications for Superiority 1 Possible Ramifications for Superiority 1. Superiority up to semantic equivalence (Golan 1993) (1) Who knows what who bought? (Lasnik and Saito 1992) Good but only when em Attract Closest bedded who receives

More information

17. Semantics in L1A

17. Semantics in L1A Spring 2012, March 26 Quantifiers Isomorphism Quantifiers (someone, nobody, everyone, two guys) express a kind of generalization. They say something about the members of a set. To see if it is true, you

More information

Comparatives, Indices, and Scope

Comparatives, Indices, and Scope To appear in: Proceedings of FLSM VI (1995) Comparatives, Indices, and Scope Christopher Kennedy University of California, Santa Cruz 13 July, 1995 kennedy@ling.ucsc.edu 1 Russell's ambiguity Our knowledge

More information

The structure of this ppt. Sentence types An overview Yes/no questions WH-questions

The structure of this ppt. Sentence types An overview Yes/no questions WH-questions The structure of this ppt Sentence types 1.1.-1.3. An overview 2.1.-2.2. Yes/no questions 3.1.-3.2. WH-questions 4.1.-4.5. Directives 2 1. Sentence types: an overview 3 1.1. Sentence types: an overview

More information

1 The structure of this exercise

1 The structure of this exercise CAS LX 522 Syntax I Fall 2013 Extra credit: Trees are easy to draw Due by Thu Dec 19 1 The structure of this exercise Sentences like (1) have had a long history of being pains in the neck. Let s see why,

More information

The structure of this ppt

The structure of this ppt The structure of this ppt 1.1.-1.10.. Functional issues in the English sentence 2.1.-2.9... Grammatical functions and related relations 2.1.-2.2. A VP-internal alternation 2.3. The four dimensions 2.4.

More information

Recap: Roots, inflection, and head-movement

Recap: Roots, inflection, and head-movement Syntax II Seminar 4 Recap: Roots, inflection, and head-movement Dr. James Griffiths james.griffiths@uni-konstanz.de he English verbal domain - Modified from the Carnie (2013) excerpt: (1) he soup could

More information

IBPS Pronouns Notes for Bank Exam

IBPS Pronouns Notes for Bank Exam IBPS Pronouns Notes for Bank Exam A pronoun (???????) is defined as a word or phrase that may be substituted for a noun or noun phrase, which once replaced, is known as the pronoun s antecedent.a pronoun

More information

Two Styles of Construction Grammar Do Ditransitives

Two Styles of Construction Grammar Do Ditransitives Two Styles of Construction Grammar Do Ditransitives Cognitive Construction Grammar CCG) and Sign Based Construction Grammar SBCG) Paul Kay LSA Summer Institute, Stanford 7/2-3/07 The SBCG project team:

More information

An HPSG Account of Depictive Secondary Predicates and Free Adjuncts: A Problem for the Adjuncts-as-Complements Approach

An HPSG Account of Depictive Secondary Predicates and Free Adjuncts: A Problem for the Adjuncts-as-Complements Approach An HPSG Account of Depictive Secondary Predicates and Free Adjuncts: A Problem for the Adjuncts-as-Complements Approach Hyeyeon Lee (Seoul National University) Lee, Hyeyeon. 2014. An HPSG Account of Depictive

More information

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press,

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014. Pp. xiii + 331. H/b 50.00. This is a very exciting book that makes some bold claims about the power of medieval logic.

More information

4 DETERMINERS AND PRONOUNS

4 DETERMINERS AND PRONOUNS 4 DETERMINERS AND PRONOUNS 1 Fill in the blanks with the indefinite article, the definite article, or Ø (zero article). Discuss any difference in meaning in case you find that two solutions are equally

More information

Sentence Processing. BCS 152 October

Sentence Processing. BCS 152 October Sentence Processing BCS 152 October 29 2018 Homework 3 Reminder!!! Due Wednesday, October 31 st at 11:59pm Conduct 2 experiments on word recognition on your friends! Read instructions carefully & submit

More information

Sentence Processing III. LIGN 170, Lecture 8

Sentence Processing III. LIGN 170, Lecture 8 Sentence Processing III LIGN 170, Lecture 8 Syntactic ambiguity Bob weighed three hundred and fifty pounds of grapes. The cotton shirts are made from comes from Arizona. The horse raced past the barn fell.

More information

Basic English. Robert Taggart

Basic English. Robert Taggart Basic English Robert Taggart Table of Contents To the Student.............................................. v Unit 1: Parts of Speech Lesson 1: Nouns............................................ 3 Lesson

More information

Meaning 1. Semantics is concerned with the literal meaning of sentences of a language.

Meaning 1. Semantics is concerned with the literal meaning of sentences of a language. Meaning 1 Semantics is concerned with the literal meaning of sentences of a language. Pragmatics is concerned with what people communicate using the sentences of the language, the speaker s meaning. 1

More information

Language and Mind Prof. Rajesh Kumar Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Language and Mind Prof. Rajesh Kumar Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Language and Mind Prof. Rajesh Kumar Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 07 Lecture - 32 Sentence CP in Subjects and Object Positions Let us look

More information

Vagueness & Pragmatics

Vagueness & Pragmatics Vagueness & Pragmatics Min Fang & Martin Köberl SEMNL April 27, 2012 Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 1 / 48 Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness Why are true sentences

More information

Where are we? Lecture 37: Modelling Conversations. Gap. Conversations

Where are we? Lecture 37: Modelling Conversations. Gap. Conversations Where are we? Lecture 37: Modelling Conversations CS 181O Spring 2016 Kim Bruce Some slides based on those of Christina Unger Can parse sentences, translate to FOL or interpret in a model. Can process

More information

The structure of this ppt

The structure of this ppt The structure of this ppt Structural, categorial and functional issues: 1.1. 1.11. English 2.1. 2.6. Hungarian 3.1. 3.9. Functional issues (in English) 2 1.1. Structural issues The VP lecture (1) S NP

More information

Speaker s Meaning, Speech Acts, Topic and Focus, Questions

Speaker s Meaning, Speech Acts, Topic and Focus, Questions Speaker s Meaning, Speech Acts, Topic and Focus, Questions Read: Portner: 24-25,190-198 LING 324 1 Sentence vs. Utterance Sentence: a unit of language that is syntactically well-formed and can stand alone

More information

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN Book reviews 123 The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN 9780199693672 John Hawthorne and David Manley wrote an excellent book on the

More information

VP Ellipsis. (corrected after class) Ivan A. Sag. April 23, b. Kim understands Korean and Lee should understand Korean, too.

VP Ellipsis. (corrected after class) Ivan A. Sag. April 23, b. Kim understands Korean and Lee should understand Korean, too. VP Ellipsis (corrected after class) Ivan A. Sag April 23, 2012 1 Syntactic Identity? (1) VP Deletion Transformation X VP Y VP Z SD: 1 2 3 4 5 SC: 1 2 3 5 Condition: 2=4 (2) a. Sandy went to the store,

More information

Reported (Indirect) Speech: Discovering the rules from Practical English Usage

Reported (Indirect) Speech: Discovering the rules from Practical English Usage Reported () Speech: Discovering the rules from Practical English Usage First, do Discovering the Rules. Then, read the explanations. You can find the explanations from Practical English Usage below this

More information

Developing Detailed Tree Diagrams

Developing Detailed Tree Diagrams Developing ailed Tree Diagrams Linguistics 222 March 4, 2013 1 More Tests for Constituency So far, we ve seen the following constituency tests: 1. Sentence fragment (Q+A) test 2. Echo-question test 3.

More information

I-language Chapter 8: Anaphor Binding

I-language Chapter 8: Anaphor Binding I-language Chapter 8: Anaphor Daniela Isac & Charles Reiss Concordia University, Montreal Outline 1 2 3 The beginning of science is the recognition that the simplest phenomena of ordinary life raise quite

More information

Table of Contents. Essay e-comments Page #s

Table of Contents. Essay e-comments Page #s Table of Contents Essay e-comments Page #s Essay Organization and Development: Introduction, Body, and Conclusion (e1 e49) Introduction Paragraphs 4-6 Body Paragraphs: Argument, Analysis, Evidence 6-9

More information

10 Common Grammatical Errors and How to Fix Them

10 Common Grammatical Errors and How to Fix Them 10 Common Grammatical Errors and How to Fix Them 1. Agreement Errors The subject and verb in a sentence must agree in number (singular vs. plural) and person (first, second, or third person). Pronouns

More information

6 th Grade ELA Post-Test Study Guide Semester One

6 th Grade ELA Post-Test Study Guide Semester One 6 th Grade ELA Post-Test Study Guide Semester One TYPES OF SENTENCES Simple sentences have one (subject, predicate, complete thought). Compound sentences contain independent clauses and use conjunctions.

More information

Handout 3 Verb Phrases: Types of modifier. Modifier Maximality Principle Non-head constituents are maximal projections, i.e., phrases (XPs).

Handout 3 Verb Phrases: Types of modifier. Modifier Maximality Principle Non-head constituents are maximal projections, i.e., phrases (XPs). Handout 3 Verb Phrases: Types of modifier Modifier Maximality Principle Non-head constituents are maximal projections, i.e., phrases (XPs). Compare buy and put: (1) a. John will buy the book on Tuesday.

More information

Contents. pg pg pg Countable, Uncountable Nouns. pg pg pg pg pg Practice Test 1. pg.

Contents. pg pg pg Countable, Uncountable Nouns. pg pg pg pg pg Practice Test 1. pg. Contents Chapter 1: Chapter 2: Chapter 3: Chapter 4: Chapter 5: Chapter 6: Chapter 7: Chapter 8: Chapter 9: Chapter 10: Chapter 11: Chapter 12: Chapter 13: Chapter 14: Chapter 15: Chapter 16: Chapter 17:

More information

Introduction to English Linguistics (I) Professor Seongha Rhee

Introduction to English Linguistics (I) Professor Seongha Rhee Introduction to English Linguistics (I) Professor Seongha Rhee srhee@hufs.ac.kr Ch. 3. Pragmatics (167-176) 1. Discourse Meaning - Pronouns 2. Deixis 3. More on Situational Context - Maxims of Conversation

More information

Errata Carnie, Andrew (2013) Syntax: A Generative Introduction. 3 rd edition. Wiley Blackwell. Last updated March 29, 2015

Errata Carnie, Andrew (2013) Syntax: A Generative Introduction. 3 rd edition. Wiley Blackwell. Last updated March 29, 2015 Errata Carnie, Andrew (2013) Syntax: A Generative Introduction. 3 rd edition. Wiley Blackwell. Last updated March 29, 2015 My thanks to: Dong-hwan An, Gabriel Amores, Ivano Caponigo, Dick Demers, Ling

More information

LESSON 30: REVIEW & QUIZ (DEPENDENT CLAUSES)

LESSON 30: REVIEW & QUIZ (DEPENDENT CLAUSES) LESSON 30: REVIEW & QUIZ (DEPENDENT CLAUSES) Teachers, you ll find quiz # 8 on pages 7-10 of this lesson. Give the quiz after going through the exercises. Review Clauses are groups of words with a subject

More information

U3: B: P20/21: E1 /3 U3: C: P22/23: E1/ 4 U3: P19: E2: V U1: P5: E1: V U3: A: 18/19: E1 /3 U3: C: P22/23: E1/ 4 U13: P97: E4/5: V U3: P19: E2: V

U3: B: P20/21: E1 /3 U3: C: P22/23: E1/ 4 U3: P19: E2: V U1: P5: E1: V U3: A: 18/19: E1 /3 U3: C: P22/23: E1/ 4 U13: P97: E4/5: V U3: P19: E2: V B1 A WORD LEVEL A1 NOUNS 1.1 Types of nouns 1.1.2 common nouns denoting uncountables Example from Threshold Student s Book U3: P26: E4: V P102: E18: V Workbook Grammar Vocabulary Reading and Writing U3:

More information

Negative Inversion Exclamatives

Negative Inversion Exclamatives taniguc7@msu.edu Semantics Workshop of the American Midwest and Prairies October 31st, 2015 Roadmap 1. The phenomenon 2. 2 empirical puzzles 3. 2 clues 4. Analysis proposal The phenomenon (1) Negative

More information

Language at work Present simple

Language at work Present simple Unit 1 Language at work Present simple Present simple Positive: Add -s or -es after the verb with he / she / it. I / you / we / they specialize in Latin American music. He / She / It specializes in high-tech

More information

Hello. I m Q-rex. Target Language. Phone Number :

Hello. I m Q-rex. Target Language. Phone Number : One Hello. I m Q-rex. Target Language In my free time I like playing soccer and listening to music. If I drink coffee, I get a headache. Phone Number : 032-234-5678 LISTENING AND READING 1. Watch your

More information

Independent and Subordinate Clauses

Independent and Subordinate Clauses Independent and Subordinate Clauses What They Are and How to Use Them By: Kalli Bradshaw Do you remember the difference between a subject and a predicate? Identify the subject and predicate in this sentence:

More information

Intro to Pragmatics (Fox/Menéndez-Benito) 10/12/06. Questions 1

Intro to Pragmatics (Fox/Menéndez-Benito) 10/12/06. Questions 1 Questions 1 0. Questions and pragmatics Why look at questions in a pragmatics class? where there are questions, there are, fortunately, also answers. And a satisfactory theory of interrogatives will have

More information

February 16, 2007 Menéndez-Benito. Challenges/ Problems for Carlson 1977

February 16, 2007 Menéndez-Benito. Challenges/ Problems for Carlson 1977 1. Wide scope effects Challenges/ Problems for Carlson 1977 (i) Sometimes BPs appear to give rise to wide scope effects with anaphora. 1) John saw apples, and Mary saw them too. (Krifka et al. 1995) This

More information

BBLAN24500 Angol mondattan szem. / English Syntax seminar BBK What are the Hungarian equivalents of the following linguistic terms?

BBLAN24500 Angol mondattan szem. / English Syntax seminar BBK What are the Hungarian equivalents of the following linguistic terms? BBLAN24500 Angol mondattan szem. / English Syntax seminar BBK 2017 Handout 1 (1) a. Fiúk szőke szaladgálnak b. Szőke szaladgálnak fiúk c. Szőke fiúk szaladgálnak d. Fiúk szaladgálnak szőke (2) a. Thelma

More information

Semantic Research Methodology

Semantic Research Methodology Semantic Research Methodology Based on Matthewson (2004) LING 510 November 5, 2013 Elizabeth Bogal- Allbritten Methods in semantics: preliminaries In semantic Fieldwork, the task is to Figure out the meanings

More information

Intensional Relative Clauses and the Semantics of Variable Objects

Intensional Relative Clauses and the Semantics of Variable Objects 1 To appear in M. Krifka / M. Schenner (eds.): Reconstruction Effects in Relative Clauses. Akademie Verlag, Berlin. Intensional Relative Clauses and the Semantics of Variable Objects Friederike Moltmann

More information

What s New in the 17th Edition

What s New in the 17th Edition What s in the 17th Edition The following is a partial list of the more significant changes, clarifications, updates, and additions to The Chicago Manual of Style for the 17th edition. Part I: The Publishing

More information

Introduction to tense shifting. LEVEL NUMBER LANGUAGE Advanced C1_2021G_EN English

Introduction to tense shifting. LEVEL NUMBER LANGUAGE Advanced C1_2021G_EN English Introduction to tense shifting GRAMMAR LEVEL NUMBER LANGUAGE Advanced C1_2021G_EN English Goals Learn about tense shifting, using reported speech as an example. Practise tense shifting in various situations.

More information

The structure of this ppt. Structural and categorial (and some functional) issues: English Hungarian

The structure of this ppt. Structural and categorial (and some functional) issues: English Hungarian The structure of this ppt Structural and categorial (and some functional) issues: 1.1. 1.12. English 2.1. 2.6. Hungarian 2 1.1. Structural issues The VP lecture (1) S NP John VP laughed. read the paper.

More information

Deriving the Interpretation of Rhetorical Questions

Deriving the Interpretation of Rhetorical Questions To appear in the proceedings of WCCFL 16 Deriving the Interpretation of Rhetorical Questions CHUNG-HYE HAN University of Pennsylvania 1 Introduction The purpose of this paper is (1) to show that RHETORICAL

More information

6 th Grade ELA Post-Test Study Guide Semester One

6 th Grade ELA Post-Test Study Guide Semester One 6 th Grade ELA Post-Test Study Guide Semester One TYPES OF SENTENCES Simple sentences have one independent clause (subject, predicate, complete thought). Compound sentences contain two independent clauses

More information

Skill-Builders. Grades 4 5. Grammar & Usage. Writer Sarah Guare. Editorial Director Susan A. Blair. Project Manager Erica L.

Skill-Builders. Grades 4 5. Grammar & Usage. Writer Sarah Guare. Editorial Director Susan A. Blair. Project Manager Erica L. Daily Skill-Builders Grammar & Usage Grades 4 5 Writer Sarah Guare Editorial Director Susan A. Blair Project Manager Erica L. Varney Cover Designer Roman Laszok Interior Designer Mark Sayer Production

More information

On Meaning. language to establish several definitions. We then examine the theories of meaning

On Meaning. language to establish several definitions. We then examine the theories of meaning Aaron Tuor Philosophy of Language March 17, 2014 On Meaning The general aim of this paper is to evaluate theories of linguistic meaning in terms of their success in accounting for definitions of meaning

More information

winter but it rained often during the summer

winter but it rained often during the summer 1.) Write out the sentence correctly. Add capitalization and punctuation: end marks, commas, semicolons, apostrophes, underlining, and quotation marks 2.)Identify each clause as independent or dependent.

More information

COMMON GRAMMAR ERRORS. By: Dr. Elham Alzoubi

COMMON GRAMMAR ERRORS. By: Dr. Elham Alzoubi COMMON GRAMMAR ERRORS THERE VS. THEIR VS. THEY'RE They re: This is a short form of they are. E.g. They re the children of our neighbors. There: It can be used as an expletive to start a sentence or can

More information

Linking semantic and pragmatic factors in the Japanese Internally Headed Relative Clause

Linking semantic and pragmatic factors in the Japanese Internally Headed Relative Clause Linking semantic and pragmatic factors in the Japanese Internally Headed Relative Clause Yusuke Kubota and E. Allyn Smith Department of Linguistics The Ohio State University http://www.ling.ohio-state.edu/~kubota/papers/rel07.pdf

More information

Research Seminar The syntax and semantics of questions Spring 1999 January 26, 1999 Week 1: Questions and typologies

Research Seminar The syntax and semantics of questions Spring 1999 January 26, 1999 Week 1: Questions and typologies 050.822 Research Seminar The syntax and semantics of questions Spring 1999 January 26, 1999 Paul Hagstrom Week 1: Questions and typologies Syntax and semantics question formation in English Position One:

More information

MIDTERM~STUDY GUIDE. A declarative sentence makes a statement. It ends with a period.

MIDTERM~STUDY GUIDE. A declarative sentence makes a statement. It ends with a period. MIDTERM~STUDY GUIDE GRAMMAR Types of sentences- A declarative sentence makes a statement. It ends with a period. Ex. Last summer I went on a long vacation. An interrogative sentence asks a question. It

More information

When data collide: Traditional judgments vs. formal experiments in sentence acceptability Grant Goodall UC San Diego

When data collide: Traditional judgments vs. formal experiments in sentence acceptability Grant Goodall UC San Diego When data collide: Traditional judgments vs. formal experiments in sentence acceptability Grant Goodall UC San Diego Two areas of concern in syntax 1. Traditional judgments + formal experiments What does

More information

Sentence Elements Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. Business English, 11e, by Mary Ellen Guffey and Carolyn Seefer 2-2

Sentence Elements Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. Business English, 11e, by Mary Ellen Guffey and Carolyn Seefer 2-2 Chapter 2 Sentences 2014 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part, except for use as permitted in a license distributed with a certain product

More information

Write It Right: Brenda Lyons, Ed.D. Say It Right

Write It Right: Brenda Lyons, Ed.D. Say It Right Write It Right: Brenda Lyons Ed.D Say It Right WRITE IT RIGHT: SAY IT RIGHT Many years ago when I served as the Associate Superintendent for Secondary Education in Edmond I became concerned about the many

More information

COMMONLY MISUSED AND PROBLEM WORDS AND EXPRESSIONS

COMMONLY MISUSED AND PROBLEM WORDS AND EXPRESSIONS COMMONLY MISUSED AND PROBLEM WORDS AND EXPRESSIONS After. Following After is the more precise word if a time sequence is involved: We went home after the meal. Allow Use allows one to instead of allows

More information

Imperatives are existential modals; Deriving the must-reading as an Implicature. Despina Oikonomou (MIT)

Imperatives are existential modals; Deriving the must-reading as an Implicature. Despina Oikonomou (MIT) Imperatives are existential modals; Deriving the must-reading as an Implicature Despina Oikonomou (MIT) The dual character of Imperatives with respect to their quantificational force has been a longlasting

More information

Review Jean Mark Gawron SDSU. March 14, Translation basics (you shouldnt get these things wrong):

Review Jean Mark Gawron SDSU. March 14, Translation basics (you shouldnt get these things wrong): Review 2014 Jean Mark Gawron SDSU March 14, 2016 1 Introduction Translation basics (you shouldnt get these things wrong): 1.1. Proper names translate as constants. NEVER as predicates. Right a. John walks.

More information

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Conversational Implicature: The Basics of the Gricean Theory 1

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Conversational Implicature: The Basics of the Gricean Theory 1 Conversational Implicature: The Basics of the Gricean Theory 1 In our first unit, we noted that so-called informational content (the information conveyed by an utterance) can be divided into (at least)

More information

S. 2 English Revision Exercises. Unit 1 Basic English Sentence Patterns

S. 2 English Revision Exercises. Unit 1 Basic English Sentence Patterns S. 2 English Revision Exercises Unit 1 Basic English Sentence Patterns A. When we make simple English sentences, we usually follow the Subject-Verb-Object patterns. Steps: 1. Put the subject and the adjectives

More information

Useful Definitions. a e i o u. Vowels. Verbs (doing words) run jump

Useful Definitions. a e i o u. Vowels. Verbs (doing words) run jump Contents Page Useful Definitions 2 Types of Sentences 3 Simple and Compound Sentences 4 Punctuation Marks 6 Full stop 7 Exclamation Mark 7 Question Mark 7 Comma 8 Speech Marks 9 Colons 11 Semi-colons 11

More information

n.pinnacle CAREER INSTITUTE C_171 SHAHPURA NEAR BANSAL HOSPITAL

n.pinnacle CAREER INSTITUTE C_171 SHAHPURA NEAR BANSAL HOSPITAL A. SUBJECT - VERB AGREEMENT 1. Two or more Singular Subjects connected by and usually take a Verb in the Plural. For example, Incorrect- Hari and Ram is here. Correct- Hari and Ram are here. 2. If two

More information

The Grass Roots for the ACT English Exam

The Grass Roots for the ACT English Exam The Grass Roots for the ACT English Exam Presented to Ms. Ausley s Junior English classes Created by Tara Seale & Julie Stephenson, Bryant (Ark.) Public Schools Overview Use logic and do NOT rush. ACT

More information

Week 3 10/12/11. Book p Booklet p.26. -Commands can be affirmative or negative. -the subject you is not stated.

Week 3 10/12/11. Book p Booklet p.26. -Commands can be affirmative or negative. -the subject you is not stated. Week 3 Book p. 118-149 Booklet p.26 - -Commands can be affirmative or negative. -the subject you is not stated. - AFFIRMATIVE COMMANDS: Shut the door now - NEGATIVE COMMANDS: Don t go outside Don t be

More information

slowly quickly softly suddenly gradually

slowly quickly softly suddenly gradually ADVERBS An Adverb is a word we use to modify a verb, an adjective or another adverb. Example; My father drove slowly. How did he drive? The adverb slowly is modifying the verb drive. My father drove a

More information

Key - Worksheet 3 Linguistics Eng B

Key - Worksheet 3 Linguistics Eng B Key - Worksheet 3 Linguistics Eng B yntax, semantics, and pragmatics 1. Draw tree diagrams and provide rewrite rules for the following: a. The boy devoured the sandwich. P V P The boys devoured the sandwich

More information

Rhetorical Questions and Scales

Rhetorical Questions and Scales Rhetorical Questions and Scales Just what do you think constructions are for? Russell Lee-Goldman Department of Linguistics University of California, Berkeley International Conference on Construction Grammar

More information

MECHANICS STANDARDS IN ENGINEERING WRITING

MECHANICS STANDARDS IN ENGINEERING WRITING MECHANICS STANDARDS IN ENGINEERING WRITING The following list reflects the most common grammar and punctuation errors I see in student writing. Avoid these problems when you write professionally. GRAMMAR

More information

1 Pair-list readings and single pair readings

1 Pair-list readings and single pair readings CAS LX 500 B1 Topics in Linguistics: Questions Spring 2009, April 21 13a. Questions with quantifiers Considering what everyone says about quantifiers in questions and different ways you can know who bought

More information

Direct and Indirect Speech

Direct and Indirect Speech Direct and Indirect Speech There are two main ways of reporting people s words, thoughts, beliefs etc. Direct speech We can give the exact words that were said. This kind of reporting is called direct

More information

STYLISTIC ANALYSIS OF MAYA ANGELOU S EQUALITY

STYLISTIC ANALYSIS OF MAYA ANGELOU S EQUALITY Lingua Cultura, 11(2), November 2017, 85-89 DOI: 10.21512/lc.v11i2.1602 P-ISSN: 1978-8118 E-ISSN: 2460-710X STYLISTIC ANALYSIS OF MAYA ANGELOU S EQUALITY Arina Isti anah English Letters Department, Faculty

More information

4-1. Gerunds and Infinitives

4-1. Gerunds and Infinitives 4-1. Gerunds and Infinitives 1. Which of these is a gerund? to play playing 2. Which of these is an infinitive? to play playing 3. How do you make a gerund? 4. How do you make an infinitive? a. Sports

More information

LNGT 0250 Morphology and Syntax

LNGT 0250 Morphology and Syntax LNGT 0250 Morphology and Syntax Announcements Assignment #6 is posted and is due Fri April 24 at 2pm. Next week s presentations order. 3 on Monday. 4 on Wed. Lecture #19 April 20 th, 2015 2 Argument structure

More information

*High Frequency Words also found in Texas Treasures Updated 8/19/11

*High Frequency Words also found in Texas Treasures Updated 8/19/11 Child s name (first & last) after* about along a lot accept a* all* above* also across against am also* across* always afraid American and* an add another afternoon although as are* after* anything almost

More information

Construal. Subjectivity/objectivity. To what extent are S or H regarded as objects of conception?

Construal. Subjectivity/objectivity. To what extent are S or H regarded as objects of conception? Subjectivity/objectivity Construal To what extent are S or H regarded as objects of conception? Objectively construed Subjectively construed I went to the dentist Can you help me? Let s go come

More information

Fry Instant Phrases. First 100 Words/Phrases

Fry Instant Phrases. First 100 Words/Phrases Fry Instant Phrases The words in these phrases come from Dr. Edward Fry s Instant Word List (High Frequency Words). According to Fry, the first 300 words in the list represent about 67% of all the words

More information

Adjectives - Semantic Characteristics

Adjectives - Semantic Characteristics Adjectives - Semantic Characteristics Prototypical ADJs (inherent, concrete, relatively stable qualities) 1. Size General size: Horizontal extension: Thickness: Vertical extension: Vertical elevation:

More information

Pragmatics - The Contribution of Context to Meaning

Pragmatics - The Contribution of Context to Meaning Ling 107 Pragmatics - The Contribution of Context to Meaning We do not interpret language in a vacuum. We use our knowledge of the actors, objects and situation to determine more specific interpretations

More information

Using Commas. c. Common introductory words that should be followed by a comma include yes, however, well.

Using Commas. c. Common introductory words that should be followed by a comma include yes, however, well. Using Commas The comma is a valuable, useful punctuation device because it separates the structural elements of sentences into manageable segments. The rules provided here are those found in traditional

More information

Lauderdale County School District Pacing Guide Sixth Grade Language Arts / Reading First Nine Weeks

Lauderdale County School District Pacing Guide Sixth Grade Language Arts / Reading First Nine Weeks First Nine Weeks c. Stories and retellings d. Letters d. 4 Presentations 4a. Nouns: singular, plural, common/proper, singular possessive compound (one word: bookcase), hyphenated words 4a. Verbs: action

More information

GUIA DE ESTUDIO PARA EL ETS DE SEGUNDO SEMESTRE.

GUIA DE ESTUDIO PARA EL ETS DE SEGUNDO SEMESTRE. GUIA DE ESTUDIO PARA EL ETS DE SEGUNDO SEMESTRE. UNIDAD 7. 1 Underline the correct word or phrase. Example: We was / were at school yesterday. 1 Was / Were Jack and Elaine on holiday last week? 2 The shops

More information

On the Road to our 1 st Project! The English language started with letters. Letters formed words, and those words are broken into 8 parts of speech.

On the Road to our 1 st Project! The English language started with letters. Letters formed words, and those words are broken into 8 parts of speech. On the Road to our 1 st Project! The English language started with letters. Letters formed words, and those words are broken into 8 parts of speech. There are 8 parts of speech. Noun Pronoun Adjective

More information

Knowledge Representation

Knowledge Representation 7 Knowledge Representation 7.0 Issues in Knowledge Representation 7.1 A Brief History of AI Representational Systems 7.2 Conceptual Graphs: A Network Language 7.3 Alternatives to Explicit Representation

More information

I ll never forget the day when Prince William and Kate Middleton married. Target Language

I ll never forget the day when Prince William and Kate Middleton married. Target Language Twenty-one I ll never forget the day when Prince William and Kate Middleton married. Target Language Do you remember the day when we first met? Ann s mother isn t home yet, which worries her. Show me what

More information

CRCT Study Guide 6 th Grade Language Arts PARTS OF SPEECH. 1. Noun a word that names a PERSON, PLACE, THING, or IDEA

CRCT Study Guide 6 th Grade Language Arts PARTS OF SPEECH. 1. Noun a word that names a PERSON, PLACE, THING, or IDEA CRCT Study Guide 6 th Grade Language Arts PARTS OF SPEECH 1. Noun a word that names a PERSON, PLACE, THING, or IDEA Singular Noun refers to ONE person, ONE place, ONE thing, or ONE Idea. (teacher, store,

More information

Contents. Section 1 VERBS...57

Contents. Section 1 VERBS...57 Section 1 Contents Introduction...5 How to Use This Book...6 Assessment Records...7 Games & Activities Matrix..15 Standards...16 NOUNS...17 Teaching Notes...18 Student Page 1 (Nouns)...20 Student Page

More information

Spanish Language Programme

Spanish Language Programme LEVEL C1.1 SUPERIOR First quarter Grammar contents 1. The substantive and the article 1.1. Review of the substantive and the article 1.2. Foreign and erudite expressions 2. The adjective I 2.1. Types of

More information

Song Lessons Understanding and Using English Grammar, 3rd Edition. A lesson about adjective, adverb, and noun clauses (Chapters 12, 13, 17)

Song Lessons Understanding and Using English Grammar, 3rd Edition. A lesson about adjective, adverb, and noun clauses (Chapters 12, 13, 17) A lesson about adjective, adverb, and noun clauses (Chapters 12, 13, 17) Notes for the Teacher 1. The Song Do a search on the Internet to find the song Father and Daughter by Paul Simon. When you search,

More information

Beware of Dog: Verbs, cont.

Beware of Dog: Verbs, cont. Left side of verb = subject Now we ll look at right side of verb Beware of Dog: Verbs, cont. The dog was (on the patio). Superverb/main verb (intransitive) The dog was eating on the patio. Superverb/HV

More information

Skill-Builders. Grades 5-6. Grammar & Usage. Writer Sarah Guare. Editorial Director Susan A. Blair. Project Manager Erica L.

Skill-Builders. Grades 5-6. Grammar & Usage. Writer Sarah Guare. Editorial Director Susan A. Blair. Project Manager Erica L. Daily Skill-Builders Grammar & Usage Grades 5-6 Writer Sarah Guare Editorial Director Susan A. Blair Project Manager Erica L. Varney Cover Designer Roman Laszok Interior Designer Mark Sayer Production

More information

Syntax 3. S-selection. S-selection. C-selection. S-selection (semantic selection) C-selection (categorial selection)

Syntax 3. S-selection. S-selection. C-selection. S-selection (semantic selection) C-selection (categorial selection) S-selection (semantic selection) Syntax 3 c-selection, s-selection, Text pg. 226-233 -bar ory not text Sandy kissed Kim Sandy skidded *Sandy kissed *Sandy skidded Kim!The oppion kissed Kim!The oppion skidded

More information

Unidad III: Lengua Adicional al Español (Inglés) IV. Tema 2: Relatives Clauses. Describing objects, places, people and activities. U n i d a d I I I :

Unidad III: Lengua Adicional al Español (Inglés) IV. Tema 2: Relatives Clauses. Describing objects, places, people and activities. U n i d a d I I I : U n i d a d I I I : Unidad III: Describing objects, places, people and activities. Lengua Adicional al Español (Inglés) IV Tema 2: Relatives Clauses Relatives Clauses Limericks are humour poems. They begin

More information